Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-15T16:04:32.577Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Functionalism, Computationalism, and Mental Contents

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Gualtiero Piccinini*
Affiliation:
Washington University, St. Louis, MO63130-4899, USA

Extract

Almost no one cites Sellars, while reinventing his wheels with gratifying regularity. (Dennett 1987, 349)

In philosophy of mind, there is functionalism about mental states and functionalism about mental contents. The former — mental State functionalism — says that mental states are individuated by their functional relations with mental inputs, Outputs, and other mental states. The latter — usually called functional or conceptual or inferential role semantics — says that mental contents are constituted by their functional relations with mental inputs, Outputs, and other mental contents (and in some versions of the theory, with things in the environment). If we add to mental State functionalism the popular view that mental states have their content essentially, then mental state functionalism may be seen as a form of functional role semantics and a solution to the problem of mental content, namely, the problem of giving a naturalistic explanation of mental content. According to this solution, the functional relations that constitute contents are physically realized — in a metaphysically unmysterious way — by the functional relations between mental inputs, outputs, and the mental states bearing those contents.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2004

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Block, N. 1986. ‘Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology,’ in Midwest Studies in Philosophy X: Studies in the Philosophy of Mind, French, P. Uehling, T.E. JR. and Wettstein, H.K. eds. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Brandom, R.B. 1994. Making it Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Communient. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brooks, R.A. 1997. ‘Intelligence without Representation,’ in Mind Design II, Haugeland, J. ed. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1957. Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1965. Aspects of a Theory of Syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P.M. 1979. Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P.M. 1989. A Neurocomputational Perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P.M. and P.S., Churchland. 1983. ‘Stalking the Wild Epistemic Engine.Noûs 17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P.S. and T.J., Sejnowski. 1992. The Computational Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, A. 1997. Being There. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Crane, T. 1990. ‘The Language of Thought: No Syntax Without Semantics.Mind and Language 5 187212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, R. 1983. The Nature of Psychological Explanation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cummins, R. 1989. Meaning and Mental Representation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D.C. 1969. Content and Consciousness. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Dennett, D.C. 1971. ‘Intentional Systems.Journal of Philosophy 68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D.C. 1978. Brainstorms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D.C. 1987. The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Deutsch, J.A. 1960. The Structural Basis of Behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. I. 1981. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F.I. 1986. ‘Misrepresentation,’ in Belief: Form, Content, and Function, Bogdan, R. ed. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Egan, F. 1999. ‘In Defence of Narrow Mindedness.Mina and Language 14.Google Scholar
Field, H. 1978. ‘Mental Representation.Erkenntnis 13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J.A. 1965. ‘Explanations in Psychology,’ in Philosophy in America, Black, M. ed. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Fodor, J.A. 1968a. Psychological Explanation. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Fodor, J.A. 1968b. ‘The Appeal to Tacit Knowledge in Psychological Explanation.Journal of Philosophy 65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J.A. 1975. The Language of Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J.A. 1978. ‘Tom Swift and His Procedural Grandmother.’ Cognition 6. Reprinted in Fodor 1981.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J.A. 1980. ‘Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology.’ Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3. Reprinted in Fodor 1981.Google Scholar
Fodor, J.A. 1981. Representations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J.A. 1987. Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J.A. 1990. A Theory of Content and Other Essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J.A. 1994. The Elm and the Expert: Mentalese and Its Semantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J.A. 1998. Concepts. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J.A. 2000. The Mind Doesn't Work That Way. MIT Press: Cambridge, MA.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geach, P.T. 1956. Mental Acts. London: Routledge & Paul.Google Scholar
Grush, R. 2001. ‘The Semantic Challenge to Computational Neuroscience,’ in Theory and Method in the Neurosciences, Machamer, P. Grush, R. and McLaughlin, P. eds. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1968. ‘Three Levels of Meaning.Journal of Philosophy 65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. 1970. ‘Sellars’ Semantics.The Philosophical Review 79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. 1973. Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1988. ‘Wide Functionalism,’ in Cognition and Representation, Schiffer, S. and Steele, S. eds. Boulder: Westview.Google Scholar
Haugeland, J. 1978. ‘The Nature and Plausibility of Cognitivism.Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2.Google Scholar
Haugeland, J. 1985. Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Haugeland, J. 1997. Mind Design IL Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horst, S. 2003. ‘The Computational Theory of Mind,’ in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2003 Edition), ed. E. N. Zalta. URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2003/entries/computational-mind/>..>Google Scholar
Ince, D. ed. 1992. Mechanical Intelligence. The Collected Works of Alan Turing. Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. and Pettit, P. 1988. ‘Functionalism and Broad Content.Mind 97.Google Scholar
