We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
An abstract is not available for this content so a preview has been provided. Please use the Get access link above for information on how to access this content.
Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)
Carnap, R (1956) Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. In Carnap, Meaning and Necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 205–221.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P (1962) Explanation, reduction, and empiricism. In Feigl, H, Maxwell, G (eds), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science iii,. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 28–97.Google Scholar
Franklin, A (2001) Are There Really Neutrinos? An Evidential History. Cambridge, MA: Perseus.Google Scholar
Goodman, N (1955) Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Cambridge, ma: Harvard up.Google Scholar
Greenwood, J (1990) Two dogmas of neo-empiricism. Philosophy of Science57: 553–574.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gutting, G (2009) What Philosophers Know. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanson, NR (1958) Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.Google Scholar
Hardwig, J (1991) The role of trust in knowledge. Journal of Philosophy88: 693–708.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C (1945) Studies in the logic of confirmation. Mind54: 1–26, 97–121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaptchuk, T (1998) Intentional ignorance: a history of blind assessment and placebo controls in medicine. Bulletin of the History of Medicine72: 389–433.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kuhn, TS (1962) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, TS (2000) The Road Since Structure. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Polanyi, M (1958) Personal Knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Price, HH (1940) The permanent significance of Hume's philosophy. Philosophy15: 7–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H (1962) The analytic and the synthetic. In Feigl, H, Maxwell, G (eds), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science iii. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 358–397Google Scholar
Quine, WV (1951) Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review60: 20–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W (1948) Concepts as involving laws and inconceivable without them. Philosophy of Science15: 287–315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar