Suppose that a fully conscious patient with a terminal illness, such as end-stage metastatic lung cancer, voluntarily requests to be killed by their doctor as a means to relieve their suffering. After other options are explored and discussed, and after it is ensured that the patient has provided informed consent, the doctor obliges and injects a lethal combination of drugs, with the full intention of those drugs killing the patient, as a means to respect their autonomy and relieve their suffering. This constitutes the paradigm case of “euthanasia” as I will use the term in this essay. Suppose that instead, the patient asks the doctor to supply a lethal combination of oral drugs that they can take at home. Again, the doctor obliges, with the full intention of those drugs killing the patient, as a means to respect their autonomy and relieve their suffering; this constitutes the paradigm case of “assisted suicide.”Footnote 1
Now suppose, as a premise of this essay, that these paradigm cases of euthanasia and assisted suicide are not inherently unethical.Footnote 2 Nonetheless, it is often argued by health professionals working within the field of palliative care that palliative care and euthanasia/assisted suicide are incompatible.Footnote 3 Across the literature, this claim is grounded on the three claims that (1) palliative care and euthanasia/assisted suicide have different aims, (2) euthanasia/assisted suicide is at odds with the doctor’s fundamental role as a healer, and (3) euthanasia/assisted suicide constitutes patient abandonment. Furthermore, even if palliative care and euthanasia/assisted suicide are compatible, it is often argued that the availability of palliative care renders euthanasia/assisted suicide redundant. This depends on two claims that (1) palliative care is always available and effective, and (2) palliative care is always preferable to euthanasia/assisted suicide. In this essay, I will argue that all of these claims are false. I will then explore some of the motivations surrounding views on the relationship between palliative care and euthanasia/assisted suicide, with the ultimate aim of establishing that palliative care and euthanasia/assisted suicide are complementary rather than mutually exclusive.Footnote 4
Palliative Care and Euthanasia Are Compatible
Palliative Care and Euthanasia Share the Same Aims of Promoting Autonomy and Relieving Suffering
One of the key aims of palliative care is promoting autonomy.Footnote 5 Autonomy is just as important in palliative care as in any other medical specialty. However, euthanasia promotes autonomy as well, so the question beckons: “Why is promoting autonomy at the end of life of the utmost ethical importance, just not when it comes to euthanasia?” The standard response goes along the lines of: “because euthanasia does not actually promote autonomy—at least not in the same way as palliative care—because autonomy cannot reach so far as to include its own immediate destruction.”Footnote 6 This claim is false. To show this, consider the example of Richie Fernando SJ, a missionary working in Cambodia who dived on a grenade, sacrificing himself to save a classroom full of disabled children.Footnote 7 His decision to dive on the grenade was autonomous; thinking otherwise is absurd. Richie’s autonomous decision did include its own immediate destruction. Furthermore, according to any ethical theory that has autonomous action as a necessary criterion for ethical responsibility, if Richie’s action really was not autonomous, then he was not ethically responsible for his action and hence cannot be praised for it. This is equally absurd. Another problem with the claim that autonomy cannot extend to its own immediate destruction is vagueness as to what counts as “immediate.” Richie’s decision clearly meets this immediacy criterion, whereas a decision to sunbake and get badly sunburnt, leading to death from a melanoma in 40 years’ time, clearly does not. But what if Richie had given away almost all of his food to the children, resulting in him dying from starvation a few months later? This seems to fall into a gray area. The ethical significance of the immediacy criterion is also questionable in and of itself.
Even if the argument that autonomy cannot extend to its own immediate destruction were true, it applies equally to the “passive” end-of-life decisions essential to palliative care. Voluntary decisions to withhold or withdraw inappropriate or futile life-sustaining treatments, such as withholding cardiopulmonary resuscitation in the instance of cardiac arrest, or turning off a mechanical ventilator in a patient still dependent upon it, extinguish future autonomy in the same way as euthanasia or diving on a grenade. Lars Materstvedt and George Bosshard admit this, asking in relation to these “passive” palliative practices: “Has not the patient then contributed to extinguishing his autonomy? Put differently: Is there a moral duty to stay alive as long as possible in order that one be able to exercise one’s autonomy until the end?”Footnote 8 I think that this serves as an argumentum ad absurdum against the “autonomy cannot extend to its own immediate destruction” argument.
