Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T14:16:06.305Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Physical-Effect Epiphenomenalism and Common Underlying Causes

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 September 2012

DWAYNE MOORE*
Affiliation:
University of Toronto

Abstract

Qualia epiphenomenalism is the view that qualitative properties of events, such as the raw feel of tastes or painfulness, lack causal efficacy. One common objection to qualia epiphenomenalism is the epistemic argument, which states that this loss of causal efficacy undermines our capacity to know about these epiphenomenal qualitative properties (Sterjnberg, 1999; Watkins, 1989). A number of rejoinders have been offered up to insulate qualia epiphenomenalism from the epistemic argument. In this paper I consider and ultimately reject two such replies, namely, the common underlying cause reply and the appeal to physical-effect epiphenomenalism.

L’épiphénoménalisme des qualia est la thèse voulant que les propriétés qualitatives des événements, comme les sensations de goût ou de douleur, soient dénuées d’efficacité causale. On objecte souvent à cette forme d’épiphénoménalisme l’argument épistémique, selon lequel cette absence d’efficacité causale nous rendrait incapables de connaître ces mêmes propriétés qualitatives épiphénoménales (Sterjnberg, 1999; Watkins, 1989). Plusieurs réponses ont été proposées pour isoler l’épiphénoménalisme des qualia de l’argument épistémique. J’étudie dans cet article, pour finalement les rejeter, deux de ces réponses, soit l’appel à la cause sous-jacente commune (Common Underlying Cause Reply) et l’appel à l’épiphénoménalisme des événements physiques.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Antony, L. 1989Anomalous Monism and the Problem of Explanatory Force”, Philosophical Review 98: 153–87.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. 1978 A Theory of Universals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bailey, A. 2006Zombies, Epiphenomenalism and Physicalist Theories of Consciousness”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36, 4: 481510.Google Scholar
Bennett, K. 2003Why the Exclusion Problem Seems Intractable, and How, Just Maybe, to Tract it”, Noûs 37: 471497.Google Scholar
Bieri, P. 1992Trying Out EpiphenomenalismErkenntnis 36: 283309.Google Scholar
Brewer, B. 1995Mental Causation: Compulsion by Reason”, Aristotelian Society Supplementary 69: 237253.Google Scholar
Broad, C. 1959 The Philosophy of C. D. Broad. Schilpp, P. (ed.) Tudor Publishing.Google Scholar
Burge, T. 1993Mind Body Causation and Explanation”, Mental Causation, Heil, J. and Mele, A. (eds.) Oxford: Clarendon Press: 97120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Butler, J. 2011Introspective Knowledge of Experience and Its Role in Consciousness Studies”, Journal of Consciousness Studies 18, 2: 128145.Google Scholar
Campbell, N. 2003An Inconsistency in the Knowledge Argument”, Erkenntnis 58: 261–66.Google Scholar
Campbell, N. 2011Reply to Nagasawa on the Inconsistency Objection to the Knowledge Argument”, Erkenntnis online first.Google Scholar
Cavedon-Taylor, D. 2008Still Epiphenominal Qualia”, Philosophia 37, 1: 105107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. 1996 The Conscious Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. 2003The Content and Epistemology of Phenomenal Belief”, Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives, Smith, Q. and Jokic, A. (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press: 220272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dancy, J. 1985 An Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1978Current Issues in the Philosophy of Mind”, American Philosophical Quarterly 15: 249261Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1991 Consciousness Explained. Little, Brown and Company: Boston.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1988 Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes, Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1987 Psychosemantics, Cambridge: The MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1989Making Mind Matter More”, Philosophical Topics 17, 1: 5979.Google Scholar
Fricker, E. 1993The Threat of Eliminativism”, Mind and Language 8, 2: 254281.Google Scholar
Hutto, D. 1999A Cause For Concern”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59, 2: 381401.Google Scholar
Gadenne, V. 2006In Defense of Qualia Epiphenomenalism”, Journal of Consciousness Studies 13, 1-2: 101114.Google Scholar
Gertler, B. 2001Introspecting Phenomenal States”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63, 2: 305328.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. 1987Supervenient Qualia”, Philosophical Review 96: 491520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hyslop, A. 1998Methodological EpiphenomenalismAustralasian Journal of Philosophy 76, 1: 6170.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1982Epiphenomenal Qualia”, Philosophical Quarterly 32: 127–36.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1986What Mary Didn’t Know”. The Journal of Philosophy 83: 291295.Google Scholar
Kirk, R. 2008The Inconceivability of Zombies”, Philosophical Studies 139: 7389.Google Scholar
Kim, J. 2005 Physicalism, or Something Near Enough. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Loewer, B. 2002Comments on Jaegwon Kim’s Mind and the Physical World”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 655662.Google Scholar
Martin, M. 1993The Rational Role of Experience”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series 93: 7188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLaughlin, B. 1994Epiphenomenalism”, A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, Guttenplan, S. (ed.). Oxford: Blackwell: 277288.Google Scholar
Medlin, B. 1967Ryle and the Mechanical Hypothesis” in Presley, C. F. (ed.), The Identity Theory of Mind. (Brisbane: University of Queensland Press: 110-111.Google Scholar
Muller, H. 2008Why Qualia are Not Epiphenomenal”, Ratio 21: 8590.Google Scholar
Muller, H. 2009More Troubles for EpiphenomenalismPhilosophia 37: 109112Google Scholar
Nagasawa, Y. 2010The Knowledge Argument and Epiphenomenalism”, Erkenntnis 72: 3756.Google Scholar
Pauen, M. 2000Painless Pain: Property Dualism and the Causal Role of Phenomenal Consciousness”, American Philosophical Quarterly 37: 5164.Google Scholar
Pauen, M. 2006Feeling Causes”, Journal of Consciousness Studies 13, 1: 129152.Google Scholar
Place, U. T. 1988Thirty Years On—Is Consciousness Still a Brain Process”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66, 2: 208219.Google Scholar
Pritchard, D. 2005 Epistemic Luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Robinson, W. 2004 Understanding Phenomenal Consciousness, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, W. 2006Knowing Epiphenomena”, Journal of Consciousness Studies 13, 1-2: 85100.Google Scholar
Robinson, W. 2011Epiphenomenalism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Zalta, E. (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epiphenomenalism/#SelStuGoogle Scholar
Searle, J. 2003 The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Staudacher, A. 2006Epistemological Challenges to Qualia-Epiphenomenalism”, Journal of Consciousness Studies 13, 1: 153175.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 2011Could Anyone Justifiably Believe Epiphenomenalism?Journal of Consciousness Studies 18, 3-4: 196216.Google Scholar
Tammelleo, S. 2008A Limited Defense of Epiphenomenalism”, South African Journal of Philosophy 27: 4051CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walter, S. 2007Epiphenomenalism”. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fieser, James and Dowden, Bradley (eds.), http://www.iep.utm.edu/epipheno/Google Scholar
Watkins, M. 1989The Knowledge Argument Against the Knowledge Argument”, Analysis 49: 158–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar