Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T14:47:49.347Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Rescuing the New Natural Law Theory: From Absolute Values to a Theory of Autonomy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 July 2012

Joshua D. Goldstein*
Affiliation:
University of Calgary
*
Joshua D. Goldstein, Department of Political Science, University of Calgary, 2500 University Dr. NW, Calgary AB, T2N 1N4, Joshua.goldstein@ucalgary.ca

Abstract

Abstract. The new natural theory developed by Germain Grisez, John Finnis, Robert George and other new natural lawyers is presented by both its friends and its liberal critics as more concerned with absolute values than theorizing human freedom. This concern is seemingly borne out by the new natural lawyers' narrow and exclusionary sexual ethic. However, this article suggests that the new natural law theory might be rescued from both these groups and shown to contain a robust and attractive account of freedom. Through a reconstruction of the new natural law theory's unique mode of arriving at moral action, this article suggests the new natural law theory integrates three distinct dimensions of autonomy which are often kept separate: a Kantian moral autonomy, a Rawlsian personal autonomy and a Hegelian ethical autonomy. The result is a new natural law theory—and a sexual ethic—more liberating than either the friends or critics of the new natural law theory would seem to allow.

Résumé. La nouvelle théorie de la loi naturelle, développée par Germain Grisez, John Finnis, Robert George et plusieurs autres défenseurs de la nouvelle loi naturelle, est présentée par ses défenseurs et critiques libéraux comme étant plus concernée par les valeurs absolues que par la théorisation de la liberté humaine. Cette préoccupation semble être née de la conception étroite et exclusive que font les théoriciens de la nouvelle loi naturelle de l'éthique sexuelle. Par contre, cet article suggère que la nouvelle théorie de la loi naturelle peut être secourue de ces deux groupes et démontre que la nouvelle loi naturelle contient une description robuste et intéressante du concept de liberté. À travers une reconstruction du mode d'arrivée à l'action morale unique à la nouvelle théorie de la loi naturelle, cet article suggère que la nouvelle théorie de la loi naturelle intègre trois dimensions distinctes de l'autonomie qui sont souvent gardées séparer: l'autonomie morale kantienne, l'autonomie personnelle rawlsienne et l'autonomie éthique hégélienne. Le résultat est une nouvelle théorie de la loi naturelle, et une éthique sexuelle, plus libérée que ce que les défenseurs et critiques de la nouvelle théorie de la loi naturelle semblent permettre.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Political Science Association 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aquinas, Thomas. 1948. Summa Theologica, trans. Province, Fathers of the English Dominican. New York: Benziger Brothers.Google Scholar
Aristotle. 1984. Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Apostle, Hippocrates G.. Grinnell, Iowa: The Peripatetic Press.Google Scholar
Bamforth, Nicholas C. and Richards, David A.J.. 2008. Patriarchal Religion, Sexuality, and Gender: A Critique of New Natural Law. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Berlin, Isaiah. 2005. “Two Concepts of Liberty.” In Liberty, ed. Hardy, Henry. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bradley, Gerald V. and George, Robert. 1994. “The New Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Jean Porter.” American Journal of Jurisprudence 39: 303–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brake, Elizabeth. 2010. “Minimal Marriage: What Political Liberalism Implies for Marriage Law.” Ethics 120: 302–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calhoun, Cheshire. 2005. “Who's Afraid of Polygamous Marriage? Lessons for Same-Sex Marriage Advocacy from the History of Polygamy.” San Diego Law Review 42: 1023–42.Google Scholar
Chappell, Timothy. 2000. “Natural Law Revisited: Natural Law Theory and Contemporary Moral Philosophy.” In The Revival of Natural Law: Philosophical, Theological and Ethical Responses to the Finnis-Grisez School, ed. Biggar, Nigel and Black, Rufus. Burlington VT: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Chartier, Gary. 2007. “Self-Integration as a Basic Good: A Response to Chris Tollefsen.” American Journal of Jurisprudence 52: 293–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, G.A. 2008. Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Corvino, John. 2005. “Homosexuality and the PIB Argument.” Ethics 115: 501–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engster, Daniel. 2004. “Care Ethics and Natural Law Theory: Toward an Institutional Political Theory of Caring.” Journal of Politics 66: 113–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, John. 1980. Natural Law and Natural Rights. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, John. 1983. Fundamentals of Ethics. Washington DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, John. 1991. Moral Absolutes: Tradition, Revision, and Truth. Washington DC: The Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, John. 1993. “Personal Integrity, Sexual Morality and Responsible Parenthood.” In Why Humane Vitae Was Right: A Reader, ed. Smith, Janet E.. San Francisco: Ignatius Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, John. 1994a. “Law, Morality, and ‘Sexual Orientation.’Notre Dame Law Review 69: 1049–76.Google Scholar