All of the aforementioned sources agree that the other key aim of palliative care is relieving suffering. “Suffering” includes physical symptoms (e.g., pain, shortness of breath, nausea, and vomiting), which may be alleviated through opioids or other drugs. It also includes emotional, psychological, spiritual, and existential suffering, for example, feeling confused, angry, or scared; feeling worthless or hopeless; or feeling like a burden on others. Avoiding these different types of suffering is largely achieved through avoiding the inappropriate and unnecessary prolongation of dying, that is, by withholding or withdrawing inappropriate or futile life-sustaining treatments.Footnote 9 However, euthanasia relieves suffering as well, so the question beckons: “Why is relieving suffering at the end of life of the utmost ethical importance, just not when it comes to euthanasia?” The standard response goes along the lines of: “because euthanasia does not actually relieve suffering—at least not in the same way as palliative care—rather, euthanasia ends suffering.”Footnote 10 This is also false. Distinguishing between “relieving” and “ending” suffering is both ontologically and ethically tenuous. Palliative care and euthanasia both ultimately aim at achieving an absence of suffering; the terms “relieving” and “ending” just pick out different means to that shared end. Euthanasia achieves an absence of suffering indirectly by virtue of removing the potential for that suffering (via death; the suffering is “ended”). Conversely, “relieving” suffering combats the suffering directly. This difference does not seem ethically significant to me. Although even if it is, palliative care often “ends” suffering just as much as euthanasia does. Withholding cardiopulmonary resuscitation, or turning off a mechanical ventilator, despite arguably being “passive” processes, still have the end result of death coming about sooner, thereby removing the potential for continued suffering by “ending” it.
Furthermore, consider the less common but nonetheless important “active” palliative care practice of “continuous deep palliative sedation,” whereby dying patients are sedated to the level of unconsciousness and then allowed to die via withholding or withdrawing inappropriate or futile life-sustaining treatments. Even if continuous deep palliative sedation does not hasten or bring about death itself, it too removes the potential for suffering and thereby “ends” rather than “relieves” suffering by virtue of its permanently sedating patients to unconsciousness so that they can no longer suffer. On the previous point, it also prevents that patient from ever exercising their autonomy again. Owing to this, Materstvedt and Bosshard admit that continuous deep palliative sedation “has an unclear border with euthanasia.”Footnote 11
Euthanasia Is Not at Odds with the Doctor’s Fundamental Role in the Palliative Setting
It is often argued that euthanasia is “fundamentally incompatible with the physician’s role as a healer.”Footnote 12 The British Medical Association similarly claims that euthanasia is “contrary to the ethics of clinical practice, as the principal purpose of medicine is to improve patients’ quality of life, not to foreshorten [them].”Footnote 13 This argument is deeply misguided. Whilst healing is usually one of the fundamental roles of a doctor, it is not one of their fundamental roles in the palliative setting. This reflects the central tenet of palliative care: it palliates rather than striving for a cure or “heal.” Michael Rabow and Steven Pantilat explain that until recently it was—and sometimes still is—incorrectly assumed that death “is a failure of medical science [… and] an enemy to be battled furiously in hospitals rather than an inevitable outcome to be experienced as a part of life.”Footnote 14 Karen Steinhauser et al. provide a similar explanation.Footnote 15 Palliative care originated as a response to these misconceptions, which was necessary because of observations such as those found in one study in which 38 percent of patients dying in a hospital spent at least 10 days in the Intensive Care Unit before death, 50 percent of family members reported moderate or severe pain in the patient at least half of the time, and median hospital charges for families were between USD $21,000 and $29,000.Footnote 16 Owing to the palliative care movement, the modern management of dying patients has become much more appropriate. Palliative care correctly recognizes that “death is not necessarily a defeat.”Footnote 17 The doctor’s role beyond that of a healer is recognized by medical bodies globally; for example, the British Medical Association emphasizes that it “does not believe that it is appropriate to prolong life at all costs, with no regard to its quality or the burdens of the intervention.”Footnote 18 For these reasons, euthanasia is not at odds with the doctor’s fundamental role in the palliative setting.
Euthanasia Does Not Necessarily Constitute Patient Abandonment
Patient nonabandonment is of the utmost ethical importance.Footnote 19 This is also recognized by Heather Cereste and Joseph Fins, who claim that nonabandonment is the doctor’s “primary responsibility.”Footnote 20 Similarly, James Marcum claims that “passionate physicians do not abandon their patients; […] the physician pledges to see the patient through to the end,”Footnote 21 and Rabow and Pantilat claim that “the promise of nonabandonment is perhaps the central principle of end-of-life care and is the [doctor’s] pledge to an individual patient as a caring partner.”Footnote 22 These sources strongly imply that euthanasia constitutes patient abandonment; the suggestion is that euthanasia does not accompany the patient right up until the end, and instead “only goes halfway” by taking the easy way out and bringing about death prematurely. This is incorrect. Palliative care and euthanasia are alternative options at the end of life. I agree that if a patient requests palliative care but is instead offered euthanasia then that patient has been abandoned. By the same token, if a patient requests euthanasia (as an informed decision) but is instead offered palliative care then that patient has also been abandoned. When a patient has sufficient decision-making capacity, respecting that patient’s autonomous decision is what constitutes companionship, whether that decision is for palliative care or euthanasia.
