Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T19:27:09.080Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The unity of moral attitudes: recipe semantics and credal exaptation*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Derek Shiller*
Affiliation:
Independent Scholar, New York City, NY, USA

Abstract

This paper offers a noncognitivist characterization of moral attitudes, according to which moral attitudes count as such because of their inclusion of moral concepts. Moral concepts are distinguished by their contribution to the functional roles of some of the attitudes in which they can occur. They have no particular functional role in other attitudes, and should instead be viewed as evolutionary spandrels. In order to make the counter-intuitive implications of the view more palatable, the paper ends with an account of the evolution of normative judgments as exaptations of the cognitive structures that underlie beliefs.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

This paper benefitted from comments by Adam Thompson, Derek Baker, David Faraci, Tristram McPherson, William Melanson, and two anonymous referees, as well as audiences at the Philosopher's Cocoon and Minds Online conferences.

References

Anderson, Michael. 2010. “Neural Reuse: A Fundamental Organizational Principle of the Brain.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33(4): 245266. 10.1017/S0140525X10000853CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ayer, Alfred J. 1936. Language, Truth and Logic. London: Victor Gollancz.Google Scholar
Baker, Derek, and Woods, Jack. 2015. “How Expressivists Can and Should Explain Inconsistency.” Ethics 125(2): 391424. 10.1086/678371CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Björnsson, Gunnar, and McPherson, Tristram. 2014. “Moral Attitudes for Non-Cognitivists: Solving the Specification Problem.” Mind 123(489): 138. 10.1093/mind/fzu031CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, Simon. 1984. Spreading the Word. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Blackburn, Simon. 1988. “Attitudes and Contents.” Ethics 98(3): 501517. 10.1086/292968CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blumson, Ben. 2012. “Mental Maps.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85(2): 413434. 10.1111/phpr.2012.85.issue-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boehm, Christopher. 2012. Moral Origins: The Evolution of Virtue, Altruism, and Shame. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred. 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
d’Errico, Francesco, and Stringer, Chris. 2011. “Evolution, Revolution or Saltation Scenario for the Emergence of Modern Cultures?Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 366(1567): 10601069. 10.1098/rstb.2010.0340CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Field, Hartry. 1978. “Mental Representation.” Erkenntnis 13(1): 961. 10.1007/BF00160888CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry. 1998. Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/0198236360.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry. 2008. Lot 2: The Language of Thought Revisited. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199548774.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry, and Pylyshyn, Zenon. 1988. “Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture.” Cognition 28(1–2): 371. 10.1016/0010-0277(88)90031-5CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Geach, Peter. 1965. “Assertion.” The Philosophical Review 74(4): 449465. 10.2307/2183123CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gibbard, Allan. 2003. Thinking How to Live. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gould, Stephen J., and Vrba, Elisabeth. 1982. “Exaptation – A Missing Term in the Science of Form.” Paleobiology 8(1): 415. 10.1017/S0094837300004310CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henn, Brenna, Cavalli-Sforza, Luigi, and Feldman, Marcus. 2012. “The Great Human Expansion.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 109(44): 1775817764. 10.1073/pnas.1212380109CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Horgan, Terry, and Timmons, Mark. 2006. “Cognitivist Expressivism.” In Metaethics after Moore, edited by Horgan, Terry and Timmons, Mark, 255298. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199269914.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, Terry, and Timmons, Mark. 2009. “Expressivism and Contrary-Forming Negation.” Philosophical Issues 19(1): 92112. 10.1111/phis.2009.19.issue-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, Richard. 2001. The Myth of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9780511487101CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, Richard. 2007. The Evolution of Morality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Klein, Richard. 2008. “Out of Africa and the Evolution of Human Behavior.” Evolutionary Anthropology: Issues, News, and Reviews 17(6): 267281. 10.1002/evan.20181CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackie, John L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Merli, David. 2008. “Expressivism and the Limits of Moral Disagreement.” Journal of Ethics 12(1): 2555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, Ruth. 1984. Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Papineau, David. 1984. “Representation and Explanation.” Philosophy of Science 51(4): 550572. 10.1086/289205CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Powell, Adam, Shennan, Stephan, and Thomas, Mark. 2009. “Late Pleistocene Demography and the Appearance of Modern Human Behavior.” Science 324(5932): 12981301. 10.1126/science.1170165CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pulvermüller, Friedemann. 2002. The Neuroscience of Language: On Brain Circuits of Words and Serial Order. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard V. O. 1960. Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Ridge, Michael. 2014. Impassioned Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199682669.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Rohr, Rudolf, Claudia, Judith Burkart, and van Schaik, Carel. 2011. “Evolutionary Precursors of Social Norms in Chimpanzees: A New Approach.” Biology and Philosophy 26(1): 130. 10.1007/s10539-010-9240-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Roojen, Mark. 1996. “Expressivism and Irrationality.” The Philosophical Review 105(3): 311335. 10.2307/2185703CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, Mark. 2008. Being For: Evaluating the Semantic Program of Expressivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199534654.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, Mark. 2013. “Tempered Expressivism.” In Oxford Studies in Metaethics 8, edited by Shafer-Landau, Russ, 283314. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeter, Laura. 2014. “Normative Concepts: A Connectedness Model.” Philosophers’ Imprint 14(25), 126.Google Scholar
Schwartz, Jeremy, and Hom, Christopher. 2015. “Why the Negation Problem Is Not a Problem for Expressivism.” Noûs 49(4): 824845.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, John. 1962. “Meaning and Speech Acts.” The Philosophical Review 71(4): 423432. 10.2307/2183455CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shiller, Derek. 2016. “A Primitive Solution to the Negation Problem.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 19(3): 725740. 10.1007/s10677-015-9670-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shiller, Derek. 2017. “The Problem of Other Attitudes.” American Philosophical Quarterly 54(2): 141152.Google Scholar
Sinclair, Neil. 2011. “Moral Expressivism and Sentential Negation.” Philosophical Studies 152(3): 385411. 10.1007/s11098-009-9484-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sinclair, Neil. 2012. “Metaethics, Teleosemantics and the Function of Moral Judgements.” Biology and Philosophy 27(5): 639662. 10.1007/s10539-012-9316-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, Kim. 2011. “From Hominins to Humans: How Sapiens Became Behaviourally Modern.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 366(1566): 809822. 10.1098/rstb.2010.0301CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stevenson, Charles L. 1937. “The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms.” Mind 46(181): 1431. 10.1093/mind/XLVI.181.14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, Stephen P. 1983. From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Tomasello, Michael, Melis, Alicia, Tennie, Claudio, Wyman, Emily, and Herrmann, Esther. 2012. “Two Key Steps in the Evolution of Human Cooperation: The Interdependence Hypothesis.” Current Anthropology 53(6): 673692. 10.1086/668207CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomasello, Michael. 2016. A Natural History of Human Morality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 10.4159/9780674915855CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toppinen, Teemu. 2013. “Believing in Expressivism.” In Oxford Studies in Metaethics 8, edited by Shafer-Landau, Russ, 252282. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Unwin, Nicholas. 1999. “Quasi-Realism, Negation and the Frege-Geach Problem.” The Philosophical Quarterly 49(196): 337352. 10.1111/phiq.1999.49.issue-196CrossRefGoogle Scholar