Article contents
The Political Philosophy of Karl Popper
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 27 January 2009
Extract
In 1968 there appeared in New Left Review an essay by its editor, Perry Anderson, which attracted considerable attention. Detecting in the student unrest then at its height ‘stirrings of a revolutionary consciousness’, Anderson was concerned to identify (and of course attack) the main elements ofthat British cultural conservatism which, in his view, the burgeoning revolutionary consciousness must overthrow. In brief, his view was that British intellectual life was dominated by a ‘“White”, counter-revolutionary emigration’ from Eastern and Central Europe – men who had fled the instability of their own societies for the continuity and order of the British tradition. Among them Anderson listed, as the dominant influence in social theory, Karl Popper. This was an accolade of sorts, but by no means any kind of intellectual tribute, for Anderson went on to dismiss Popper as nothing more than a ‘fluent ideologue’, incompetent alike in sociology and political theory.
- Type
- Review Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1980
References
1 Anderson, Perry, ‘Components of the National Culture’, New Left Review, L (1968), 3–57, pp. 17–19 and p. 27. See also p. 1.Google Scholar
2 Magee, B., Popper (London: Collins, 1973), p. 83.Google Scholar
3 Objective Knowledge, p. 154.Google Scholar
4 Unended Quest, pp. 168–9.Google Scholar
5 Objective Knowledge, pp. 145–6.Google Scholar
6 Unended Quest, pp. 48–9.Google Scholar
7 See especially The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 1, Chap, 10.Google Scholar Popper's term ‘open society’ has recently been appropriated by advocates of economic laissez-faire – vide the recent Institute of Economic Affairs publication The Coming Confrontation – Will the Open Society Survive to 1989? (London: Institute of Economic Affairs, 1978), edited by Harris, R. and Seldon, A.Google Scholar. In this book Popper's name is not in fact mentioned, and its political stance, generally hostile to all social engineering, is far different from his.
8 Conjectures and Refutations, pp. 126–8.Google Scholar
9 Objective Knowledge, p. 248.Google Scholar
10 Mill, J. S., On Liberty, Chap. II.Google Scholar
11 Unended Quest, p. 168.Google Scholar
12 Objective Knowledge, pp. 242–4, 296–8Google Scholar; The Poverty of Historicism, p. 147.Google Scholar
13 Objective Knowledge, p. 237.Google Scholar
14 The Open Society and Its Enemies, Vol. 1, p. 188.Google Scholar
15 The Poverty of Historicism, pp. 113, 116–7, 122–8.Google Scholar
16 The Poverty of Historicism, p. 139.Google Scholar
17 The Poverty of Historicism, p. 115.Google Scholar
18 The Logic of Scientific Discovery, pp. 27–30.Google Scholar
19 Examples are Anderson in ‘Components of the National Culture’, and Cornforth, M., The Open Philosophy and the Open Society (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1968).Google Scholar
20 The Poverty of Historicism, p. 128Google Scholar; The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 2, p. 87.Google Scholar
21 Mill, J. S., Utilitarianism, On Liberty and Considerations on Representative Government (London: Dent, 1972), pp. 190–1.Google Scholar
22 Fletcher, R., ed., John Stuart Mill (London: Nelson, 1973), p. 186.Google Scholar
23 The Poverty of Historicism, p. 153.Google Scholar
24 As suggested by Oakeshott, M., Rationalism in Politics (London: Methuen, 1962).Google Scholar
25 I have discussed some of Popper's arguments against psychologism in my The Structure of Social Science (London: Allen and Unwin, 1974), pp. 106–8.Google Scholar
26 The Poverty of Historicism, pp. 158–9.Google Scholar
27 Objective Knowledge, pp. 21–2.Google Scholar
28 A form of ‘mitigated inductivism’ is adumbrated in my The Structure of Social Science, p. 17.Google Scholar
29 See Adorno, T. W. et al. , The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology (London: Heinemann, 1976).Google Scholar Cf. also my ‘Technique, Critique and Social Science’, in Brown, S., ed., Philosophical Disputes in the Social Sciences (London: Harvester Press, forthcoming)Google Scholar, for a critical account of ‘critical theory’.
30 Cited in The Poverty of Historicism, p. 67.Google Scholar
31 The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 1, p. 176.Google Scholar
32 The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 2, p. 161.Google Scholar
33 The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 1, p. 124.Google Scholar
34 The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 2, pp. 124–5.Google Scholar
35 Hobbes, T., Leviathan, Chap. XIII, last paragraph.Google Scholar
36 The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 2, p. 234.Google Scholar
37 Hume, D., A Treatise of Human Nature, Book Three, Part II.Google Scholar
- 3
- Cited by