Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T20:03:19.791Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

In Favor of the Classical Quine on Ontology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 October 2019

Gary Kemp*
Affiliation:
Philosophy, School of Humanities, University of Glasgow, Glasgow, U.K.

Abstract

I make a Quinean case that Quine’s ontological relativity marked a wrong turn in his philosophy, that his fundamental commitments point toward the classical view of ontology that was worked out in most detail in his Word and Object (1960). This removes the impetus toward (a version of) structuralism in his later philosophy.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s) 2019. Published by Canadian Journal of Philosophy

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Davidson, Donald. 1967. “Truth and Meaning.” Synthese 17 (3): 304–23.Google Scholar
Eklund, Matti. 2007. “The Ontological Significance of Inscrutability.” Philosophical Topics 35 (1/2): 115–34.Google Scholar
Fogelin, Robert. 1997. “Quine’s Limited Naturalism.” The Journal of Philosophy 94 (11): 543–63.Google Scholar
Hylton, Peter. 1990. “Translation, Meaning, and Self-Knowledge” In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, 91: 269–90.Google Scholar
Hylton, Peter. 2007. Quine, Arguments of the Philosophers. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kemp, Gary. 2017. “Is Everything a Set? Quine and (Hyper)Pythagoreanism.” The Monist, 100 (2): 155–66.Google Scholar
Kemp, Gary, and Lugg, Andrew. “Quine on Ontology: Chapter 7 of Word and Object.” In Quine: Structure and Ontology, edited by Janssen-Lauret, Frederique. UK: Oxford University Press, forthcoming.Google Scholar
McGee, Vann. 2005. “Inscrutability and Its Discontents.” Noûs 39 (3): 397425.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hillary. 1985. “A Comparison of Something with Something Else.” New Literary History 17 (1): 6179.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. (1937) 1961. “New Foundations for Mathematical Logic,” in From a Logical Point of View, second edition. Harvard University Press, 80101.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. (1948) 1961. “On What There Is,” in From a Logical Point of View, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 119.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. (1951) 1976. “On Carnap’s Views on Ontology.” In The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays, revised ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 203211.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. (1953) 1961. “The Problem of Meaning in Linguistics.” In From a Logical Point of View, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 4764.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. (1954) 1976. “The Scope and Language of Science.” In The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays, revised ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 228–45.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. 1960. Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. (1964) 1976. “Ontological Reduction and the World of Numbers.” In Ways of Paradox, revised ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 212–20.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. 1968. “Ontological Relativity.” The Journal of Philosophy 65 (7): 185212.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. 1969a. “Ontological Relativity.” In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press, 2668.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. 1969b. “Propositional Objects.” In Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press, 139–60.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. (1970) 2008. “On the Reasons for the Indeterminacy of Translation.” In Confessions of a Confirmed Extensionalist and Other Essays, edited by Føllesdal, D. and Quine, D.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 209214.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. (1975) 2008. “Mind and Verbal Dispositions.” In Confessions of a Confirmed Extensionalist and Other Essays, edited by Føllesdal, D. and Quine, D.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press: 244–56.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. 1976. “Whither Physical Objects?Studies in the Philosophy of Science 39: 303–10.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. 1981a. “Things and Their Place in Theories.” In Theories and Things. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 123.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. 1981b. “Empirical Content.” In Theories and Things. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2430.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. (1983) 2008. “Ontology and Ideology Revisited.” In Confessions of a Confirmed Extensionalist and Other Essays, edited by Føllesdal, D. and Quine, D.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 315–18.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. 1990. Pursuit of Truth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. 1992. Pursuit of Truth, revised ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. (1992) 2008. “Structure and Nature.” In Confessions of a Confirmed Extensionalist and Other Essays, edited by Føllesdal, D. and Quine, D.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 401–6.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van. 1995. From Stimulus to Science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ricketts, Thomas. 2011. “Roots of Ontological Relativity.” American Philosophical Quarterly, 48 (3): 287300.Google Scholar
Tarski, Alfred. (1933) 1983. “The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages.” In Logic, Semantics, Meta-Mathematics. Translated by Woodger, J. H., edited and introduced by Corcoran, J.. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 152278.Google Scholar
Tarski, Alfred. (1955) 1983. “The Establishment of Scientific Semantics.” In Logic, Semantics, Meta-Mathematics. Translated by Woodger, J. H., edited and introduced by Corcoran, J.. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 401–8.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. (1953) 1958. Philosophical Investigations. Translated by Anscombe, G. E. M.. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar