Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T01:53:01.186Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2010 Winter Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 January 2014

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Meeting Report
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] Cook, R., Intuitionism reconsidered, The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mathematics and logic, (Shapiro, S., editor), Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2005, pp. 387411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2] Field, H., Pluralism in Logic, The Review of Symbolic Logic, vol. 2 (2009), no. 2, pp. 242259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[1] Conway, J. H., On numbers and games, Academic Press, 1976.Google Scholar
[2] Ehrlich, P., Universally extending arithmetic continua, Le Labyrinthe du Continu, Colloque de Cerisy, (Sinaceur, H. and Salanskis, J. M., editors), Springer-Verlag France, Paris, 1992, pp. 168178.Google Scholar
[3] Ehrlich, P., Continuity, Encyclopedia of philosophy, second edition, (Borchart, D. M., editor in chief), Macmillan Reference, USA, 2005, vol 2, pp. 489518.Google Scholar
[4] Ehrlich, P., The absolute arithmetic continuum, Synthese, (forthcoming).Google Scholar
[5] Ehrlich, P., The absolute arithmetic continuum and its Peircean counterpart, New essays on Peirce's mathematical philosophy, (Moore, M., editor), Open Court Press (forthcoming).Google Scholar
[1] Halpern, J. and Pearl, J., Causes and explanations: A structural-model approach. Part I: Causes, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, vol. 56 (2005), pp. 843887.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2] Hitchcock, C., Prevention, preemption, and the principle of sufficient reason, Philosophical Review, vol. 116 (2007), pp. 495532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3] Hitchcock, C. and Knobe, J., Cause and Norm, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 11 (2009), pp. 587612.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[1] Maksimova, L. L., Pretabular superintuitionist logic, Algebra i Logika, vol. 11 (1972), no. 5, pp. 558570.Google Scholar
[2] Maksimova, L. L., Pretabular extensions of Lewis S4, Algebra i Logika, vol. 14 (1975), no. 1, pp. 2855.Google Scholar
[3] Meyer, Robert K., Sentential constants in R and R¬ , Studia Logica, vol. 45 (1986), no. 3, pp. 301327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[4] Slaney, John K. 3088 varieties: a solution to the Ackermann constant problem, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 50 (1985), no. 2, pp. 487501.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[1] Sagüillo, J., Domains of sciences, universe of discourse, and omega arguments, History and Philosophy of Logic, vol. 20 (1999), pp. 267280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2] Tarski, A., Logic, semantics, metamathematics, Hackett, Indianapolis, 1983, pp. 409420.Google Scholar