Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T22:46:33.741Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Richard Gaskin, The Unity of the Proposition. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press 2008. Pp. xv + 455.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 December 2019

Bernard Linsky*
Affiliation:
University of Alberta, Edmonton, ABT6G 2E7, Canada

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Critical Notice
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Page references in parentheses without further identification will be to Gaskin.

2 This notion of ‘Linguistic Idealism’ comes out of Gaskin's Experience and the World's Own Language: A Critique of John McDowell's Empiricism (Oxford: Clarendon 2006). Gaskin appreciates how odd this sounds: ‘How, someone might complain, can propositions at the level of reference (whether true or false) both be worldly entities — as they must if they really exist at the level of reference — and also say something?’’ (114).

3 Russell, Bertrand Principles of Mathematics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1903).Google Scholar

4 Linsky, LeonardThe Unity of the Proposition,’ Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (1992): 243–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar The only earlier works he could find, he says, are Anthony, Palmer Concept and Object: The Unity of the Proposition in Logic and Psychology (London and New York: Routledge 1988)Google Scholar and Hylton, PeterThe Nature of the Proposition and the Revolt against Idealism,’ in Philosophy and History, Rorty, R. Schneewind, J.B. and Skinner, Q. eds. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1984).Google Scholar

5 Gibson, Martha From Naming to Saying: The Unity of the Proposition (Oxford: Blackwell 2004),CrossRefGoogle Scholar Davidson, Donald Truth and Predication, (Cambridge, MA: Belknap 2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar and JeffKing, The Nature and Structure of Content (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2007).Google Scholar

6 I am grateful to an anonymous referee for the CJP for pointing out Gibson's book. Consequently, I owe to the referee the observation that neither Gibson nor Davidson believes in propositions as entities, and that perhaps much of the interest in The Problem of the Unity of the Proposition is really in the move from the theory of reference to a theory of the semantics of sentences, whether or not that involves propositions as entities. For most the problem is indeed explaining the difference between a sentence (with truth conditions) and a list of names (which refer).

7 See (L. Linsky, 259): ‘Having acknowledged his inability to solve the problem of the unity of the proposition when it is first presented in Principles, Russell does not return in later publications to make further attempts at a resolution.’

8 Thus in the margin of his copy of Grundgesetze, next to §2, he writes: ‘What is the Sinn of ?2 = 4? This is a most puzzling question’ (Bernard Linsky, ‘Russell's Marginalia in his Copies of Frege's Works,’ Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 24 [2004]: 14).

9 Russell's marginal at the occurrence of the context principle at § 62 is simply a question mark, ‘?’ and otherwise he ignores this allegedly fundamental principle in both the marginal comments and his notes for Appendix A of Principles. (He notices the concept/object distinction when it occurs in the list of four fundamental principles along with the context principle on p. x.) (See B. Linsky ‘Russell's Marginalia’ (2004) above and Bernard Linsky, ‘Russell's Notes on Frege for Appendix A of The Principles of Mathematics,’ Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 25 (2005): 133-72.

10 See the summary of the argument of chapters 3 and 4 on page 258.

11 George Bealer suggested this to me in conversation in response to the presentation of my: ‘From Descriptive Functions to Sets of Ordered Pairs,’ in Reduction — Abstraction — Analysis: Proceedings of the 31st International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium in Kirchberg, 2008, Alexander Hieke and Hannes Leitgeb, eds. (Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag 2009) 259-72.

12 More precisely known as ?-conversion, but this name from Church's original has stuck (The Calculi of Lambda-Conversion [Princeton: Princeton University Press 1941]).

13 See Armstrong, David M. A World of States of Affairs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1997), 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

14 In ‘Demonstratives,’ originally presented in 1970 and hence influential long before its eventual publication in Themes from Kaplan, Almog, Joseph Perry, John and Wettstein, Howard eds. (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1989).Google Scholar (The source of ‘Russellian Propositions’ as a label appears to be the passage on 496: Three paragraphs ago I sketched a metaphysical picture of the structure of a proposition. This picture is taken from the semantical parts of Russell's Principles of Mathematics.’

15 The reader will notice that earlier footnotes suggest both Russell's own attitudes towards these various problems that arose after Principles of Mathematics, and that those problems are distinct. Russsell says that he has no solution to his Problem of the Unity of the Proposition, and I suspect that neither should we.

16 That debate has begun with an excellent book symposium in Dialectica 64 (2010), with a précis of the book by Gaskin, 259-64, comments from William Valicella, 265-77, Manuel García-Carpintero, 279-88, Benjamin Schnieder, 289-301, and then Gaskin's replies to Vallicella, Schnieder, and García-Carpintero, 303-11.