Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-15T09:21:40.263Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How Beliefs Find Their Objects

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Michael Beebe*
Affiliation:
University of British Columbia

Extract

A theory is developed explaining how beliefs, and derivatively intentions and perhaps the other propositional attitudes, find their objects. Beliefs about particular objects are divided into two kinds. Attributive beliefs find their objects purely through the mediation of contained descriptive content, while referential beliefs connect directly with their objects via a causal connection. This distinction is explicated in terms of complementing semantic and epistemic differences, and details of the causal connection are explored.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 1979

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 There is quite a wide literature on the topic, but these three sources are probably the most important: Quine, W.F., “Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes”, in The Ways of Paradox (Revised Edition) (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard U.P., 1976), pp. 185-96;Google Scholar Kaplan, David, “Quantifying In,” in Words and Objections, ed. · Davidson, D. and Hintikka, J. (Dordrecht-Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1969), pp. 178214;Google Scholar and Hintikka, J., Knowledge and Belief (Ithaca: Cornell U.P., 1962).Google Scholar

2 See Kripke, Saul, “Speaker's Reference and Semantic Reference,” in Midwestern Studies in Philosophy, vol. 2, pp. 255-78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3 David Kaplan, “Dthat”, unpublished paper circulated privately.

4 Donnellan, Keith, “Reference and Definite Descriptions,” Philosophical Review 75 (1966), pp. 281304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5 Keith Donnellan, “Reference and Definite Descriptions.“

6 W.V. Quine, “Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes“

7 Burge, Tyler, “Belief de Re,” journal of Philosophy 74 (1977), pp. 338-62CrossRefGoogle Scholar, but especially p. 341.

8 Tyler Burge, “Belief De Re“; Wallace, John, “Belief and Satisfaction,” Nous 6 (1972), pp. 8595;CrossRefGoogle Scholar and Loar, Brian, “Reference and Propositional Attitudes,” Philosophical Review 80 (1972), pp. 4362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

9 Kripke, Saul, “Naming and Necessity,” in Semantics of Natural Language, ed. Davidson, D. and Harman, C. (Dordrecht-Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1972), pp. 253355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

10 Saul Kripke, “Naming and Necessity.“

11 These are the main sources: Saul Kripke, “Naming and Necessity,” Donnellan, Keith, “Proper Names and Identifying Descriptions,” in Semantics of Natural Language, ed. Davidson, D. and Harman, G. (Dordrecht-Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1972), pp. 356-79;CrossRefGoogle Scholar and David Kaplan, “Demonstratives”, given at the 1977 Meetings of the Pacific Division of the American Philosophical Association (and also “Dthat”, circulated privately).

12 David Kaplan, “Quantifying ln.”

13 W.V. Quine, “Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes.” The explicit avowal of this view occurs on p. 190 in The Ways of Paradox (Revised Edition).

14 Quine, W.V., “Intensions Revisited,” in Midwestern Studies in Philosophy, vol. 2, PP.511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

15 Goldman, Alvin I., ” A Causal Theory of Knowing,” Journal of Philosophy 76 (1967), pp. 357-72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

16 C.B. Martin and Max Deutscher, “Memory,” Philosophical Review 75 (1966), pp.161-96.

17 C. B. Martin and Max Deutscher, “Memory“; see pp.186-91.

18 Only referential beliefs and intentions find their objects this way, of course, for only they need any sort of causal connection with their objects. Attributive beliefs find their objects purely through their descriptive content. They have places clusters though. An attributive belief about the ϕ will be in the cluster in which one represents to oneself the object which one thinks is in fact the ϕ . But it is a contingent feature of any attributive belief that it has the object it has, while it is an essential feature of a referential belief. The causal element acts in belief analogously to rigid designators in sentences.

19 An example of Donnellan's is relevant here (Keith Donnellan, “Proper Names and Identifying Descriptions“). Suppose one knows A (J. L. Aston-Martin in Donnallan's story) by reputation, knows his written work, and so on. One then meets someone, B, at a party and thinks he is A. Later in talking with a friend one might say “A wrote such-and-such a book” and “A said so-and-so at the party.” In fact it was B and not A who said the things at the party. Now, Donnellan in his discussion of this example seems to suggest that in discussing his books, the speaker refers to A, but that in reporting B's remarks at the party, he refers to Bthough of course the speaker thinks B and A are the same. This is in effect to suggest that at least sometimes the referent is determined not through the cluster, but just through the causal connection embedded in the trace of the belief the speaker wishes to convey. I think Donnellan is wrong about this. We need clusters, and so no unambiguous reference takes place here at all.

20 For arguments to the conclusion that we very often lack identifying knowledge of objects we refer to and, a fortiori, have beliefs about, see Keith Donnellan, “Proper Names and Identifying Descriptions” and Saul Kripke, “Naming and Necessity.“

21 There is a wrong way to express what is impossible here, which makes it look like a false metaphysical thesis about Homer. Suppose the object of the beliefs we take to be about Homer was, by the belief-trace technique, found to be a third century B.C. Greek with no connection whatever with The /Iliad and The Odyssey. That peasant could not be the object of our belief, we want to say. And that is right. But it is false that Homer could not have been a third century Greek peasant for of course he could have been.