Jacquette, D. 1991. ‘The Myth of Pure Syntax,’ in Topics in Philosophy and Artificial Intelligence, Albertazzi, L. and Poli, R. eds. Bozen: Istituto Mitteleuropeo di Cultura.Google Scholar
Loar, B. 1981. Mina and Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Loewer, B. and Rey, G. eds. 1991. Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Marr, D. 1982. Vision. New York: Freeman.Google Scholar
McCorduck, P. 1979. Machines Who Think: A Personal Inquiry into the History and Prospects of Artificial Intelligence. San Francisco, CA: Freeman.Google Scholar
McCulloch, W.S. 1965. Embodiments of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
McCulloch, W.S. and Pitts, W.H.. 1943. ‘A Logical Calculus of the Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity.’ Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics 7 115133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, G.A. Galanter, E.H. and Pribram, K.H.. 1960. Plans and the Structure of Behavior. New York: Holt.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R.G. 1984. Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, R.G. 1993. White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Oppenheim, P. and Putnam, H. 1958. ‘Unity of Science as a Working Hypothesis,’ in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume II Concepts, Theories, and the Mind-Body Problem, Feigl, H. Scriven, M. and Maxwell, G. eds. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1992. A Study of Concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Piccinini, G. 2000. ‘Turing's Rules for the Imitation Game.Minds and Machines 10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piccinini, G. 2002. ‘Review of John von Neumann's The Computer and the Brain.Minds and Machines 12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piccinini, G. 2003a. Commutations and Computers in the Sciences of Mind and Brain. Doctoral Dissertation, Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh. URL = <http://etd.library. pitt.edu/ETD/available/etd-08132003-155121/>>Google Scholar
Piccinini, G. 2003b. ‘Alan Turing and the Mathematical Objection.Minds and Machines 12.Google Scholar
Piccinini, G. forthcoming a. ‘Functionalism, Computationalism, and Mental States.’ Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Piccinini, G. forthcoming b. ‘The First Computational Theory of Mind and Brain: A Close Look at McCulloch and Pitts's “Calculus of Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity”.' Synthese.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1960. ‘Minds and Machines,’ in Dimensions of Mind: A Symposium, Hook, S. ed. New York: Collier.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1963. ‘Brains and Behavior,’ in Analytical Philosophy, Butler, R.J. ed. New York: Barnes and Noble. Reprinted in Block, N. ed., Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, Volume 1: 2436. London: Methuen 1980.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1964. ‘Robots: Machines or Artificially Created Life?Journal of Philosophy 61668-91. Reprinted in H. Putnam, Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, Volume 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1975.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1967a. ‘The Mental Life of Some Machines,’ in Intentionality, Minds, and Perception, Castañeda, H.-N. ed. Detroit: Wayne State University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1967b. ‘Psychological Predicates,’ in Art, Philosophy, and Religion. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press. Reprinted as ‘The Nature of Mental States’ in W. Lycan, ed., Mind and Cognition: An Anthology. Second Edition, Maiden: Blackwell 1999.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1974. ‘Comments on Wilfrid Sellars.Synthese 27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. 1988. Representation and Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1997. ‘A Half Century of Philosophy, Viewed from Within.’ Daedalus (Winter 1997) 175208.Google Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z.W. 1984. Computation and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Ryle, G. 1949. The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1954. ‘Some Reflections on Language Games.Philosophy of Science 21. Reprinted in Sellars 1963.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W. 1956. ‘Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind,’ in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. I, The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis, Feigl, H. and Scriven, M. eds. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Reprinted in Sellars 1963.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1961. ‘The Language of Theories,’ in Current Issues in the Philosophy of Science, Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G. eds. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston. Reprinted in Sellars 1963.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1963. Science, Perception, and Reality. Atascadero: Ridgeview.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1967 Science and Metaphysics: Variations on Kantian Themes. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. 1974. ‘Meaning as Functional Classification.Synthese 27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W. 1975. ‘Autobiographical Reflections,’ in Action, Knowledge, and Reality: Studies in Honor of Wilfrid Sellars, Castañeda, H.-N. ed. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Shannon, C.E. and J., McCarthy. 1956. Automata Studies. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, B.C. 1996. On the Origin of Objects. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stich, S. 1983. From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sutherland, N.S. 1960. ‘Theories of Shape Discrimination in Octopus.Nature 186.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Thelen, E. and L., Smith 1994. A Dynamic Systems Approach to the Development of Cognition and Action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Turing, A.M. (1936-7 [1965]). ‘On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem. In The Undecidable, Davis, M. ed. Ewlett: Raven.Google Scholar
Turing, A.M. 1950. ‘Computing Machinery and Intelligence.Mind 59.Google Scholar
van Gelder, T. 1995. ‘What Might Cognition Be, if not Computation?The Journal of Philosophy 92.Google Scholar
Vendler, Z. 1972. Res Cogitans: An Essay in Rational Psychology. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
von Neumann, J. 1958. The Computer and the Brain. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Wiener, N. 1948. Cybernetics or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google ScholarPubMed
Wittgenstein, L. 1953. Philosophical Investigations. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar