Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-94fs2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-11T08:57:48.719Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Love: self-propagation, self-preservation, or ekstasis?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Jennifer Whiting*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Toronto

Abstract

My title refers to three accounts of interpersonal love: the rationalist (and ultimately rational egoist) account that Terence Irwin ascribes to Plato; the anti-rationalist but strikingly similar account that Harry Frankfurt endorses in his own voice; and the ‘ekstatic’ account that I – following the lead of Martha Nussbaum – find in Plato's Phaedrus. My claim is that the ekstatic account points to important features of interpersonal love to which the other accounts fail to do justice, especially reciprocity and a regulative ideal of equality.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1.

I dedicate this essay to the memory of two friends with whom I often discussed these issues: Rogers Albritton, who died during the year I was drafting this for an APA Symposium, and Paul Hoffman, at whose memorial conference I later presented a revised version. (Paul was himself a student and friend of Rogers and presented a paper at the memorial conference for Rogers.) Though we often disagreed about these issues, I like to think that each would see something of their own spirit living on in this paper. Each was a model of ‘ekstatic’ conversation, always engaging on equal and reciprocal terms with their interlocutors and willing to follow their interlocutors on the interlocutor's own terms. Paul once told me he thought he learned more from thinking about what his students were trying to say in their papers than from any other activity. He, like Rogers, had a talent for taking others seriously.

References

Aristotle, . 2002. Nicomachean Ethics, Translated by Christopher Rowe, with introduction and commentary by Sarah Broadie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brink, David. 1991. “Rational Egoism, Self and Others.” In Identity, Character and Morality, edited by Rorty, A., and Flanagan, O., 339378. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, John M., and Hutchinson, D. S., eds. 1997. Plato: The Complete Works. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry. 1988. The Importance of What We Care About. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry. 1994. “Autonomy, Necessity, and Love.” In Vernunftbegriffe in der Moderne: Stuttgarter Hegel-Kongress 1993. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, [Reprinted in Frankfurt (1999) 129–141 (which is the pagination used above)].Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry. 1997. “Identification and Wholeheartedness.” In Responsibility, Character, and the Emotions: New Essays in Moral Psychology, edited by David Schoeman, Ferdinand. New York: Cambridge University Press, [Reprinted in Frankfurt (1988) 159–176 (which is the pagination used above)].Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry. 1999. Necessity, Volition, and Love. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry. 2002. “Reply to Wolf.” In Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes from Harry Frankfurt, edited by Buss, S., and Overton, L., 245252. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry. 2004. The Reasons of Love. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Helm, Bennett. 1996. “Freedom of the Heart.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (2): 7187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Helm, Bennett. 2010. Love, Friendship, and the Self: Intimacy, Identification, and the Social Nature of Persons. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffman, Paul. 1995. “Freedom and Strength of Will: Descartes and Albritton.” Philosophical Studies 77 (2/3): 241260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irwin, T. H. 1988. Aristotle's First Principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. H. 1995. Plato's Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, John. 1978. “Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 52: 1329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, John. 1979. “Virtue and Reason.” The Monist 62 (3): 331350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, Richard. 2007. “Review Essay on The Reasons of Love.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (2): 463475.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1970. The Possibility of Altruism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1979. “The speech of Alcibiades: a reading of Plato's Symposium.” Philosophy and Literature 3 (2): 131172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1982. “‘This story isn't true’: poetry, goodness, and understanding in Plato's Phaedrus.” In Plato on Beauty, Wisdom, and the Arts, edited by Moravcsik, J., and Tempko, P.. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1989. The fragility of goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Vasiliou, Iakovos. 2008. Aiming at Virtue in Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, David. 1999. “Love as a Moral Emotion.” Ethics 109 (2): 338374, [Reprinted in Velleman 2006. Self to Self. New York: Cambridge University Press].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Jennifer. 1986. “Friends and Future Selves.” The Philosophical Review 9: 547580, [To be reprinted in Whiting forthcoming, volume I].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Jennifer. 1991. “Impersonal Friends.” The Monist 74 (1): 329, [To be reprinted in Whiting forthcoming, volume I].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Jennifer. 1996. “Self-Love and Authoritative Virtue.” In Aristotle, Kant and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty, edited by Engstrom, S., and Whiting, J., 162199. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, [To be reprinted in Whiting forthcoming, volume I].Google Scholar
Whiting, Jennifer. 2002. “Personal Identity: the non-branching form of ‘What Matters’.” In The Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics, edited by Gale, Richard, 190218. Oxford: Blackwell, [To be reprinted in Whiting forthcoming, volume I].Google Scholar
Whiting, Jennifer. 2005. “Trusting ‘First’ and ‘Second’ Selves: Aristotelian Reflections on Virginia Woolf and Annette Baier.” In Persons and Passions: Essays in Honor of Annette Baier, edited by Jenkins, J. Whiting, J., and Williams, C., 329364. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, [To be reprinted in Whiting forthcoming, volume I].Google Scholar
Whiting, Jennifer. 2006. “The Nicomachean Conception of Philia.” In The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, edited by Kraut, R., 276304. Oxford: Blackwell, [To be reprinted in Whiting forthcoming, volume I].Google Scholar
Whiting, Jennifer. forthcoming. Essays in two volumes. Volume I: First, Second and Other Selves: Essays on Friendship and Personal Identity. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wolf, Susan. 2002. “The True, the Good, and the Loveable: Frankfurt's Avoidance of Objectivity.” In Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes from Harry Frankfurt, edited by Buss, S., and Overton, L., 227244. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Woolf, Virginia. 2011. The Collected Short Stories of Virginia Woolf. Oxford: City Press.Google Scholar