Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-13T07:48:51.186Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

ELLSBERG’S PARADOX AND THE VALUE OF CHANCES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 December 2015

Richard Bradley*
Affiliation:
London School of Economics and Political Science, Houghton Street, London WC2A 2AE, UK. Email: r.bradley@lse.ac.uk. URL: http://personal.lse.ac.uk/bradleyr/

Abstract:

What value should we put on our chances of obtaining a good? This paper argues that, contrary to the widely accepted theory of von Neumann and Morgenstern, the value of a chance of some good G may be a non-linear function of the value of G. In particular, chances may have diminishing marginal utility, a property that is termed chance uncertainty aversion. The hypothesis that agents are averse to uncertainy about chances explains a pattern of preferences often observed in the Ellsberg paradox. While these preferences have typically been taken to refute Bayesian decision theory, it is shown that chance risk aversion is perfectly compatible with it.

Type
Symposium on Rational Choice and Philosophy
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abdellaoui, M., Vossmann, F. and Weber, M.. 2005. Choice-based elicitation and decomposition of decision weights for gains and losses under uncertainty. Management Science 51: 13841399.Google Scholar
Anscombe, F. and Aumann, R.. 1963. A definition of subjective probability. Annals of Mathematical Statistics 34: 199205.Google Scholar
Chakravarty, S. and Roy, J.. 2009. Recursive expected utility and the separation of attitudes towards risk and ambiguity: an experimental study. Theory and Decision 66: 199228.Google Scholar
Ellsberg, D. 1961. Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics 75: 643669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, L. 2010. A paradox for the “smooth ambiguity” model of preference. Econometrica 78: 20852099.Google Scholar
Ergin, H. and Gul, F.. 2009. A theory of subjective compound lotteries. Journal of Economic Theory 144: 899929.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machina, M. 2011. Event-separability in the Ellsberg urn. Economic Theory 48: 425436.Google Scholar
Machina, M. and Schmeidler, D.. 1992. A more robust definition of subjective probability. Econometrica 60: 745780.Google Scholar
Klibanoff, P., Marinacci, M. and Mukerji, S.. 2005. A smooth model of decision making under ambiguity. Econometrica 73: 18491892.Google Scholar
Klibanoff, P., Marinacci, M. and Mukerji, S.. 2012. On the smooth ambiguity model: a reply. Econometrica 80: 13031321.Google Scholar
Schmeidler, D. 1989. Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica 57: 571587.Google Scholar
Segal, U. 1990. Two-stage lotteries without the reduction axiom. Econometrica 58: 349377.Google Scholar
Seo, K. 2009. Ambiguity and second-order belief. Econometrica 77: 15751605.Google Scholar
Stefánsson, H. and Bradley, R.. 2015. How valuable are chances? Philosophy of Science 82: 602625.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trautmann, S. and van de Kuilen, G.. Forthcoming. Ambiguity attitudes. In The Wiley-Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making, Volume 1, ed. Keren, G. and Wu, G.. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Trautmann, S. T., Vieider, F. M. and Wakker, P. P.. 2011. Preference reversals for ambiguity aversion. Management Science 57: 13201333.Google Scholar
von Neumann, J. and Morgenstern, O.. (2007 [1944]). Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wakker, P. 2010. Prospect Theory: For Risk and Uncertainty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar