Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T08:55:45.285Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Nuclear terrorism and virtual risk: Implications for prediction and the utility of models

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 May 2017

Robert J. Downes
Affiliation:
Department of War Studies, King’s College London
Christopher Hobbs
Affiliation:
Department of War Studies, King’s College London

Abstract

Assessing the risk of nuclear terrorism is a challenging task due to the diversity of actors involved, variety of pathways to success, range of defensive measures employed, and the lack of detailed historical record upon which to base analysis. Numerical models developed to date vary wildly in both approach and ultimate assessment: estimates of the likelihood a nuclear terrorist attack differ by up to nine orders of magnitude. This article critiques existing efforts from the standpoint of probability theory, and proposes an alternative perspective on the utility of risk assessment in this area. Nuclear terrorism is argued to be a ‘virtual risk’ for which it is not possible to meaningfully ascribe a quantitative measure, making numerical estimates of the likelihood of nuclear terrorism misleading. Instead, we argue that focus should be placed on utilising models to identify areas of disagreement as targets for further research, with greater emphasis on understanding terrorist decision-making and adaption in response to nuclear security measures.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© British International Studies Association 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

Author’s email: robert.downes@kcl.ac.uk

**

Author’s email: christopher.hobbs@kcl.ac.uk

References

1 Sharon Squassoni, ‘Outcomes from the 2014 Nuclear Security Summit’, Centre for Strategic and International Studies Critical Questions (25 March 2014), available at: http://csis.org/publication/outcomes-2014-nuclear-security-summit} accessed 1 July 2016.

2 NTI Nuclear Security Index, ‘Nuclear Threat Initiative’, available at: {http://ntiindex.org/} accessed 10 February 2016.

3 Porter, Theodore M., Trust in Numbers: The Pursuit of Objectivity in Science and Public Life (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995)Google Scholar, ch. 4.

4 Mueller, John, ‘The Atomic Terrorist: Assessing the Likelihood’, conference paper, Program on International Security (University of Chicago, 2008), p. 14 Google Scholar; Allison, Graham T., Nuclear Terrorism: The Ultimate Preventable Catastrophe (London: Macmillan, 2004), p. 15 Google Scholar.

5 Silver, Nate, ‘Crunching the risk numbers’, Wall Street Journal (8 January 2010)Google Scholar; Allison, Graham T., ‘Nuclear attack a worst-case reality?’, The Washington Times (23 April 2008)Google Scholar; Crowley, Michael, ‘Yes, Obama really is worried about a Manhattan nuke’, Time (26 March 2014)Google Scholar.

6 Kaplan, Stanley and Garrick, B. John, ‘On the quantitative definition of risk’, Risk Analysis, 1 (1981), pp. 1127 Google Scholar.

7 Many potential hazards may fall outside the ambit of our collective knowledge resulting in so-called Black Swan events, as discussed by Nassim Taleb in his book of the same name. See Taleb, Nassim Nicholas, The Black Swan: The Impact of the Highly Improbable (London: Peguin, 2008)Google Scholar.

8 Zimmerman, Peter D. and Lewis, Jeffrey G., ‘The bomb in the backyard’, Foreign Policy (16 October 2009), available at: {http://foreignpolicy.com/2009/10/16/the-bomb-in-the-backyard/} accessed 1 July 2016Google Scholar.

9 Ferguson, Charles D. and Potter, William C., The Four Faces of Nuclear Terrorism (London: Routledge, 2005), p. 5 Google Scholar.

10 Mathematically, this formulation presents risk as the ‘expected consequence’ of the hazard.

11 Anthony (Tony) Cox, Louis , Jr, ‘Some limitations of “Risk = Threat x Vulnerability x Consequence” for risk analysis of terrorist attacks’, Risk Analysis, 28 (2008), pp. 17491761 Google Scholar.

12 While consequence analysis typically focuses on a single impact measure, such as economic damage expressed in dollars lost, there is increasing acknowledgement that impacts are multidimensional and should therefore be addressed in such terms. See, for instance, Frey, Bruno S., Luechinger, Simon, and Stutzer, Alois, ‘Calculating tragedy: Assessing the costs of terrorism’, Journal of Economic Surveys, 21 (2007), pp. 124 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Everitt, B. S. and Skrondal, A., The Cambridge Dictionary of Statistics (4th edn, Cambridge University Press, 2010), p. 174 Google Scholar; Háyek, Alan, ‘“Mises redux” – redux: Fifteen arguments against finite Frequentism’, Erkenntnis, 45 (1996), pp. 209227 Google Scholar. Note that our designation of Frequentist probability could, more properly, be referred to as finite Frequentist probability. This approach demonstrates a wide range of mathematical and philosophical problems as an interpretation of probability despite its numerous enticements.

14 Ibid.

15 Williams, Alan F. and Shabanova, Veronika I., ‘Responsibility of drivers, by age and gender, for motor-vehicle crash deaths’, Journal of Safety Research, 34 (2003), p. 527 Google Scholar.

16 Porter, Trust in Numbers, ch. 4.

17 In the context of Bayesian Probability, the same observation can be applied to the generation of the prior probability distribution, although there are guiding principles that can be applied in this case such as the Jeffreys Prior, see Lindley, D. V., ‘The use of prior probability distributions in statistical inference and decisions’, Proceedings of the Fourth Berkeley Symposium on Mathematical Statistics and Probability (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1961), pp. 453468 Google Scholar.

18 Bedford, Tim and Cooke, Roger, Probabilistic Risk Analysis: Foundations and Methods (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001)Google Scholar, ch. 10.

19 Winkler, Robert L. and Murphy, Allan H., ‘“Good” probability assessors’, Journal of Applied Meteorology, 7 (1968), p. 751 Google Scholar.

20 Apostolakis, George, ‘The concept of probability in safety assessment of technological systems’, Science, 250 (1990), p. 1359 Google Scholar.

21 Talbott, William, ‘Bayesian Epistemology’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter (2016)Google Scholar.

22 Matthews, Robert A. J., ‘Fact Versus Fiction: The Use and Abuse of Subjectivity in Scientific Research’, European Science and Environment Forum Working Paper, No. 2 (1998)Google Scholar.

23 Aven, Terje, Renn, Ortwin, and Rosa, Eugene A., ‘On the ontological status of the concept of risk’, Safety Science, 49 (2011), p. 1077 Google Scholar.

24 Goldstein, Michael, ‘Subjective Bayesian analysis: Principles and practice’, Bayesian Analysis, 1 (2006), p. 408 Google Scholar.

25 Kahneman, Daniel and Tversky, Amos, ‘Subjective probability: a judgement of representativeness’, in C.-A. Staël von Holstein (ed.), The Concept of Probability in Psychological Experiments (Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1974), p. 44 Google Scholar, emphasis added.

26 Kaplan and Garrick, ‘On the quantitative definition of risk’, p. 18.

27 Ibid.

28 Winkler and Murphy, ‘“Good” probability assessors’, p. 752.

29 Ibid.

30 Bedford and Cooke, Probabilistic Risk Analysis, pp. 191–217.

31 An alternative name for the knowledge gap could be epistemic goodness, the extent to which relevant knowledge about the hazard or scenario under consideration is knowable.

32 Briggs, Andrew H., Goeree, Ron, Blackhouse, Gord, and O’Brien, Bernie J., ‘Probabilistic analysis of cost-effectiveness models: Choosing between treatment strategies for gastroesophageal reflux disease’, Medical Decision Making, 22 (2002), p. 291 Google ScholarPubMed; Dewan, Naresh A., Shehan, Christopher J., Reeb, Steven D., Gobar, Lisa S., Scott, Walter J., and Ryschon, Kay, ‘Likelihood of malignancy in a solitary pulmonary nodule: Comparison of Bayesian analysis and results of FDG-PET scan’, Chest, 112 (1997), pp. 416422 Google Scholar.

33 Clauset, Aaron, Young, Maxwell, and Gleditsch, Kristian S., ‘On the frequency of severe terrorist events’, Journal of Conflict Resolution, 51 (2007), pp. 5887 Google Scholar.

34 Ibid., p. 64.

35 Willis, Henry H., LaTourrette, Tom, Kelly, Terrence K., Hickey, Scot, and Neill, Samuel, Terrorism Risk Modeling for Intelligence Analysis and Infrastructure Protection (RAND, 2007), p. 5 Google Scholar.

36 Ibid.

37 Ibid.

38 Adams, John, ‘Risk and morality: Three framing devices’, in Richard Victor Ericson and Aaron Doyle (eds), Risk and Morality (University of Toronto Press, 2003), pp. 87104 Google Scholar.

39 Ibid., p. 87.

40 Kindhauser, Mary K. (ed.), Communicable Diseases 2002: Global Defence Against the Infectious Disease Threat (World Health Organisation, 2002), available at: {http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/42572/1/9241590297.pdf} accessed 8 July 2016Google Scholar.

