Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-4rdpn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T12:36:57.474Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Knowledge and Social Roles: A Virtue Approach

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 January 2012

Abstract

Attributor contextualism and subject-sensitive invariantism both suggest ways in which our concept of knowledge depends on a context. Both offer approaches that incorporate traditionally non-epistemic elements into our standards for knowledge. But neither can account for the fact that the social role of a subject affects the standards that the subject must meet in order to warrant a knowledge attribution. I illustrate the dependence of the standards for knowledge on the social roles of the knower with three types of examples–focusing on knowledge attribution, action, and a mix of the two–and show why neither attributor contextualism nor subject-sensitive invariantism can explain them. I then suggest that subject-sensitive invariantism should be supplemented with insights from virtue epistemology so that it can explain the dependence of the standards of knowledge on social roles. This supplementation of subject-sensitive invariantism helps to solve a persistent problem facing that theory: the case of knowledge attributions made by those in high-stakes contexts about subjects in low-stakes contexts.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Axtell, Guy. 1998. “The Role of the Intellectual Virtues in the Reunification of Epistemology.” The Monist 81: 488508.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bach, Kent. 2008. “Applying Pragmatics to Epistemology.” Philosophical Issues 18: 6888.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Code, Lorraine. 1987. Epistemic Responsibility. Hanover, NH: University Press of New England.Google Scholar
Code, Lorraine. 2006. Ecological Thinking: The Politics of Epistemic Location. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Stewart. 1988. “How to Be a Fallibilist.” Philosophical Perspectives 2: 91123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Stewart. 1998. “Contextualist Solutions to Epistemological Problems: Scepticism, Gettier, and the Lottery.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76(2): 289306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Stewart. 1999. “Contextualism, Skepticism, and the Structure of Reasons.” Philosophical Perspectives: Epistemology 13: 5789.Google Scholar
Craig, Edward. 1990. Knowledge and the State of Nature: An Essay in Conceptual Synthesis. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
DeRose, Keith. 1995. “Solving the Skeptical Problem.” Philosophical Review 104(1): 152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeRose, Keith. 1999. “Contextualism: An Explanation and a Defense.” In Greco, J. and Sosa, E. (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology, pp. 187205. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
DeRose, Keith. 2002. “Assertion, Knowledge, and Context.” Philosophical Review 111: 167203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeRose, Keith. 2004. “The Problem with Subject-Sensitive Invariantism.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48(2): 346–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeRose, Keith. 2005. “The Ordinary Language Basis for Contextualism, and the New Invariantism.” The Philosophical Quarterly 55: 172–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epictetus, . 1995. The Discourses, the Handbook, Fragments of Epictetus. Gill, C. (ed.), Hard, R. (trans.). London: Everyman.Google Scholar
Fantl, Jeremy and Matthew, McGrath. 2009. Knowledge in an Uncertain World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greco, John. 2008. “What's Wrong with Contextualism?The Philosophical Quarterly 58: 416–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, John. 2004. Knowledge and Lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Henderson, David. 2009. “Motivated Contextualism.” Philosophical Studies 142: 119–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David. 1996. “Elusive Knowledge.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74(4): 549–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, Duncan. 2002. “Two Forms of Epistemological Contextualism.” Grazer Philosophische Studien 64: 1955.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanley, Jason. 2005. Knowledge and Practical Interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Michael. 1992. Unnatural Doubts: Epistemological Realism and the Basis of Scepticism. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Williams, Michael. 1999. “Skepticism.” In Greco, J. and Sosa, E. (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology, pp. 3569. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Williams, Michael. 2004. “Scepticism and the Context of Philosophy.” Philosophical Issues 14: 456–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, Sarah. 2010. “Virtues, Social Roles, and Contextualism.” Metaphilosophy 41: 95114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda. 1996. Virtues of the Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar