Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T20:24:40.022Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Commutativity, Normativity, and Holism: Lange Revisited

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 November 2019

Lisa Cassell*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Maryland, Baltimore County, Baltimore, MD, USA

Abstract

Lange (2000) famously argues that although Jeffrey Conditionalization is non-commutative over evidence, it’s not defective in virtue of this feature. Since reversing the order of the evidence in a sequence of updates that don’t commute does not reverse the order of the experiences that underwrite these revisions, the conditions required to generate commutativity failure at the level of experience will fail to hold in cases where we get commutativity failure at the level of evidence. If our interest in commutativity is, fundamentally, an interest in the order-invariance of information, an updating sequence that does not violate such a principle at the more fundamental level of experiential information should not be deemed defective. This paper claims that Lange’s argument fails as a general defense of the Jeffrey framework. Lange’s argument entails that the inputs to the Jeffrey framework differ from those of classical Bayesian Conditionalization in a way that makes them defective. Therefore, either the Jeffrey framework is defective in virtue of not commuting its inputs, or else it is defective in virtue of commuting the wrong kinds of ones.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s) 2019. Published by Canadian Journal of Philosophy

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bradley, Richard. 2005. “Radical Probabilism and Bayesian Conditionalization.” Philosophy of Science, 72(2): 342–64.Google Scholar
Christensen, David. 1992. “Confirmation Holism and Bayesian Epistemology.” Philosophy of Science, 59(4): 540–57.Google Scholar
Diaconis, Persi, and Zabell, Sandy. 1982. “Updating Subjective Probability.” Journal of the American Statistical Association 77 (380): 822–30.Google Scholar
Domotor, Zoltan. 1980. “Probability Kinematics and Representation of Belief Change.” Philosophy of Science, 47: 384403.Google Scholar
Doring, Frank. 1999. “Why Bayesian Psychology is Incomplete.” Philosophy of Science (Proceedings), 66: 379–89.Google Scholar
Dunn, Jeffrey. “Bayesian Epistemology and Having Evidence” (PhD diss., University of Massachusetts, Amherst, 2010).Google Scholar
Dunn, Jeffrey. 2015. “Reliability for Degrees of Belief.” Philosophical Studies, 172(7): 1929–52.Google Scholar
Field, Hartry. 1978. “A Note on Jeffrey Conditionalization.” Philosophy of Science, 45(3): 361–67.Google Scholar
Garber, Daniel. 1980. “Field and Jeffrey Conditionalization.” Philosophy of Science, 47(1): 142–45.Google Scholar
Hedden, Brian. 2015. Reasons without Persons: Rationality, Identity, and Time. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, Richard. 1965. The Logic of Decision. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, Richard. 1975. “Carnap’s Empiricism.” In Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Induction, Probability, and Confirmation Vol. 6, edited by Maxwell, G. and Jr.Anderson, R. M., 3749. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Lange, Marc. 2000. “Is Jeffrey Conditionalization Defective in Virtue of Being Non-Commutative.” Synthese, 123(3): 393403.Google Scholar
Schwartz, Wolfgang. 2018. “Imaginary Foundations.” Ergo, 29: 764–89.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas. 1984. “Belief and the Will.” Journal of Philosophy, 81: 235–56.Google Scholar
Wagner, Carl. 2002. “Probability Kinematics and Commutativity.” Philosophy of Science, 69: 266–78.Google Scholar
Wagner, Carl. 2003. “Commuting Probability Revisions: The Uniformity Rule.” Erkenntnis 59 (3): 349–64.Google Scholar
Weisberg, Jonathan. 2009. “Commutativity or Holism? A Dilemma for Conditionalizers.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(4): 793812.Google Scholar