Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-15T19:42:48.817Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Recovering What Is Said With Empty Names

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Gualtiero Piccinini
Affiliation:
University of Missouri - St. Louis, St. Louis, MO63132, USA
Sam Scott
Affiliation:
Toronto, ONM6K 3B2, Canada

Extract

As our data will show, negative existential sentences containing socalled empty names evoke the same strong semantic intuitions in ordinary speakers and philosophers alike.

(1)

  • (a) Santa Claus does not exist.

  • (b) Superman does not exist.

  • (c) Clark Kent does not exist.

Uttering the sentences in (1) seems to say something truth-evaluable, to say something true, and to say something different for each sentence. A semantic theory ought to explain these semantic intuitions.

The intuitions elicited by (1) are in apparent conflict with the Millian view of proper names. According to Millianism, the meaning (or ‘semantic value’) of a proper name is just its referent. But empty names, such as ‘Santa Claus’ and ‘Superman’, appear to lack a referent. If they do, then Millianism entails that they have no meaning.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, F. and Dietrich, L.A.. 2004. ‘What's in a(n Empty) Name?Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85 (2004) 125–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, F. and Fuller, G.. 2007. ‘Empty Names and Pragmatic Implicatures.Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (2007) 449–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, F. and Stecker, R.. 1994. ‘Vacuous Singular Terms.’ Mind and Language 9 (1994) 387401.Google Scholar
Adams, F. Stecker, R. and Fuller, G.. 1992. ‘The Semantics of Thoughts.Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 73 (1992) 375–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bach, K. 1994a. ‘Conversational Impliciture.’ Mind and Language 9 (1994) 124–62.Google Scholar
Bach, K. 1994b. Thought and Reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bach, K. 2001. ‘You Don't Say?Synthese 128 (2001) 1544.Google Scholar
Bach, K. 2002. ‘Giorgione Was So-Called Because of His Name.Philosophical Perspectives 16 (2002) 73–103.Google Scholar
Bach, K. 2006. ‘The Excluded Middle: Semantic Minimalism without Minimal Propositions.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (2006) 435–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bach, K. 2007. ‘Review of Minimal Semantics.Philosophical Review 116 (2007) 303–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braun, D. 1993. ‘Empty names.’ Noûs 27 (1993) 449–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braun, D. 2005. ‘Empty Names, Fictional Names, Mythical Names.Noûs 39 (2005) 596–631.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borg, E. 2004. Minimal Semantics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgess, J.P. and Rosen, G.. 1997. A Subject with No Object: Strategies for Nominalistic Interpretation of Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Caplan, B. 2002. Empty Names: An Essay on the Semantics, Pragmatics, Metaphysics, and Epistemology of Empty Names and Other Directly Referential Expressions. Ph.D. diss., University of California, Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Caplan, B. 2007. ‘Millian Descriptivism.Philosophical Studies 133 (2007) 181–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cappelen, H. and Lepore, E.. 2005. Insensitive Semantics: A Defense of Semantic Minimalism and Speech Act Pluralism. Malden, MA: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donnellan, K.S. 1970. ‘Proper Names and Identifying Descriptions.Synthese 21 (1970) 335–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorr, C. 2007. ‘There Are No Abstract Objects.’ In Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics, Hawthorne, J. Sider, T. and Zimmerman, D. eds. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Elugardo, R. and Stainton, R. eds. 2005. Ellipsis and Non-Sentential Speech. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edwards, K. forthcoming. ‘Concept Referentialism and the Role of Empty Concepts.’ Mind and Language.Google Scholar
Everett, A. 2003. ‘Empty Names and ‘Gappy’ Propositions.’ Philosophical Studies 116 (2003) 136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Everett, A. 2005. ‘Against Fictional Realism.The Journal of Philosophy 102 (2005) 624–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Everett, A. 2007. ‘Pretense, Existence, and Fictional Objects.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (2007) 56–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, H. 1989. Realism, Mathematics, and Modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Green, M.S. 2007. ‘Direct Reference, Empty Names and Implicature.Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (2007) 419–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, M.S. forthcoming. ‘Gappy Propositions, Ways of Believing and Empty Names.’ In Essays on Empty Names, Everett, A. and H., Deutsch eds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Grice, H.P. 1989. Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1998. ‘Reference and Description Revisited.Philosophical Perspectives 12 (1998) 201–18.Google Scholar
Katz, J.J. 1994. ‘Names Without Bearers.Philosophical Review 103 (1994) 1–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S.A. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Larson, R.K. and Segal, G.. 1995. Knowledge of Meaning: An Introduction to Semantic Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meinong, A. 1904. ‘The Theory of Objects.’ In Realism and the Background of Phenomenology, Chisholm, R.M. ed. 1960. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Parsons, T. 1980. Nonexistent Objects. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Perry, J. 2001. Reference and Reflexivity. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Piccinini, G. and Scott, S.. 2006. ‘Splitting Concepts.Philosophy of Science 73 (2006) 390–409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Predelli, S. 2002. ‘“Holmes” and Holmes — A Millian Analysis of Names from Fiction.Dialectica 56 (2002) 261–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Priest, G. 2005. Towards Non-Being: The Logic and Metaphysics of Intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Recanati, F. 1989. ‘The Pragmatics of What Is Said.’ Mind and Language 4 (1989) 295329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Recanati, F. 2004. Literal Meaning. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Reimer, M. 2001a. ‘The Problem of Empty Names.Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79 (2001) 491–506.Google Scholar
Reimer, M. 2001b. ‘A ‘Meinongian’ Solution to a Millian Problem.American Philosophical Quarterly 38 (2001) 233–48.Google Scholar
Ryckman, T.C. 1988. ‘The Millian Theory of Proper Names and the Problems of Negative Existentials and Non-Referring Names.’ In Philosophical Analysis: A Defense by Example, Austin, D.F. ed. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Sainsbury, M. 2005. Reference Without Referents. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, N. 1998. ‘Nonexistence.’ Noûs 32 (1998) 277319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, J.R. 1983. Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Segal, G. 2001. ‘Two Theories of Proper Names.’ Mind and Language 16 (2001) 547–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soames, S. 2002. Beyond Rigidity: The Unfinished Semantic Agenda of Naming and Necessity. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stainton, R. 2005. ‘In Defense of Non-Sentential Assertion.’ In Semantic vs. Pragmatics, Szabo, Z. ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stanley, J. 2000. ‘Context and Logical Form.Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (2000) 391–434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, K. 2000. ‘Emptiness Without Compromise.’ In Reference and the Rational Mind, Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications 2003.Google Scholar
Taylor, K. (2001). ‘Sex, Breakfast, and Descriptus Interruptus.’ Synthese 128 (2001) 4561.Google Scholar
Thau, M. 2002. Consciousness and Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wyatt, N. 2007. ‘The Pragmatics of Empty Names.Dialogue 46 (2007) 663–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zalta, E.N. 2000. ‘Pretense Theory and Abstract Object Theory.’ In Empty Names, Fiction and the Puzzles of Non-Existence, Everett, A. & Hofweber, T. eds. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar