Article contents
The Expositor, the Censor, and the Common Law
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 01 January 2020
Extract
A central tenet of modern Legal Positivism is the claim that “the existence of the law is one thing, its merit or demerit another.” I shall call this “the Positivist dictum.” Jeremy Bentham, the first and perhaps the greatest of the English Positivists, announced this doctrine in his early Fragment on Government, when he distinguished the “Expositor” of the law—who “explains what the law is” and “shows what the Legislator and Judge have done” — from the “Censor” — who instructs us in “what the law ought to be.”
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Authors 1979
References
1 Austin, John, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (london: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1956), pp. 184.Google Scholar
2 The following abbreviations shall be used in referring to collected editions of Bentham's writings: (1) “Works” for The Works of Jeremy Bentham, ed. Bowring (Edinburgh, 1838-43), vols. I-XI; (2) “CW” for The Collected Works of jeremy Bentham, ed. ]. H. Burns (london: The Athlorie Press, 1968- ). The above remarks are found in A Comment on the Commentaries (Comment) and A Fragment on Government (FG) (CW, ed. ]. H. Burns and H. l. A. Hart, 1977), pp. 397-a.
3 Hart, H. L. A., “Bentham and the Demystification of the Law,” Modern Law Review, 36 (1973), pp. 8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
4 Olivecrona, Karl, “The Will of the Sovereign: Some Reflections on Bentham's Concept of ‘a Law', American Journal of Jurisprudence 20 (1975) pp. 107-a.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
5 Of Laws in General (CW, ed. H. L. A. Hart, 1970), Chapter XIX, section 3 (hereafter: OLG XIX, 3).
6 Beginning in the early 1170s. He entitled this work, in early stages, The Elements of Critical jurisprudence - a work which encompasses the material in the Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, Of Laws in General, and his treatises on “Indirect Legislation” and on “The Influence of Place and Time in Matters of Legislation.“
7 Province, pp.191.
8 Lectures on Jurisprudence, 5th edition, ed. Robert Campbell (London: john Murray, 1885), especially lectures XXVIII - XXX, XXXIII, XXXVII - XXXIX, “Essays on Interpretation and Analogy,” and “Notes on Codification.“
9 “But wherever it exists, lawyers will be its defenders, and, perhaps innocently, its admirers. They love the sourced of their power, of their reputation, of their fortune: the love unwritten law for the same reason that the Egyptian priest loved hieroglyphics, for the same reason that the priests of all religions have loved their peculiar d'ogmas and mysteries.” “General View of a Complete Code of Law,” Works, Ill, pp. 206. Bentham saw himself as the “Luther” of jurisprudence, see Works, VII, pp. 270n.
10 “Scotch Reform,” Works, V, pp. 5-8. See also Works, II, pp. 125, 126; VII, pp. 197-98; IX, pp. 8-9,25-26,75.
11 In “Truth vs. Ashurst” Bentham calls it “dog-law“: “When your dog does anything you want to break him of you wait till he does it, and them beat him for it. This is the way you make laws for your dog: and this is the way judges made law for you and me.” Works, V, pp. 235. See also Works, Ill, pp.206; and II, pp. 125.
12 Works. V, pp. 14,478, 512; VII, pp. 308 -9; II, pp. 126; IV, pp. 360. But compare the unpublished MS entitled “Law Common vs. Statute” )university College London, Bentham MSS Box lxiii, pp. 49-50’ hereafter UC oxiii: 49-50) in which Bentham admits that the technique of analogy imposes a significant constraint on judical caprice.
13 “The grant utility of the law is certainty: unwritten law does not - it cannot - possess this quality; the citizen can find no part of it, cannot take it for his guide; he is reduced to consultations - he assembles the lawyers - he collects as many opinions as his fortune will permit; and all this ruinous procedure often serves only to create new doubts.” “General View,” Works, Ill, pp. 206.
14 My account here follows closely the discussion in Simpson, A.W.B., “The Common Law and Legal Theory,” in Oxford Essays in jurisprudence, ed. Simpson, A. W. B. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973), pp. 77–99.Google Scholar
15 “law Common vs. Statue,” (UCixiii: 50).
16 Sir William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England, Book I, pp. 68, 67.
18 Blackstone, Commentaries, Book I, pp. 74.
19 The importance of this was made clear to me after reading Long, Douglas G., Bentham on Liberty (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1977), especially pp. 88–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar I am indebted to this account for the material in the next paragraph.
20 See note 13 above; also “Pannomial Fragments,” Works, Ill, pp. 223 - 24 and Constitutional Code, Works, IX, pp. 25.
21 long, Bentham on Liberty, pp. 201. See especially long's references in note 7 to this passage.
22 The latter half of this condition is explicitly called for in Comment pp. 125 (see below section 7); also see OLG, XV, 12.
23 Bentham embillishes the argument above when he argues in (the late) Pannomial Fragments” that a judge's particular orders are authoritative only if there is another command (or rule)” general in its extent and in such sort general as to include and give authority to this individual decree of his.” He then insists that in common law there is no such general authorizing law because a law is a command and there is no assignable commander of such a general authorizing command. works, Ill, pp. 223.
24 Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (CW, ed. ). H. Burns and H. l. A. Hart, 1970), chapter XVII, section 22 (hereafter IPML,XVII, 22).
25 And Bentham seems to agree. See Comment, II, 4, pp. 184.
26 Simpson, “The Common Law,” p. 89.
27 “A law is an expression of will: that is an assemblage of signs expressive of an act of the will. These signs then may by possibility be any signs whatever which are capable of expressing such a will: the behavior of him who instead of saying, put to death the chief leaders of the people, smote off the tallest heads among a parcel of poppies, might instead of being an advice, have been a command” (OLG, XIII, 1).
28 Here Bentham differs significantly from the Natural Law tradition at a point where a superficial view might have uncovered a convergence of views. According to St. Thomas, promulgation is a logically necessary condition of a principle of reason's being /aw (this holds even for “natural law” which is, according to Aquinas, “Written on the hearts of men“). See Summa Theo/ogica, lallae, QQ. 90a4, 91a2.
29 “Written law has a ceretain manifest foundation. There is a legislator-there is a will- there is an expression of that will, a known period of its birth. Unwritten law possesses none of those qualities: its origin is unknown; it goes on continually increasing - it can never be finished; it is continually altering, without observation.” “General View,” Works, Ill, pp. 206.
30 This is clearly illustrated in Comment, II, 1, pp. 119.
31 See also “Rationale of judicial Evidence,” Works, VII, pp. 309.
32 The following discussion draws on a more extensive investigation (in preparation) of Bentham's theory of fictions and his view of the nature and scope of the Principle of Utility. From this discussion it becomes clear that the dependence of Bentham's metaphysics and epistemology on his Utilitarianism is even more radical than I claim below. Although the evidence for Bentham's views on fictions offered below is drawn largely from his later writings (dating from 1813 to the mid-1820s), there is ample evidence that Bentham's researches into “metaphysics” date back to his earliest period (1770s). Bentham relies on these researches often in his works, but did not attempt to put them together systematically until late in his career. On Bentham's early researches on language and fictions see James Steintrager, Bentham (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1977) chapter 1, and long, Bentham on Liberty, chapter 4.
33 Ogden, C. K., Bentham's Theory of Fictions (Patterson: Littlefield, Adams and Co., 1959), pp.12Google Scholar (“A Fragment on Ontology,” Works, VIII, pp. 197).
34 See Ogden, pp. xxvii, xxviii, xlvii, lxxii -lxxx, 86-91; “Chrestomathia,” Works VIII, pp. 126-27.
35 Bentham seems to be inconsistent on the status of laws. He is logically committed to the fictitious status of laws and actions, but he says in at least one place that both are real entities - in contrast with rights and obligations (OLG, App. C, 15). But he may be using “real” in an extended sense, as he does when he says at some points that qualities are “real” (i.e. more, or closer to, real). See Ogden, bentham's Theory of Fictions, pp. lx- xi.
36 On Bentham's “technological” view of language, see Ogden, pp. xlvi-lii.
37 Bentham even says, at the conclusion of his account of custom: “Now of the idea of customs thus generated is made up the idea of the Common law” (Comment, II, 4, pp.185).
38 “It is not too much to say that one sustaining motif throughout Bentham's long and complicated life was his conviction of the primacy of legislation and of his own mission as the philosopher-legislator.” Gertrude Himmelfarb, “Bentham Scholarship and the Bentham ‘Problem',” Journal of Modern History(1969), pp. 194. Bentham makes this very clear in the MS quoted by Mary Peter Mack, a Bentham Reader(New York: Pegasus, 1969), pp. xi.
39 The distinction appears earlier in a letter to the Gazetteer & New Daily Advertiser (December 3, 1770) attacking John Glynn for faults later also attributed to Blackstone. See. D. Baumgardt, Bentham and the Ethics of Today (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1952), pp. 18.
40 FG, Preface, pp. 417 n.z. See also IPML, XVI, 56, 59; and OLG,XIX, 5.
41 Cf. Austin's notion of “General jurisprudence” in his “Uses of the Study of Jurisprudence,” in Province, pp. 367.
42 For the chapter references in the first sentence see OLG, pp. 233 editor's note 1, and the editor's introduction.
43 See Generally, “General View,” Works, Ill, pp. 161-163.
44 See “Nomography,” Works, Ill, pp. 233-83.
45 On the relation between the end of “giving execution and effect to the will of the legislator” and the Principle of Utility see my “The Principle of Utility and the Law of Procedure: Bentham's Theory of Adjudication,” Georgia Law Review 11 (1977), pp. 1395-407,1410-19.
46 On the influence of Beccaria and Helvetius see Long, Bentham on Liberty, Chapter 2 (especially pp. 26-28), and references given there. Bentham reports that not only were the works eventuating in IPML, OLG, and other related tracts “built solely on the foundation of utility laid as it is by Helvetius” (letter to Voltaire, November, 1776), but also that it was through Helvetius that he discovered his “genius for legislation.” See Himmelfarb, “The Bentham Problem,” pp. 196-97.
47 See Steintrager, Bentham, pp. 20-22.
48 Steintrager, pp. 20.
49 Graveson, R.H., “The Restless Spirit of English Law,” in jeremy Bentham and the Law, ed. Keeton, G. W. and Schwartzenberger, G. (London: Stevens and Sons, 1948), pp. 102.Google Scholar
50 Simpson, “The Common law,” pp. 99.
51 The above arguments are based solely on the major published works of Bentham. Since completion of this article, I have had an opportunity to study much of the unpublished MS material at University College london. These MSS, especially some very important early ones, strongly confirm the reading developed in this article. I have taken account of this MSS material in a much expanded version of the above arguments which is part of a book-length study of Bentham's theories of law and adjudication now in preparation.
- 4
- Cited by