Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-j824f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-15T02:02:02.873Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Randall's Interpretation of the Aristotelian “Active Intellect”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 June 1971

James R. Horne
Affiliation:
University of Waterloo

Extract

Aristotle's explanation of the “active intellect” in De Anima III, 5 constitutes a problem for us simply because we have to take this philosopher so seriously. If he were a writer given to poetic lapses or mythical adornments to his work we could consider dismissing the whole chapter as unessential. However, we know that Aristotle does not write unessential chapters, and that he is invariably engaged in an attempt to explain his subject fully and systematically, neither adding to it nor leaving anything out.

The De Anima, for example, is an attempt to describe the characteristics of living things, in an ascending order from the basic functions of vegetables to the most abstract thinking by human beings. The activities of nutrition, sensation, common sense, imagination, and movement are presented in Book II and in the early part of Book III.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 1971

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Aristotle, , De Anima, trans. Hett, W. S., (Loeb Classical Library; London: Harvard University Press, 1957), II, 3, p. 415a, 11. 9–12.Google Scholar

2 Ibid., Ill, 5.

3 Burnet, John, “Soul (Greek)”, Encyclopedia of Religion and Ethics, ed. Hastings, James, Selbie, John A., and Gray, Louis H. (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1921), XI, p. 741.Google Scholar

4 Tillich, Paul, Systematic Theology III, (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1963), p. 411.Google Scholar

5 Mure, G. R. G., Aristotle, (New York: Oxford University Press, 1964), pp. 213–14.Google Scholar

6 Ross, W. D., Aristotle, (Cleveland and New York: The World Publishing Company, 1963), p. 146.Google Scholar

7 Aristotle, De Generalione Animalium, trans. Peek, A. L., (Loeb Classical Library: London: Harvard University Press, 1953), II, 3, p. 736b, 1. 28.Google Scholar

8 Aristotle, De Anima, 1, 4, p. 408b, n. 27–33.

9 JrRandall, John H.., Aristotle, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1962), pp. 100103.Google Scholar

10 Randall, op. cit., p. 100.

11 Ibid., p. 99.

12 Ibid., p. 105.

13 Ibid., p. 99.

14 Haring, Ellen S., “A Twentieth Century Aristotle” The Review of Metaphysics (Dec, 1960), Vol. 14,—2g6n.Google Scholar

15 JrRandall, John H.., Nature and Historical Experience, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1958), p. 238Google Scholar. Randall quotes John Dewey, Experience and Nature, (New York: W. W. Norton and Company, Inc., 1929) pp. 166, 167, 174.

16 Randall, Nature and Historical Experience, p. 222.

17 Randall, Aristotle, p. 105.

18 Jaeger, W., Aristotle, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1948), pp. 332–3.Google Scholar

19 Randall, Aristotle, p. 105.

20 Aristotle, Poetics, trans. Bywater, I., in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. McKeon, R., (New York: Random House, 1941), p. 1459a, 11. 5–7.Google Scholar

21 Rist, J. M., “Notes on De Anima 3:5”, Classical Philology, (Jan. 1966) Vol. 61, pp. 820.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

22 Randall, Nature and Historical Experience, pp. 221–2.

23 James, William, The Varieties of Religious Experience, (New York: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1919)Google Scholar, Stace, Walter T., Mysticism and Philosophy, (New York: J. B. Lippincott Company, 1960)Google Scholar, and Zaehner, R. C., Mysticism Sacred and Profane, (New York: Oxford University Press, 1961).Google Scholar

24 William James, op. cit., p. 382.

25 Ramsey, Ian, Religious Language, (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1963). PP. 1154.Google Scholar