41 In the United Kingdom, the response to mid-nineteenth century cholera epidemics followed precisely this pattern. Popularly attributed to the revolutionary statistical epidemiology of Dr John Snow, who painstakingly identified a contaminated communal water pump handle as the source of a central London outbreak, the realisation that cholera spread via the faecal-oral route forced the authorities to act. Legislative changes followed and regulations governing public health were disseminated by the General Board of Health that required local authorities to ‘provide dispensaries operating around the clock with sufficient medical aid to treat cholera patients’ among other stipulations, see Snow, John, On the Mode of Communication of Cholera (John Churchill, 1855)Google Scholar; Cameron, Donald and Jones, Ian G., ‘John Snow, the Broad Street pump and modern epidemiology’, International Journal of Epidemiology, 12 (1983), pp. 393396 Google Scholar; Kotar, S. L. and Gessler, J. E., Cholera: A Worldwide History (Jefferson, NC: McFarland and Company, 2014), pp. 151160 Google Scholar.

42 Enders, Walter and Sandler, Todd, ‘The effectiveness of antiterrorism policies: a vector-autoregression-intervention analysis’, The American Political Science Review, 87 (1993), pp. 829844 Google Scholar.

43 Preventive Security Measures, Convention on International Aviation, Annex 17, ‘Security: Safeguarding International Civil Aviation Against Acts of Unlawful Interference’ (International Civil Aviation Organisation, 2014).

44 Burchell, Mark J., ‘W(h)ither the Drake equation?’, International Journal of Astrobiology, 5 (2006), pp. 243250 Google Scholar.

45 SETI Institute, ‘The Drake Equation’, available at: {http://www.seti.org/node/434} accessed 2 February 2016.

46 Burchell, ‘W(h)ither the Drake equation?’, p. 249.

47 Adams, ‘Risk and morality’, p. 92.

48 Ibid.

49 Ibid.

50 There are likely to have been many more unrecorded or unreported cases, with political or other reasons acting as a constraint upon national authorities from sharing such sensitive information. The International Atomic Energy Agency’s Incident and Trafficking Database (ITDB) is a case in point: event reporting is voluntary and therefore the completeness of the database is open to question. While statistical tools can be applied to the ITDB, this must be done in the knowledge that the results are inherently limited for this reason.

51 Bunn, Matthew, ‘A mathematical model of the risk of nuclear terrorism’, The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 607 (2006), pp. 103120 Google Scholar.

52 Ibid., p. 113.

53 Ferguson and Potter, The Four Faces of Nuclear Terrorism, pp. 33, 194–5.

54 Ibid., p. 4.

55 Jenkins, Brian Michael, ‘The new age of terrorism’, in Brian Michael Jenkins (ed.), McGraw-Hill Homeland Security Handbook (RAND, 2006)Google Scholar, ch. 9.

56 Cole, Benjamin, The Changing Face of Terrorism (London: I. B. Tauris, 2010)Google Scholar.

57 Ferguson and Potter, The Four Faces of Nuclear Terrorism, ch. 1.

58 Mowatt-Larssen, Rolf, ‘The Armageddon test: Preventing nuclear terrorism’, Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, 65 (2009), pp. 6070 Google Scholar.

59 Volders, Brecht and Sauer, Tom (eds), Nuclear Terrorism: Countering the Threat (London: Routledge, 2016)Google Scholar; Levi, Michael, On Nuclear Terrorism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009)Google Scholar.

60 After receiving criticism for ‘alarmist’ views on the issue, Peter Zimmerman famously included a section headed ‘John Mueller: Pollyanna?’ in his paper, ‘Do we really need to worry? Some reflections on the threat of nuclear terrorism’, Defence Against Terrorism Review, 2:2 (2009), pp. 1–14. In Achieving Nuclear Ambitions: Scientists, Politicians, and Proliferation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), Jacques Hymans notes that Allison ‘cites – without irony – an analysis conducted by science fiction writer Tom Clancy’ as part of an argument showing terrorists or even individuals could self-produce fissile materials for inclusion in an IND.

61 Allison, Nuclear Terrorism, p. 15; Mueller, ‘The Atomic Terrorist’, p. 14.

62 Keller, William and Modarres, Mohammad, ‘A historical overview of probabilistic risk assessment development and its use in the nuclear power industry: a tribute to the late Professor Normal Carl Rasmussen’, Reliability Engineering and System Safety, 89 (2005), pp. 271285 Google Scholar.

63 Reactor Safety Study: An Assessment of Accident Risks in U.S. Commercial Nuclear Power Plants (US Nuclear Regulatory Commission, 1975).

64 Ezell, Barry C. et al., ‘Probabilistic risk analysis and terrorism risk’, Risk Analysis, 30 (2010), pp. 575589 Google Scholar.

65 Paté-Cornell, Elisabeth, ‘Fault tree vs. event trees in reliability analysis’, Risk Analysis, 4 (1984), pp. 177186 Google Scholar.

66 For a particularly accessible introduction to the theory, see ibid.

67 Bunn, ‘A mathematical model of the risk of nuclear terrorism’, pp. 104–6; Mueller, ‘The Atomic Terrorist’, p. 14. Levi stands in contrast to this approach, for example, by analysing the set of defensive measures as a whole, that is, as a layered defensive system.

68 Bunn, ‘A mathematical model of the risk of nuclear terrorism’, p. 103.

69 Ibid.

70 Kenney, Michael, ‘From Pablo to Osama: Counter-terrorism lessons from the war on drugs’, Survival, 45 (2003), pp. 187206 Google Scholar.

71 Enders and Sandler, ‘The effectiveness of antiterrorism policies’.

72 For instance, via a joint US-Russia blue ribbon ceremony inaugurating the first US Second Line of Defense border monitoring system in place at Moscow’s Sheremetyevo airport, see Lara Cantuti and Lee Thomas, ‘Second Line of Defense Program’, paper presented at The Institute of Nuclear Materials Management (US Department of Energy, 1999), p. 3.

73 Morton, David P., Pan, Fend, and Saeger, Kevin J., ‘Models for nuclear smuggling interdiction’, IIE Transactions, 39 (2007), pp. 314 Google Scholar.

74 One notable exception is the study by Morton, Pan, and Saeger where resource allocation is dynamically modelled in the face of a (potentially) unknown number of adversaries.

75 US National Research Council Committee on Methodological Improvements to the Department of Homeland Security’s Biological Agent Risk Analysis, ‘Department of Homeland Security Bioterrorism Risk Assessment: A Call for Change’ (National Academies Press, 2008), p. 27.

76 Ibid.

77 Borum, Randy, ‘Understanding terrorist psychology’, in Andrew Silke (ed.), The Psychology of Counter-Terrorism (London: Routledge, 2010)Google Scholar.

78 Levi, On Nuclear Terrorism, p. 49.

79 Reader, Ian, Contemporary Religious Violence in Japan: The Case of Aum Shinrikyo (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 2000)Google Scholar.

80 Flint, Colin and Radil, Steven M., ‘Terrorism and counter-terrorism: Situating al-Qaeda and the global war on terror within geopolitical trends and structure’, Eurasian Geography and Economics, 20 (2009), pp. 150171 Google Scholar.

81 Lugar, Richard G., ‘The Lugar Survey on Proliferation Threats and Responses’, Office of United States Senator Richard G. Lugar (2005), p. 16 Google Scholar.

82 Shmueli, Galit, ‘To explain or predict’, Statistical Science, 25 (2010), pp. 289310 Google Scholar.

83 Morgan, Mary S. and Morrison, Margaret (eds), Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Sciences (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999)Google Scholar.

84 McBurney, Peter, ‘What are models for?’, in Massimo Cossentino, Michael Kaisers, Karl Tuyls, and Gerhard Weiss (eds), Multi-Agent Systems (Springer Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2012), pp. 175188 Google Scholar.

85 Bunn, ‘A mathematical model of the risk of nuclear terrorism’, p. 103.

86 Burchell, ‘W(h)ither the Drake equation?’, p. 244.

87 Paté-Cornell, Elisabeth and Guikema, Seth, ‘Probabilistic modeling of terrorist threats: a systems analysis approach to setting priorities among countermeasures’, Military Operations Research, 7 (2002), p. 1 Google Scholar.

88 Burchell, ‘W(h)ither the Drake equation?’, p. 244.

89 Bunn, ‘A mathematical model of the risk of nuclear terrorism’, p. 117.

90 For instance, Lugar, ‘The Lugar Survey on Proliferation Threats and Responses’.

91 McBurney, ‘What are models for?’, p. 184.

92 Bunn, ‘A mathematical model of the risk of nuclear terrorism’, p. 108.

93 Kaplan and Garrick, ‘On the quantitative definition of risk’.

94 O’Hagan, Anthony et al., Uncertain Judgements: Eliciting Experts’ Probabilities (Hoboken, NJ: Wiley, 2006), p. 25 Google Scholar.

95 Howard, Ronald A., Dynamic Probabilistic Systems, Volume II: Semi-Markov and Decision Processes (Mineola, NY: Dover, 2007), p. 965 Google Scholar; for instance, Miller, William M., ‘A state-transition model of epidemic foot-and-mouth disease’, New Techniques in Veterinary Epidemiology and Economics, 1 (1976)Google Scholar.

96 See, for example, Ransom Weaver et al., ‘Modeling and Simulating Terrorist Decision-Making: A ‘Performance Moderator Function’ Approach to Generating Virtual Opponents’, Proceedings of the 10th Conference on Computer Generated Forces and Behavioural Representation (2001).

97 US National Research Council, ‘Risk assessment’.

98 Lampland, Martha, ‘False numbers as formalizing practices’, Social Studies of Science, 40 (2010), pp. 377404 Google Scholar.