Palliative Care Does Not Render Euthanasia Redundant
Now suppose that euthanasia is not inherently incompatible with palliative care. Nonetheless, it is often argued that palliative care renders euthanasia redundant.Footnote 23 This redundancy claim in turn depends on two claims: (1) the factual claim that palliative care is always available and effective, and (2) the stronger ethical claim that palliative care is always preferable to euthanasia. Both of these claims are false.
The Factual Claim that Palliative Care Is Always Available and Effective
The “always” qualifier should make the falsity of this claim obvious. Let us turn to Australia as an example. The Australian and New Zealand Society of Palliative Medicine admits that there are “significant deficits in the [current] provision of palliative care”Footnote 24 and that the “Specialist Palliative Care workforce is currently too small to be able to care for all [patients dying expected deaths in Australia and New Zealand] and their families, loved ones and carers, even though this would be highly desirable.”Footnote 25 It also identifies various “evidence-to-practice gaps,” which impede the provision of palliative care, including the coordination and integration of care (e.g., opioid access through community pharmacies) and management of the terminal phase (the last 7–10 days of life).Footnote 26 It also identifies a number of vulnerable populations, including “patients with [noncancerous] life-limiting illnesses, those who live in rural and remote areas, residents of Residential Aged Care Facilities, the indigenous populations, and those from culturally and linguistically diverse backgrounds.”Footnote 27 Many interlocutors agree that palliative care should always be available and have formulated plans to achieve this goal.Footnote 28 For instance, the Australian and New Zealand Society of Palliative Medicine boldly claims that palliative care is “achievable for all patients” and that “all primary care and specialist providers, patients and families should have access to specialist palliative care in all settings.”Footnote 29 I agree that this would be ideal, although I suspect that it is naïve. No doubt the availability of palliative care can be substantially improved. But it is important not to conflate this should claim with the current state of affairs. Even if palliative care will be available to everyone at some point in the future, this is not currently the case.
Irrespective of its availability, it is widely (and regrettably) recognized that palliative care is not always completely effective.Footnote 30 For example, the Australian Medical Association admits that “there are some instances where it is difficult to achieve satisfactory relief of suffering,”Footnote 31 and the Australian and New Zealand Society of Palliative Medicine admits that “despite the best that palliative care can offer to support patients in their suffering, appropriate specialist palliative care to remedy physical, psychological and spiritual difficulties may not relieve all suffering at all times.”Footnote 32 Furthermore, I have stressed that suffering extends beyond physical symptoms. It is more feasible to relieve someone’s pain than it is to relieve, for example, their loss of independence and their indignity owing to dual incontinence. Palliative care can and does incorporate psychological, emotional, spiritual, and existential aspects of care; however, it is simply false that palliative care is always able to relieve these kinds of suffering.
The Ethical Claim that Palliative Care Is Always Preferable to Euthanasia
Suppose for the sake of argument that palliative care is always available and effective. It still would not render euthanasia redundant because the ethical claim is false; palliative care is not always preferable to euthanasia. As before, the “always” qualifier should make the falsity of this claim obvious.
The most immediate reason for preferring euthanasia to palliative care is if the patient requests euthanasia rather than palliative care. But opponents correctly argue that a request for euthanasia may not necessarily be voluntary. Ensuring voluntariness is difficult, perhaps even impossible.Footnote 33 “Voluntary” means “supported with informed consent,” which in turn most interlocutors agree has three necessary and sufficient criteria: sufficient provision of information, sufficient decision-making capacity (which is decision-specific and may vary with time), and freedom from coercion.Footnote 34 Although the first criterion should always be ensured, decision-making capacity can be undermined by dementia, clinical depression, or judgment clouded by pain; and subtle coercion may be introduced if the patient feels like an emotional or financial burden on their family, or like a financial burden on their state.Footnote 35 Clinical tests for measuring decision-making capacity do exist, however, their reliability is questionable.Footnote 36
Ensuring voluntariness in requests for euthanasia through advance care directives (ACDs) has its own host of problems; for example, unambiguous wording is difficult to achieve and it is difficult to know what one would really want ahead of time.Footnote 37 ACDs are especially problematic in the context of dementia: depending on one’s theory of personal identity, if the current patient with dementia is not the same person as the last person at the time when the ACD was written, then the ACD should have no bearing on the current patient. Conversely, if the patient is still the same person as the past person, there may nonetheless be a conflict of interests, in which case it is contentious as to whose interests should be prioritized.Footnote 38 There are also problems in ensuring voluntariness owing to the relinquishing of control in the final moments of the euthanasia procedure itself: if the patient gets cold feet it might be too late for them to reverse their decision.Footnote 39
I do not have solutions to the problems of ensuring that a direct request for euthanasia is voluntary or ensuring that a request for euthanasia via an ACD is voluntary. What I do want to point out, however, is that it has been overlooked that these problems apply equally to “passive” palliative practices: a request for withholding or withdrawing inappropriate or futile life-sustaining treatments might also have its voluntariness undermined by any of these problems. Therefore, these problems cannot be reasons for preferring palliative care to euthanasia.
