Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T07:58:02.327Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

From Modern Roots to Postmodern Rhizomes

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2024

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

It has been commonplace to maintain of the phenomenon that occurred during classical times, the change from relying on myth to trusting in reason: (1) that the emergence of philosophy from myth was marked by an abrupt discontinuity; (2) that mythical thinking was left behind once philosophy was invented or discovered; and (3) that the ancient Greeks were the agents of this miracle. This paper suggests that the so-called “Greek miracle” was, in fact, a miracle manqué and, more importantly, that close examination of this failed miracle offers valuable insight into the philosophical crisis facing the world today.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1993 Fédération Internationale des Sociétés de Philosophie / International Federation of Philosophical Societies (FISP)

References

Barth, J. 1984. “The Literature of Exhaustion,” The Friday Book New York: G.P. Putnam's Sons.Google Scholar
Barthes, R. 1977. “From Work to Text,” Image, Music, Text New York: Hill and Wang.Google Scholar
Borges, J.L. 1983. Labyrinths New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Bohm, D. 1980. Wholeness and the Implicate Order. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1986. Law's Empire. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. 1970. The Order of Things. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Fuller, S. 1989. Philosophy of Science and Its Discontents. Boulder, Colo.: Westview.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H-G. 1985. Truth and Method. New York: Crossroad.Google Scholar
Gleick, J. 1977. Chaos: Making a New Science. New York: Crossroad.Google Scholar
Guthrie, W.K.C. 1960. The Greek Philosophers. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Jaeger, W. 1967. The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kirk, G.S. 1974. The Nature of Greek Myths. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, A. 1988. Whose Justice? Which Rationality? Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Malinowski, B. 1955. “Myth in Primitive Psychology,” Magic, Science and Religion. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Margolis, J. 1989. Texts Without Referents. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, Ltd.Google Scholar
Morford, M.P.O. and Lenardon, R.J.. 1985. Classical Mythology. New York: Longman.Google Scholar
Nicolis, G. & Prigogine, I.. 1989. Exploring Complexity. New York: Freeman.Google Scholar
Popper, K. 1958. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York: Harper.Google Scholar
Prigogine, I. & Stengers, I.. 1984. Order Out of Chaos. New York: Bantam.Google Scholar
Quine, W.V.O. 1970. The Web of Belief. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1977. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, R., 1980. “A Reply to Dreyfus and Taylor,” The Review of Metaphysics 34:3946.Google Scholar
Rorty, R., 1989. Irony, Contingency and Solidarity Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sinos, D. 1989. Lecture, Prince George's Community College.Google Scholar
Toulmin, S. (1990) Cosmopolis New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1961) Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L., 1969. Philosophical Investigations. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar