Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-13T04:57:52.216Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Occurrent states

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Gary Bartlett*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies, Central Washington University, Ellensburg, WA, USA

Abstract

The distinction between occurrent and non-occurrent mental states is frequently appealed to by contemporary philosophers, but it has never been explicated in any significant detail. In the literature, two accounts of the distinction are commonly presupposed (and occasionally stated explicitly). One is that occurrent states are conscious states. The other is that non-occurrent states are dispositional states, and thus that occurrent states are manifestations of dispositions. I argue that neither of these accounts is adequate, and therefore that another account is needed. I propose that occurrent states are active states.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2017

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alston, William. 1967. “Motives and Motivation.” In Vol. 5 of The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edwards, Paul, 399409. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David. 1968. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David. 1973. Belief, Truth and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9780511570827CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartlett, Gary. Unpublished. “Functionalism and the Problem of Occurrent States.”Google Scholar
Block, N. J., and Fodor, J. A.. 1972. “What Psychological States are Not.” The Philosophical Review 81(2): 159181. doi: 10.2307/2183991.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Botterill, George. 1994. “Beliefs, Functionally Discrete States, and Connectionist Networks: A Comment on Ramsey, Stich, and Garon.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45(3): 899906. 10.1093/bjps/45.3.899CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braddon-Mitchell, David, and Jackson, Frank. 1996. Philosophy of Mind and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Braddon-Mitchell, David, and Jackson, Frank. 2006. Philosophy of Mind and Cognition. 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Broad, C. D. 1922. “Critical Notices.” Mind XXXI(124): 496510. doi: 10.1093/mind/XXXI.124.496.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broad, C. D. 1924a. “Mr. Johnson on the Logical Foundations of Science (I).” Mind XXXIII(131): 242261. doi: 10.1093/mind/XXXIII.131.242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broad, C. D. 1924b. “Mr. Johnson on the Logical Foundations of Science (II).” Mind XXXIII(132): 369384. doi: 10.1093/mind/XXXIII.132.369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broad, C. D. 1933. Vol. 1 of Examination of McTaggart’s Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Broad, C. D. 1945. “Some Reflections on Moral-Sense Theories in Ethics.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 45(1): 131166. doi: 10.1093/aristotelian/45.1.131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buckwalter, Wesley, Rose, David, and Turri, John. 2015. “Belief Through Thick and Thin.” Noûs 49(4): 748775. doi: 10.1111/nous.12048.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Patricia, and Sejnowski, Terrence. 1992. The Computational Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, Wayne. 2005. “Reasons and Psychological Causes.” Philosophical Studies 122(1): 51101. doi: 10.1007/s11098-005-7249-3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Sousa, Ronald. 2014. “Emotion.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited byZalta, Edward.https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/emotion/.Google Scholar
Ducasse, C. J. 1951. Nature, Mind, and Death. La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Farkas, Katalin. 2008. The Subject’s Point of View. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199230327.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gallie, W. B. 1948. “Dr. Ewing on ‘Mental Acts’.” Mind LVII(228): 480487. doi: 10.1093/mind/LVII.228.480.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gallie, W. B., Sprott, W. J. H., and Mace, C. A.. 1947. “Does Psychology Study Mental Acts or Dispositions?Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 21(1): 134174. doi: 10.1093/aristoteliansupp/21.1.134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gertler, Brie. 2007. “Overextending the Mind?” In Arguing About the Mind, edited by Gertler, Brie and Shapiro, Lawrence, 192206. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Gertler, Brie. 2011. Self-Knowledge. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. 1970. A Theory of Human Action. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin. 1978. “Epistemology and the Psychology of Belief.” Monist 61(4): 525535. doi: 10.5840/monist197861442.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, Terence, and Tienson, John. 1995. “Connectionism and the Commitments of Folk Psychology.” In Philosophical Perspectives 9: AI, Connectionism and Philosophical Psychology, edited by Tomberlin, James, 127152. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview. doi: 10.2307/2214215.Google Scholar
Johnson, W. E. 1921–1924. Vol. 3 of Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kriegel, Uriah. 2011. Subjective Consciousness: A Self-Representational Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mele, Alfred. 2003. Motivation and Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/019515617X.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Melia, Joseph. 2000. “Continuants and Occurrents (II).” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74(1): 7792. doi: 10.1111/1467-8349.00064.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nisbett, Richard, and Wilson, Timothy. 1977. “Telling More Than We can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes.” Psychological Review 84(3): 231259. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.84.3.231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Price, H. H. 1969. Belief. West Conshohocken, PA: Templeton Press. Accessed March 15, 2017. http://www.giffordlectures.org/lectures/beliefGoogle Scholar
Simons, Peter. 2000. “Continuants and Occurrents (I).” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74(1): 5975. doi: 10.1111/1467-8349.00063.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steward, Helen. 1997. The Ontology of Mind: Events, Processes, and States. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stout, Rowland. 2016. “The Category of Occurrent Continuants.” Mind 125(497): 4162. doi: 10.1093/mind/fzv138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Richard. 1960. “‘I Can’.” The Philosophical Review 69(1): 7889. doi: 10.2307/2182268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Jessica. 2017. “Determinates vs. Determinables.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Zalta, Edward.https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/determinate-determinables/.Google Scholar
Wilson, Timothy. 2002. Strangers to Ourselves: Discovering the Adaptive Unconscious. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.Google Scholar