Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T22:55:50.487Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Political Philosophy of Karl Popper

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 January 2009

Extract

In 1968 there appeared in New Left Review an essay by its editor, Perry Anderson, which attracted considerable attention. Detecting in the student unrest then at its height ‘stirrings of a revolutionary consciousness’, Anderson was concerned to identify (and of course attack) the main elements ofthat British cultural conservatism which, in his view, the burgeoning revolutionary consciousness must overthrow. In brief, his view was that British intellectual life was dominated by a ‘“White”, counter-revolutionary emigration’ from Eastern and Central Europe – men who had fled the instability of their own societies for the continuity and order of the British tradition. Among them Anderson listed, as the dominant influence in social theory, Karl Popper. This was an accolade of sorts, but by no means any kind of intellectual tribute, for Anderson went on to dismiss Popper as nothing more than a ‘fluent ideologue’, incompetent alike in sociology and political theory.

Type
Review Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1980

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Anderson, Perry, ‘Components of the National Culture’, New Left Review, L (1968), 357, pp. 1719 and p. 27. See also p. 1.Google Scholar

2 Magee, B., Popper (London: Collins, 1973), p. 83.Google Scholar

3 Objective Knowledge, p. 154.Google Scholar

4 Unended Quest, pp. 168–9.Google Scholar

5 Objective Knowledge, pp. 145–6.Google Scholar

6 Unended Quest, pp. 48–9.Google Scholar

7 See especially The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 1, Chap, 10.Google Scholar Popper's term ‘open society’ has recently been appropriated by advocates of economic laissez-faire – vide the recent Institute of Economic Affairs publication The Coming Confrontation – Will the Open Society Survive to 1989? (London: Institute of Economic Affairs, 1978), edited by Harris, R. and Seldon, A.Google Scholar. In this book Popper's name is not in fact mentioned, and its political stance, generally hostile to all social engineering, is far different from his.

8 Conjectures and Refutations, pp. 126–8.Google Scholar

9 Objective Knowledge, p. 248.Google Scholar

10 Mill, J. S., On Liberty, Chap. II.Google Scholar

11 Unended Quest, p. 168.Google Scholar

12 Objective Knowledge, pp. 242–4, 296–8Google Scholar; The Poverty of Historicism, p. 147.Google Scholar

13 Objective Knowledge, p. 237.Google Scholar

14 The Open Society and Its Enemies, Vol. 1, p. 188.Google Scholar

15 The Poverty of Historicism, pp. 113, 116–7, 122–8.Google Scholar

16 The Poverty of Historicism, p. 139.Google Scholar

17 The Poverty of Historicism, p. 115.Google Scholar

18 The Logic of Scientific Discovery, pp. 2730.Google Scholar

19 Examples are Anderson in ‘Components of the National Culture’, and Cornforth, M., The Open Philosophy and the Open Society (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1968).Google Scholar

20 The Poverty of Historicism, p. 128Google Scholar; The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 2, p. 87.Google Scholar

21 Mill, J. S., Utilitarianism, On Liberty and Considerations on Representative Government (London: Dent, 1972), pp. 190–1.Google Scholar

22 Fletcher, R., ed., John Stuart Mill (London: Nelson, 1973), p. 186.Google Scholar

23 The Poverty of Historicism, p. 153.Google Scholar

24 As suggested by Oakeshott, M., Rationalism in Politics (London: Methuen, 1962).Google Scholar

25 I have discussed some of Popper's arguments against psychologism in my The Structure of Social Science (London: Allen and Unwin, 1974), pp. 106–8.Google Scholar

26 The Poverty of Historicism, pp. 158–9.Google Scholar

27 Objective Knowledge, pp. 21–2.Google Scholar

28 A form of ‘mitigated inductivism’ is adumbrated in my The Structure of Social Science, p. 17.Google Scholar

29 See Adorno, T. W. et al. , The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology (London: Heinemann, 1976).Google Scholar Cf. also my ‘Technique, Critique and Social Science’, in Brown, S., ed., Philosophical Disputes in the Social Sciences (London: Harvester Press, forthcoming)Google Scholar, for a critical account of ‘critical theory’.

30 Cited in The Poverty of Historicism, p. 67.Google Scholar

31 The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 1, p. 176.Google Scholar

32 The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 2, p. 161.Google Scholar

33 The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 1, p. 124.Google Scholar

34 The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 2, pp. 124–5.Google Scholar

35 Hobbes, T., Leviathan, Chap. XIII, last paragraph.Google Scholar

36 The Open Society and its Enemies, Vol. 2, p. 234.Google Scholar

37 Hume, D., A Treatise of Human Nature, Book Three, Part II.Google Scholar