Finnis, John. 1994b. “Liberalism and Natural Law Theory.” Mercer Law Review 45: 687704.Google Scholar
Finnis, John. 1997. “The Good of Marriage and the Morality of Sexual Relations: Some Philosophical and Historical Observations.” American Journal of Jurisprudence 42: 97134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, John. 2002. “Natural Law Theory and Limited Government.” In Natural Law, Liberalism, and Morality: Contemporary Essays, ed. George, Robert P.. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, John. 2005. “Foundations of Practical Reason Revisited.” American Journal of Jurisprudence 50: 109–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, John. 2008a. “Reason, Revelation, Universality and Particularity in Ethics.” American Journal of Jurisprudence 53: 2348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, John. 2008b. “Marriage: A Basic and Exigent Good.” Monist 91: 388406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, John. 2011. Reason in Action: Collected Essays, vol I. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garrett, Jeremy R. 2008. “Why the Old Sexual Morality of the New Natural Law Undermines Traditional Marriage.” Social Theory and Practice 34: 591622.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
George, Robert P. 2002. Making Men Moral: Civil Liberties and Public Morality. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
George, Robert P. 2004. “What's Sex Got to Do with It? Marriage, Morality, and Rationality.” American Journal of Jurisprudence 49: 6385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
George, Robert P. and Bradley, Gerard V.. 1995. “Marriage and the Liberal Imagination.” Georgetown Law Journal 84: 301–20.Google Scholar
George, Robert P. and Wolfe, Christopher, ed. 2000. Natural Law and Public Reason. Washington DC: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
Goldstein, Joshua D. 2011. “New Natural Law Theory and the Grounds of Marriage: Friendship and Self-Constitution.” Social Theory and Practice 37: 461–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grisez, Germain. 1997. The Way of the Lord Jesus, vol. 3: Difficult Moral Questions. Quincy Il: Franciscan Press.Google Scholar
Grisez, Germain, Boyle, Joseph and Finnis, John. 1987. “Practical Principles, Moral Truth, and Ultimate Ends.” American Journal of Jurisprudence 32: 99151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grisez, Germain and Shaw, Russell. 1974. Beyond the New Morality: The Responsibilities of Freedom. Notre Dame IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, G.W.F. 1996 [1821]. Elements of the Philosophy of Right, trans. Nisbet, H.B.. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hittinger, Russell. 2008. A Critique of the New Natural Law Theory. Notre Dame IN: Notre Dame University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1981 [1785]. Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Ellington, James W.. Indianapolis IN: Hackett Publishing Co.Google Scholar
Koppelman, Andrew. 1997. “Is Marriage Inherently Heterosexual?American Journal of Jurisprudence 42: 5195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, Patrick and George, Robert P.. 1997. “What Sex Can Be: Self-Alienation, Illusion, or One-Flesh Union.” American Journal of Jurisprudence 42: 135–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, Patrick and George, Robert P.. 2008. Body-Self Dualism in Contemporary Ethics and Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, John. 2003 [1690]. “Two Treatises of Government.” In Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration, ed. Shapiro, Ian. New Haven CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Macedo, Stephen. 1995. “Homosexuality and the Conservative Mind.” Georgetown Law Journal 84: 261300.Google Scholar
Macedo, Stephen. 1997. “Sexuality and Liberty: Making Room for Nature and Tradition?” In Sex, Preference and Family: Essays on Law and Nature, ed. Estlund, David M. and Nussbaum, Martha C.. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Macedo, Stephen. 2002. “Against the Old Sexual Morality of the New Natural Law.” In Natural Law, Liberalism, and Morality, ed. George, Robert P.. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Metz, Tamara. 2007. “The Liberal Case for Disestablishing Marriage.” Contemporary Political Theory 6: 196217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plato. 1991. The Republic, trans. Bloom, Allan. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Plato. 2003. Phaedrus, trans. Scully, Stephen. Newburyport MA: Focus Publishing.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. 1988. The Morality of Freedom. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salzman, Todd A. and Lawler, Michael G.. 2006. “New Natural Law Theory and Foundational Sexual Ethical Principles: A Critique And A Proposal.” The Heythrop Journal 47: 182205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schultz, Janice. 1985. “Is-Ought: Prescribing and a Present Controversy.” Thomist: A Speculative Quarterly Review 49: 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sunstein, Cass and Thaler, Richard. 2008. “Privatizing Marriage.” The Monist 91: 377–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walsh, Francis Michael. 2008. “The Return of the Naturalistic Fallacy: A Dialogue on Human Flourishing.” The Heythrop Journal 49: 370–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weinrib, Lloyd L. 2007. “Natural Law and Rights.” In Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays, ed. George, Robert P.. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar