Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T14:46:18.888Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

In defence of revealed preference theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 May 2020

Johanna Thoma*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Logic and Scientific Method, London School of Economics and Political Science, Houghton Street, LondonWC2A 2AE, UK

Abstract

This paper defends revealed preference theory against a pervasive line of criticism, according to which revealed preference methodology relies on appealing to some mental states, in particular an agent’s beliefs, rendering the project incoherent or unmotivated. I argue that all that is established by these arguments is that revealed preference theorists must accept a limited mentalism in their account of the options an agent should be modelled as choosing between. This is consistent both with an essentially behavioural interpretation of preference and with standard revealed preference methodology. And it does not undermine the core motivations of revealed preference theory.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Afriat, S.N. 1967. The construction of utility functions from expenditure data. International Economic Review 8(1), 6777.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Afriat, S.N. 1973. On a system of inequalities in demand analysis: an extension of the classical method. International Economic Review 14, 460472.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Akerlof, G. 1970. The market for ‘lemons’: quality uncertainty and the market mechanism. Quarterly Journal of Economics 84(3), 488500.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Angner, E. 2018. What preferences really are. Philosophy of Science 85(4), 660681.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, T. and Pesaran, M., eds. 1990. Disaggregation in Econometric Modelling. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Barseghyan, L., Molinari, F., O’Donoghue, T. and Teitelbaum, J.C. 2013. The nature of risk preferences: evidence from insurance choices. American Economic Review 103(6), 24992529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Becker, G.S. and Murphy, K.M. 1988. A theory of rational addiction. Journal of Political Economy 96(4), 675700.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bermudez, J.L. 2009. Decision Theory and Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernheim, D. and Rangel, A. 2008. Choice-theoretic foundations for behavioral welfare economics. In The Foundations of Positive and Normative Economics, ed. Schotter, A. and Caplin, A., 155192. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Binmore, K. 2008. Rational Decisions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blundell, R.W., Browning, M. and Crawford, I.A. 2003. Nonparametric Engel curves and revealed preference. Econometrica 71(1), 205240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Border, K.C. 1992. Revealed preference, stochastic dominance, and the expected utility hypothesis. Journal of Economic Theory 56(1), 2042.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bossert, W. and Suzumura, K. 2012. Revealed preference and choice under uncertainty. SERIEs 3(1–2), 247258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, J. and Krupnick, A. 2009. The definition and choice of environmental commodities for nonmarket valuation. Discussion paper RFF-DP 09-35. Washington, DC: Resources for the Future.Google Scholar
Bradley, R. 2017. Decision Theory with a Human Face. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carson, R.T. 1998. Valuation of tropical rain forests: philosophical and practical issues in the use of contingent valuation. Ecological Economics 24, 1529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chambers, C.P. and Echenique, F. 2016. Revealed Preference Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, C. 2016. Preferences and positivist methodology in economics. Philosophy of Science 83(2), 192212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, A. and Einav, L. 2007. Estimating risk preferences from deductible choice. American Economic Review 97(3), 745788.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, C. and Alexandrova, A. 2008. No revolution necessary: neural mechanisms for economics. Economics and Philosophy 24(3), 381406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dietrich, F. and List, C. 2016. Mentalism versus behaviourism in economics: a philosophy-of-science perspective. Economics and Philosophy 32(2), 249281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dreier, J. 1996. Rational preference: decision theory as a theory of practical rationality. Theory and Decision 40(3), 249276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Echenique, F. and Saito, K. 2015. Savage in the market. Econometrica 83(4), 14671495.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fogarty, J. 2010. The demand for beer, wine and spirits: a survey of the literature. Journal of Economic Surveys 24(3), 428478.Google Scholar
Gilboa, I. 2009. Theory of Decision under Uncertainty. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilboa, I., Postlewaite, A., Samuelson, L. and Schmeidler, D. 2014. Economic models as analogies. The Economic Journal 124(578), 513533.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, E.J. and Osband, K. 1991. A revealed preference theory of expected utility. Review of Economic Studies 58(4), 677695.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, R.C. and Srivastava, S. 1986. Expected utility maximization and demand behavior. Journal of Economic Theory 38(2), 313323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guala, F. 2019. Preferences: neither behavioural nor mental. Economics and Philosophy 35(3), 383401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gul, F. and Pesendorfer, W. 2008. The case for mindless eonomics. In The Foundations of Positive and Normative Economics, ed. Caplin, A. and Schotter, A.. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hands, D.W. 2013. Foundations of contemporary revealed preference theory. Erkenntnis 78, 10811108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, G.W. and Ross, D. 2018. Varieties of paternalism and the heterogeneity of utility structures. Journal of Economic Methodology 25(1), 4267.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, J. 1977. On the rationale of the Bayesian approach: comments on Professor Watkins’s paper. In Foundational Problems in the Special Sciences, ed. Butts, R. and Hintikka, J.. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing.Google Scholar
Hausman, D. 2000. Revealed preference, belief, and game theory. Economics and Philosophy 16(1), 99115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. 2012. Preference, Value, Choice, and Welfare. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Houthakker, H.S. 1950. Revealed preference and the utility function. Economia 17, 159174.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. 1999. The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jullien, B. and Salanié, B. 2000. Estimating preferences under risk: the case of racetrack bettors. Journal of Political Economy 108(3), 503530.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagel, J.H., Battalio, R.C. and Green, L. 1995. Economic Choice Theory: An Experimental Analysis of Animal Behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, T. 1996. Revealed preference theory on the choice of lotteries. Journal of Mathematical Economics 26(4), 463477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Little, I. 1949. A reformulation of the theory of consumer’s behaviour. Oxford Economic Papers 1(1), 9099.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luce, R.D. and Raiffa, H. 1957. Games and Decisions: Introduction and Critical Survey. New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Maher, P. 1993. Betting on Theories. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mas-Colell, A., Whinston, M. and Green, J. 1995. Microeconomic Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. 1991. Decision theory and folk psychology. In Foundations of Decision Theory: Issues and Advances, ed. Bacharach, M. and Hurley, S., 147175. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, A. 1992. Economics: Mathematical Politics or Science of Diminishing Returns? Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ross, D. 2011. Estranged parents and a schizophrenic child: choice in economics, psychology and neuroeconomics. Journal of Economic Methodology 18(3), 217231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samuelson, P. 1938. A note on the pure theory of consumer’s behaviour. Econometrica 5(17), 6171.Google Scholar
Savage, L. 1972. The Foundations of Statistics (2nd revised edn). New York, NY: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
Sugden, R. 2000. Credible worlds: the status of theoretical models in economics. Journal of Economic Methodology 7(1), 131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. 2009. Credible worlds, capacities and mechanisms. Erkenntnis 70(1), 327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thoma, J. 2020. Folk psychology and the interpretation of decision theory. Ergo.Google Scholar
Varian, H. 1982. The nonparametric approach to demand analysis. Econometrica 50(4), 945974.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Neumann, J. and Morgenstern, O. 1944. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar