Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T05:56:05.916Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

UTILITARIANISM AND PRIORITARIANISM I

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 December 2006

DAVID McCARTHY*
Affiliation:
University of Edinburgh

Abstract

Utilitarianism and prioritarianism make a strong assumption about measures of how good lotteries over histories are for individuals, or for short, individual goodness measures. Given some idealizing assumptions about interpersonal and intrapersonal comparisons, they presuppose that any individual goodness measure can be transformed into any other individual goodness measure by a positive affine transformation. But it is far from obvious that the presupposition is correct, so both theories face the threat of presupposition failure. The usual response to this problem starts by assuming that what implicitly determines the set of individual goodness measures is independent of our discourse about utilitarianism and prioritarianism. I suggest reversing this response. What determines the set of individual goodness measures just is the body of platitudes we accept about utilitarianism and prioritarianism. This approach vindicates the utilitarian and prioritarian presupposition. As a corollary, it shows that individual goodness measures are expectational, and provides an answer to an argument due to Broome that for different reasons to do with measurement, prioritarianism is more or less meaningless.

Type
Essay
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I owe far more than the usual debt of gratitude to John Broome, Wlodek Rabinowicz and Peter Vallentyne for extensive comments and advice about this and related work. Their generosity has been remarkable. I have also benefited greatly from comments by Bertil Tungodden and two anonymous referees. Support for this project was provided by the Arts and Humanities Research Council, and also by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation, the Federal Ministry of Education and Research and the Program for the Investment in the Future of the German Government through a Sofja Kovalevskaja Award in the form of a Visiting Fellowship at the Philosophy, Probability and Modeling Group at the University of Konstanz.

References

REFERENCES

Aczél, J. and Dhombres, J.. 1989. Functional equations in several variables. Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, J. 1990–91. Fairness. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91:87102CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, J. 1991. Weighing goods. BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Broome, J. 2004. Weighing lives. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Coulhon, T. and Mongin, P.. 1989. Social choice theory in the case of von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities. Social Choice and Welfare 6:175–87Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1984. Radical interpretation. In Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Diamond, P. 1967. Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons of utility: comment. Journal of Political Economy 75:765–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hammond, P. 1981. Ex-ante and ex-post welfare optimality under uncertainty. Economica 48:235–50Google Scholar
Hammond, P. 1991. Interpersonal comparisons of utility: why and how they are and should be made. In Interpersonal comparisons of well being, ed. Elster, J. and Roemer, J.. Cambridge University Press:200–54Google Scholar
Harsanyi, J. 1955. Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons of utility. Journal of Political Economy 63:309–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jensen, K. K. 1995. Measuring the size of a benefit and its moral weight. Theoria 61:2560Google Scholar
Jensen, K. K. 2003. What is the difference between (moderate) egalitarianism and prioritarianism? Economics and Philosophy 19:89109CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamm, F. 1993. Morality, mortality. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. 1970. How to define theoretical terms. Journal of Philosophy 67:427–46Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1974. Radical interpretation. Synthese 23:331–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. 1983. New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61:343–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCarthy, D. Forthcoming. Measuring life's goodness. Philosophical BooksGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D. 1991. Equality or priority? Lindley Lectures, University of KansasGoogle Scholar
Rabinowicz, W. 2002. Prioritarianism for prospects Utilitas 14:221Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1971. A theory of justice. Harvard University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samuelson, P. 1952. Probability, utility, and the independence axiom. Econometrica 20:670–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. 1976. Welfare inequalities and Rawlsian axiomatics. Theory and Decision 7:243–62Google Scholar
Sen, A. 1977. Non-linear social welfare functions: a reply to Professor Harsanyi. In Foundational problems in the special sciences, ed. Butts, R. and Hintikka, J.. Reidel:297302Google Scholar
Sen, A. 1986. Social choice theory. In Handbook of mathematical economics, ed. Arrow, K. and Intriligator, M.. Amsterdam, North Holland. 3:1073–81Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. 1966. Singular terms, truth-value gaps, and free logic. Journal of Philosophy 63:481–95Google Scholar
Wakker, P. 1989. Additive Representations of Preferences. KluwerCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weymark, J. 1991. A reconsideration of the Harsanyi-Sen debate on utilitarianism. In Interpersonal comparisons of well being, ed. Elster, J. and Roemer, J.. Cambridge University Press: 255320Google Scholar