Interlocutors claiming that palliative care makes euthanasia redundant often point toward the evidence that, when offered palliative care, many patients withdraw their request for euthanasia.Footnote 40 There is also evidence that in the United Kingdom, where palliative care is more widely available than in most other places, requests for euthanasia are less frequent than elsewhere.Footnote 41 This shows that some patients prefer palliative care to euthanasia—of course, they do!—but it does not show that this is the case for all patients. Furthermore, we have only been presented one side of the story: no doubt many patients being offered palliative care would opt for euthanasia if it were made available to them. Ideally, patients would have access to both palliative care and euthanasia, allowing them to make an informed choice for one or the other. Robert George, Ilora Finlay, and David JeffreyFootnote 42 are correct in arguing that choosing euthanasia when palliative care is not available as an alternative option for consideration is unideal, although the converse is also true: choosing palliative care when euthanasia is not available as an alternative option for consideration is also unideal. So even if palliative care was universally available, it still would not render euthanasia redundant.
There are often good reasons for preferring euthanasia to palliative care. The most common reasons for requesting euthanasia include: wanting to avoid indignity, unbearable or hopeless suffering, and functional decline; loss of enjoyable activities and weariness of life; not wanting to become a burden on family; and wanting to maintain control of death and desiring a good quality of death.Footnote 43 It is reasonable that some patients “do not want to live through a deteriorating physical and psychological process that inevitably leads to death.”Footnote 44 For many patients, euthanasia is primarily “a way of limiting the loss of self due to personal disintegration”Footnote 45 and a way of controlling the manner and timing of death.Footnote 46 Palliative care simply cannot achieve this, irrespective of its capacity to alleviate pain and other symptoms. This is not a radical view; almost two-thirds of Dutch doctors in one empirical study agree with me.Footnote 47
Accepting Euthanasia as Being Complementary to Palliative Care Does Not Indicate the Failure of Palliative Care and Should Not Threaten to Detract from It
Suppose that I have succeeded in establishing that palliative care and euthanasia are compatible and that the former does not render the latter redundant. In the final part of this essay, I will consider the two main motivations for the arguments that palliative care and euthanasia are incompatible and that the former renders the latter redundant, in order to better elucidate the relationship between palliative care and euthanasia.
The first main motivation is that euthanasia is perceived as an indicator of palliative care’s failure. The American Medical Association describes requests for euthanasia as being “tragic.”Footnote 48 Deborah Kirklin claims that “a call for euthanasia is an indictment of the care being given,” and “whilst death is clearly not viewed as a sign of failure in palliative care, it would seem that a call from the patient for help in dying often is.”Footnote 49 Materstvedt and Bosshard claim that euthanasia “should be unnecessary if terminal care patients are properly cared for.”Footnote 50 Rabow and Pantilat claim that the right to die movement is an “expression, at least in part, of patient dissatisfaction with how people are cared for at the end of life.”Footnote 51 However, I maintain that an individual’s personal preference for euthanasia does not necessarily reflect a failure of palliative care and vice versa. Euthanasia is sometimes more successful at relieving suffering than palliative care; always expecting palliative care to relieve physical suffering—let alone nonphysical suffering—is unreasonable and is not a “failing” of palliative care in any important sense.
The other main motivation for the argument that palliative care renders euthanasia redundant is that euthanasia threatens to detract from palliative care.Footnote 52 I have argued that it is important that palliative care does not detract from euthanasia, although I have not stressed enough that the opposite is also true. Palliative care is invaluable. When euthanasia becomes legalized in more jurisdictions across the world, political and organizational bodies should, and no doubt will continue to lobby for increased palliative care funding, emphasizing the responsibility of providing good quality palliative care regardless of the ethics or current laws on euthanasia. Palliative care and euthanasia are not “like fire and water” (as Materstvedt and Bosshard query)Footnote 53; rather, they should be viewed as complementary alternatives at the end of life. This is how palliative care and euthanasia are viewed under the Belgian model of “integral palliative care,”Footnote 54 which I believe to be the correct view.
Acknowledgments
The author would like to thank Dr. Michaelis Michael and Dr. Markos Valaris for their academic guidance during the research and writing of this essay. The author would also like to thank his family and friends for their encouragement, support, and feedback during this process.
Conflicts of Interest
The author declares none.