Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T20:46:12.881Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Desiring to Try: Reply to Adams

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Alfred R. Mele*
Affiliation:
Davidson College, Davidson , NC28036, USA

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Reply
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 1987

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 ‘He Wants to Try,’ Analysis 50 (1990) 251-3

2 I argued that cases of a familiar kind are unpersuasive—e.g., the woman who allegedly tries to ‘shatter her prized shatter-proof widget in order to prove to a friend that her widget is shatter-proof, while not being at all desirous of shattering it’ (’He Wants to Try,’ 251).

3 My ‘subsequent paper’ is ‘He Wants to Try Again: A Rejoinder,’ Analysis 51 (1991) 225-8; Adams’s rebuttal is ‘He Doesn’t Really Want to Try,’ Analysis 51 109-12; his new attempt is ‘Trying, Desire, and Desiring to Try,’ in this volume.

4 See my Springs of Action (New York: Oxford University Press 1992).

5 Fred Dretske has argued that a componential view of the sort at issue is instrumental in solving the problem of the causal relevance of mental states in Explaining Behavior (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press 1988) and in establishing the possibility of free action in ‘The Metaphysics of Freedom,’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1992) 1-13. For a reply to the first claim, see my ‘Dretske’s Intricate Behavior,’ Philosophical Papers20 (1991) 1-10. For criticism of the second, see Davison, S.Dretske on the Metaphysics of Freedom,’ Analysis 54 (1994) 115-23CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and McCann, H.Dretske on the Metaphysics of Freedom,’ Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23 (1993) 619-30CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 See Searle, J. Intentionality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1983)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. In my ‘Are Intentions Self-Referential?’ Philosophical Studies 52 (1987) 309-29 and elsewhere I argue that the view that all intentions are self-referring (i.e., that the content of any intention refers to that very intention) has psychologically unrealistic implications for toddler’s intentions. I have not quarreled with the idea that some intentions or desires are self-referring, and I have no reservations about there being second-order desires.

7 I myself have never claimed that infants and animals desire to try to do things, even though I have claimed that they desire to do things and that they try to do things.

8 For references to some relevant empirical work, see my Springs of Action, 225, n.12. Also see Gopnik, A.How we Know our Minds: The illusion of First-Person Knowledge,’ Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1993) 1-14CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 Here I ignore various complications and maneuvers addressed in Springs of Action, 204-6.

10 This dispute is skirted in ‘The Intention/Volition Debate.’

11 Adams will claim that being settled upon doing one’s best to A is sufficient for intending to A; and I reject the claim. On my view, intending to A is incompatible with believing that one probably will not A (Springs of Action, ch. 8); and Belton believes that his attempt to solve the problem probably will not generate a solution (’He Wants to Try’). Further, an intention to A, on my view, encompasses motivation to A (Springs of Action); and Belton is motivationally indifferent to his solving the puzzle. (Incidentally, S’s wanting to A plainly is compatible with S’s believing that he probably will not A.)

12 I am grateful to Fred Adams for discussion and to Bob Ware for advice about condensing a draft.