Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T13:54:55.942Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Justification is potential knowledge

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Jonathan Jenkins Ichikawa*
Affiliation:
Philosophy Department, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada

Abstract

This paper will articulate and defend a novel theory of epistemic justification; I characterize my view as the thesis that justification is potential knowledge (JPK). My project is an instance of the ‘knowledge-first’ programme, championed especially by Timothy Williamson. So I begin with a brief recapitulation of that programme.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alston, William P. 1988. “The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification.” Philosophical Perspectives 2: 257299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ball, Brian, and Blome-Tillmann, Michael. Forthcoming. “Counter Closure and Knowledge Despite Falsehood”Google Scholar
Bird, Alexander. 2007. “Justified Judging.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74: 81110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
BonJour, Laurence, and Sosa, Ernest. 2003. Epistemic Justification: Internalism Vs. Externalism, Foundations Vs. Virtues. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Burge, Tyler. 1979. “Individualism and the Mental.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4: 73122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. J. 1997. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Clarke, Roger. 2013. “Belief Is Credence One (In Context).” Philosophers’ Imprint 13: 118.Google Scholar
Cohen, Stewart. 1984. “Justification and Truth.” Philosophical Studies 46: 279295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conee, Earl, and Feldman, Richard. 2008. “Evidence.” In Epistemology: New Essays, edited by Smith, Quentin, 83104. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1987. “Knowing One's Own Mind.” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 60: 441458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, Fred. 1981. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Engel, Mylan. 1992. “Personal and Doxastic Justification in Epistemology.” Philosophical Studies 67: 133150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feit, Neil, and Cullison, Andrew. 2011. “When Does Falsehood Preclude Knowledge?Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 92: 283304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, Richard, and Conee, Earl. 1985. “Evidentialism.” Philosophical Studies 48: 1534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, Richard, and Conee, Earl. 2001. “Internalism Defended.” American Philosophical Quarterly 38: 118.Google Scholar
Fumerton, Richard. 1995. Metaepistemology and Skepticism. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I. 1979. “What Is Justified Belief?Justification and Knowledge, 125. Boston, MA: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I. 1988. “Strong and Weak Justification.” Philosophical Perspectives 2: 5169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I. 1999. “Internalism Exposed.” Journal of Philosophy 96: 271293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I. 2011. “Reliabilism.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, spring 2011 edition, edited by Zalta, Edward N.. Palo Alto: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.Google Scholar
Greco, John. 2010. Achieving Knowledge: A Virtue-Theoretic Account of Epistemic Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, John. 2004. Knowledge and Lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hill, Christopher S., and Schechter, Joshua. 2007. “Hawthorne's Lottery Puzzle and the Nature of Belief.” Philosophical Issues 17: 10201122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ichikawa, Jonathan, and Jarvis, Benjamin W.. 2013. The Rules of Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul A. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, Saul A. 1982. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1996. “Elusive Knowledge.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 549567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Littlejohn, Clayton. 2012. “Lotteries, Probabilities, and Permissions.” Logos and Episteme 3: 509514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGlynn, Aidan. 2012. “Justification as ‘Would-Be’ Knowledge.” Episteme 9: 361376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Jennifer. 2013. “Knowledge as a Mental State.” Oxford Studies in Epistemology 4: 275310.Google Scholar
Nelkin, Dana K. 2000. “The Lottery Paradox, Knowledge, and Rationality.” Philosophical Review 109: 373409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reed, Baron. 2010. “A Defense of Stable Invariantism.” Noûs 44: 224244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Martin. 2010. “What Else Justification Could Be.” Noûs 44: 1031.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, Ernest. 2007. A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, Robert. 1981. Inquiry. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sutton, Jonathan. 2007. Without Justification. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turri, John. 2010. “On the Relationship Between Propositional and Doxastic Justification.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80: 312326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Warfield, Ted A. 2005. “Knowledge From Falsehood.” Philosophical Perspectives 19: 4058211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weatherson, Brian. 2003. “What Good are Counterexamples?Philosophical Studies 115 (1): 131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, Timothy. 2000. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0198250436 (alk. paper).Google Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda Trinkaus. 1996. Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry Into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar