Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T20:30:10.542Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Platonic Laws of Nature

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 November 2019

Tyler Hildebrand*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Dalhousie University, Halifax, NS, Canada

Abstract

David Armstrong accepted the following three theses: universals are immanent, laws are relations between universals, and laws govern. Taken together, they form an attractive position, for they promise to explain regularities in nature—one of the most important desiderata for a theory of laws and properties—while remaining compatible with naturalism. However, I argue that the three theses are incompatible. The basic idea is that each thesis makes an explanatory claim, but the three claims can be shown to run in a problematic circle. I then consider which thesis we ought to reject (hint: see the title) and suggest some general lessons for the metaphysics of laws.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s) 2020. Published by Canadian Journal of Philosophy

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Armstrong, David. 1978a. Universals and Scientific Realism: Nominalism and Realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David. 1978b. Universals and Scientific Realism: A Theory of Universals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David. 1983. What Is a Law of Nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David. 1989. Universals: An Opinionated Introduction. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David. 1997. A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, Elizabeth. 2018. “Symmetric Dependence.” In Reality and Its Structures, edited by Bliss, Ricki and Priest, Graham, 5069. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Beebee, Helen. 2000. “The Non-Governing Conception of Laws of Nature.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61: 571–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, Karen. 2017. Making Things Up. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bird, Alexander. 2007. Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolender, John. 2006. “Nomic Universals and Particular Causal Relations: Which Are Basic and Which Are Derived?Philosophia 34: 405–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carroll, John. 1994. Laws of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cowling, Sam. 2017. Abstract Entities. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demarest, Heather. 2017. “Powerful Properties, Powerless Laws.” In Causal Powers, edited by Jacobs, Jonathan, 3853. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred. 1977. “Laws of Nature.” Philosophy of Science 44: 248–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ellis, Brian. 2001. Scientific Essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Emery, Nina. 2019. “Laws and Their Instances.” Philosophical Studies 176: 1535–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fales, Evan. 1990. Causation and Universals. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Fine, Kit. 2001. “The Question of Realism.” Philosophers’ Imprint 1: 130.Google Scholar
Fine, Kit. 2012. “A Guide to Ground.” In Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality, edited by Correia, Fabrice and Schneider, Benjamin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Foster, John. 1983. “Induction, Explanation, and Natural Necessity.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 83 (1): 87102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foster, John. 2004. The Divine Lawmaker. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
French, Steven. 2014. The Structure of the World: Metaphysics and Representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl. 1965. Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hicks, Michael Townsen, and Schaffer, Jonathan. 2017. “Derivative Properties in Fundamental Laws.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 68: 411–50.Google Scholar
Hicks, Michael Townsen, and van Elswyk, Peter. 2015. “ Humean Laws and Circular Explanation.” Philosophical Studies 172: 433–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hildebrand, Tyler. 2013a. “Can Primitive Laws Explain?Philosophers’ Imprint 13 (15): 115.Google Scholar
Hildebrand, Tyler. 2013b. “Tooley’s Account of the Necessary Connection Between Law and Regularity.” Philosophical Studies 166: 3343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hildebrand, Tyler. 2019. “Scientific Practice and the Epistemology of Governing Laws.” Journal for the American Philosophical Association 5: 174–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jenkins, Carrie S. 2011. “Is Metaphysical Grounding Irreflexive?Monist 94: 267–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koslicki, Kathrin. 2013. “Ontological Dependence: An Opinionated Survey.” In Varieties of Dependence: Ontological Dependence, Grounding, Supervenience, Response-Dependence (Basic Philosophical Concepts), edited by Schneiter, Benjamin, Hoeltje, Miguele, and Steinberg, Alex, 3164. Munich: Philosophia Verlag.Google Scholar
Koslicki, Kathrin. 2015. “The Course-Grainedness of Grounding.” Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 9: 306–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lange, Marc. 2013. “Grounding, Scientific Explanation, and Humean Laws.” Philosophical Studies 164: 255–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lange, Marc. 2018. “Transitivity, Self-Explanation, and the Explanatory Circularity Argument Against Humean Accounts of Natural Law.” Synthese 195: 1337–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1973. Counterfactuals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1983. “New Work for a Theory of Universals.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61: 343–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1986. “Against Structural Universals.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64: 2546.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewer, Barry. 1996. “Humean Supervenience.” Philosophical Topics 24: 101–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewer, Barry. 2012. “Two Accounts of Laws and Time.” Philosophical Studies 160: 115–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 1998. The Possibility of Metaphysics: Substance, Identity, and Time. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Maudlin, Tim. 2007. The Metaphysics Within Physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Elizabeth. 2015. “Humean Scientific Explanation.” Philosophical Studies 172: 1311–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mumford, Stephen. 2004. Laws in Nature. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raven, Michael. 2013. “Is Ground a Strict Partial Order?American Philosophical Quarterly 50: 193201.Google Scholar
Raven, Michael. 2015. “Ground.” Philosophy Compass 10: 322–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raven, Michael. Manuscript. “A Problem for Immanent Universals in States of Affairs.” Accessed November 3, 2017.Google Scholar
Rives, Bradley. 2014. “Laws, the Inference Problem, and Uninstantiated Universals.” The Southern Journal of Philosophy 52: 496520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodriguez-Pereyra , Gonzalo. 2015. “Grounding Is Not a Strict Order.” Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1: 517–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosen, Gideon. 2010. “Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Reduction.” In Modality: Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology, edited by Hale, Bob and Hoffmann, Aviv, 109–36. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2008. “Causation and Laws of Nature.” In Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics, edited by Sider, Theodore, Hawthorne, John, and Zimmerman, Dean, 82107. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2009. “On What Grounds What.” In Metametaphysics, edited by Chalmers, David, Manley, David, and Wasserman, Ryan, 347–83. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2010. “Monism: The Priority of the Whole.” The Philosophical Review 119: 3176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2012. “Grounding, Transitivity, and Contrastivity.” In Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality, edited by Correia, Fabrice and Schneider, Benjamin, 122–38. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2016. “It Is the Business of Laws to Govern.” Dialectica 70: 577–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shumener, Erica. 2019. “Laws of Nature, Explanation, and Semantic Circularity.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 70 (3): 787815.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, Theodore. 1992. “Tooley’s Solution to the Inference Problem.” Philosophical Studies 67: 261–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swinburne, Richard. 2006. “Relations between Universals, Or Divine Laws?Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84: 179–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tooley, Michael. 1977. “The Nature of Laws.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7: 667–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tooley, Michael. 1987. Causation: A Realist Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tugby, Matthew. 2013. “Platonic Dispositionalism.” Mind 122: 451–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tugby, Matthew. 2017. “The Problem of Retention.” Synthese 194: 2053–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas. 1989. Laws and Symmetry. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilsch, Tobias. 2018. “Genuine Violations of Laws.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 96: 806–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilsch, Tobias. Manuscript. “Governing Laws of Nature: Guidance and Production.” Accessed May 27 2019.Google Scholar
Wilson, Jessica. 2014. “No Work for a Theory of Grounding.” Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 57: 535–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar