Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T20:33:25.632Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Agent-Relative Reasons as Second-Order Value Responses

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 March 2020

Jörg Löschke*
Affiliation:
University of Zurich, Department of Philosophy, Zurich, Switzerland

Abstract

Agent-relative reasons are an important feature of any nonconsequentialist moral theory. Many authors think that they cannot be accommodated within a value-first theory that understands all value as agent-neutral. In this paper, I offer a novel explanation of agent-relative reasons that accommodates them fully within an agent-neutral value-first view. I argue that agent-relative reasons are to be understood in terms of second-order value responses: when an agent acts on an agent-relative reason, she responds appropriately to the agent-neutral value of her own appropriate response to some agent-neutral value. This view helps reconcile important elements of deontology and consequentialism.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s) 2020. Published by Canadian Journal of Philosophy

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Betzler, Monika. 2004. “Personal Projects as Practical Reasons.” Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Bykvist, Krister. 2009. “No Good Fit: Why the Fitting Attitude Analysis of Value Fails.” Mind 118: 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chappell, Timothy. 2014. Knowing What to Do. Imagination, Virtue, and Platonism in Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crisp, Roger. 2005. “Values, Reasons and the Structure of Justification: How to Avoid Passing the Buck.” Analysis 65: 8085.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dancy, Jonathan. 1993. Moral Reasons. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Dancy, Jonathan. 2000. “Should We Pass the Buck?Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 47: 159–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Danielsson, Sven, and Olson, Jonas. 2007. “Brentano and the Buck-Passers.” Mind 116: 511–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. 2006. The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Double, Richard. 1999. “Morality, Impartiality, and What We Can Ask of Persons.” American Philosophical Quarterly 36: 149–58Google Scholar
Finlay, Steven. 2014. Confusion of Tongues: A Theory of Normative Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gregory, Alex. 2014. “A Very Good Reason to Reject the Buck-Passing Account.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92: 287303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gregory, Alex. 2016. “Reasons as Good Bases.” Philosophical Studies 173: 2291–310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hammerton, Matthew. 2016. “Patient-Relativity in Morality.” Ethics 127: 626.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heuer, Ulrike. 2006. “Explaining Reasons: Where Does the Buck Stop?Journal of Ethics & Social Philosophy 1: 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heuer, Ulrike. 2011. “The Paradox of Deontology, Revisited.” Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics 1: 236–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 1987. “‘Good’ and ‘Good for.’” Mind 96: 7173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 2001. Virtue, Vice, and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 2003. “Moore in the Middle.” Ethics 113: 599628.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. 2014. British Ethical Theorists from Sidgwick to Ewing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeske, Diane. 2001. “Friendship and Reasons of Intimacy.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63: 329–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeske, Diane. 2008. Rationality and Moral Theory: How Intimacy Generates Reasons. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagan, Shelly. 1989. The Limits of Morality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kamm, Frances. 1992. Non-Consequentialism, the Person as an End-in-itself, and the Significance of Status. Philosophy and Public Affairs 21: 354–89.Google Scholar
Kamm, Frances. 2007. Intricate Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kauppinen, Antti. 2014. “Fittingness and Idealization.” Ethics 124: 572–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, Simon. 2013. Partiality. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kelly, Chris. 2014. “Value Monism, Richness, and Environmental Ethics.” Les ateliers de l’éthique/The Ethics Forum 9: 110–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lang, Gerald. 2008. “The Right Kind of Solution to the Wrong Kind of Reason Problem.” Utilitas 20: 472–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lippert-Rasmussen, Kasper. 2009. “Kamm on Inviolability and Agent-Relative Restrictions.” Res Publica 15: 165–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Louise, Jennie. 2004. “Relativity of Value and the Consequentialist Umbrella.” Philosophical Quarterly 54: 518–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mack, Eric. 2005. “Prerogatives, Restrictions, and Rights.” Social Philosophy and Policy 22: 357–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maguire, Barry. 2016. “The Value-Based Theory of Reasons.” Ergo 3: 232–62.Google Scholar
Maguire, Barry. 2017. “Love in the Time of Consequentialism.” Noûs 51: 686712.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McNaughton, David, and Rawling, Piers. 1992. “Honoring and Promoting Values.” Ethics 102: 835–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McNaughton, David, and Rawling, Piers. 1998. “On Defending Deontology.” Ratio 11: 3754.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McNaughton, David, and Rawling, Piers. 2013. “Contours of the Practical Landscape.” In Thinking About Reasons: Themes from the Philosophy of Jonathan Dancy, edited by Bakhurst, David, Hooker, Brad, and Little, Olivia, 240–64. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McHugh, Conor, and Way, Jonathan. 2016. “Fittingness First.” Ethics 126: 575606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1986. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1995. “Personal Rights and Public Space.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 24: 83107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nair, Shyam. 2014. “A Fault Line in Ethical Theory: Consequentialism, Deontic Constraints, and the Prisoner’s Dilemma.” Philosophical Perspectives 28: 173200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nye, Howard, Plunkett, David, and Ku, John. 2015. “Non-Consequentialism Demystified.” Philosophers’ Imprint 15: 128.Google Scholar
Oddie, Graham. 2005. Value, Reality, and Desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Orsi, Francesco. 2013. “What’s Wrong with Moorean Buck-Passing?Philosophical Studies 164: 727–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, Philipp. 1987. “Universalizability without Utilitarianism.” Mind 96: 7482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, Philipp. 1988. “The Paradox of Loyalty.” American Philosophical Quarterly 25: 163–71.Google Scholar
Portmore, Douglas. 2011. Commonsense Consequentialism: Wherein Morality Meets Rationality. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabinowicz, Wlodek, and Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni. 2004. “The Strike of the Demon: On Fitting Pro-Attitudes and Values.” Ethics 114: 391423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabinowicz, Wlodek, and Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni. 2006. “Buck-Passing and the Right Kind of Reasons.” Philosophical Quarterly 56: 114–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 2000. “The Truth in Particularism.” In Moral Particularism, edited by Hooker, Brad and Little, Margret Olivia, 4878. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 2001. Value, Respect, and Attachment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Regan, Donald H. 2004. “Why Am I My Brother’s Keeper?” In Reason and Value: Themes from the Philosophy of Joseph Raz, edited by Wallace, R. Jay, Scheffler, Samuel, and Smith, Michael, 202–30. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ridge, Michael. 2011. “Reasons for Action: Agent-Neutral vs. Agent-Relative.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/reasons-agent.Google Scholar
Ridge, Michael. 2014. Impassioned Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni. 2011. Personal Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosati, Connie. 2008. “Objectivism and Relational Good.” Social Philosophy and Policy 25: 314–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowland, Richard. 2013. “Wrong Kinds of Reasons and Consequences.” Utilitas 25: 405–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowland, Richard. 2016. “In Defence of Good Simpliciter.” Philosophical Studies 173: 1371–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, Thomas. 1998. “What We Owe to Each Other.” Cambridge, MA: Belknap.Google Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel. 1982. The Rejection of Consequentialism: A Philosophical Investigation of the Considerations Underlying Rival Moral Conceptions. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel. 2004. “Projects, Relationships, and Reasons.” In Reason and Value: Themes from the Philosophy of Joseph Raz, edited by Wallace, R. Jay, Scheffler, Samuel, and Smith, Michael, 247–69. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Schroeder, Mark. 2007a. “Teleology, Agent-Relative Value, and ‘Good.’” Ethics 117: 265–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, Mark. 2007b. Slaves of the Passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, Mark. 2009. “Buck-Passer’s Negative Thesis.” Philosophical Explorations 12: 341–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seglow, Jonathan. 2013. Defending Associative Duties. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Michael. 2003. “Neutral and Relative Value after Moore.” Ethics 113: 576–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Michael. 2009. “Two Kinds of Consequentialism.” Philosophical Issues 19: 257–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suikkanen, Jussi. 2009. “Buck-Passing Accounts of Value.” Philosophy Compass 4/5: 768–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tan, Kok-Chor. 2010. “Equality and Special Concern.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40: 7398.Google Scholar
van Willigenburg, Theo. 2005. “Reason and Love: A Non-Reductive Analysis of the Normativity of Agent-Relative Reasons.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 8: 4562.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Väyrynen, Pekka. 2006. “Resisting the Buck-Passing Account of Value.” Oxford Studies in Metaethics 1: 295324.Google Scholar
Velleman, David. 1999. “Love as a Moral Emotion.” Ethics 109: 338–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallace, R. Jay. 2010. “Reasons, Values, and Agent-Relativity.” Dialectica 64: 503–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar