Article contents
The Pros and Cons of Legal Automation and its Governance
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 20 January 2017
Extract
The article examines the field of legal automation, its advantages and drawbacks, the ways in which legal constraints and safeguards can be embedded into technology and how the law may govern human behaviour through codes, IT architectures, and design. By stressing both benefits and shortcomings of legal automation, the article does not suggest that the latter is something “neutral”. Rather, making legal reasoning and enforcement automatic, so that even a machine can process and understand this information, should be conceived as a set of constraints and affordances that transform, or reshape, the environment of people’s interaction and moreover, the interplay of human and artificial agents, thereby affecting basic pillars of the (rule of) law. The overall aim is to flesh out goals and values that are at stake with choices of technological dependence, delegation and trust, so as to determine the good mix between legal automation and public deliberation.
- Type
- Special Issue on the Man and the Machine
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016
References
1 Pagallo, Ugo, Introduzione alla filosofia digitale: da Leibniz a Chaitin (Torino: Giappichelli, 2006).Google Scholar
2 Durante, Massimo, “Normativity, Constructionism, and Constraining Affordances”, XIII (2) Ethics and Politics (2011), pp. 180 et sqq.;Google Scholar Pagallo, Ugo, “Good Onlife Governance: On Law, Spontaneous Orders, and Design”, in Luciano Floridi (ed.), The Onlife Manifesto: Being Human in a Hyperconnected Era (Dordrecht: Springer, 2015), pp. 161 et sqq.Google Scholar
3 Casanovas, Pompeu, Pagallo, Ugo, Palmirani, Monica and Sartor, Giovanni (eds.), AI Approaches to the Complexity of Legal Systems. Law, Social Intelligence, nMAS and the Semantic Web. (Berlin-Heidelberg: Springer, 2014);Google Scholar Casanovas, Pompeu, Pagallo, Ugo, Sartor, Giovanni, and Ajani, Gianmaria (eds.), AI Approaches to the Complexity of Legal Systems. Complex Systems, the Semantic Web, Ontologies, Argumentation, and Dialogue (Berlin–Heidelberg: Springer, 2010);CrossRefGoogle Scholar Palmirani, Monica, Pagallo, Ugo, Casanovas, Pompeu et al. (eds.), AI Approaches to the Complexity of Legal Systems. Models and Ethical Challenges for Legal Systems, Legal Language and Legal Ontologies, Argumentation and Software Agents (Berlin–Heidelberg: Springer, 2012).Google Scholar
4 Breuker, Joost, Casanovas, Pompeu, Klein, Michel C.A. et al. (eds.), Law, Ontologies and the Semantic Web. Channelling the Legal Information Flood (Amsterdam: IOS Press, 2009)Google Scholar; Casanovas, Complex Systems, supra note 3.
5 Simon, Herbert A., The Sciences of the Artificial. Cambridge (Mass., MIT Press, 1996), at p. 128.Google Scholar
6 Sartor, Giovanni, Palmirani, Monica, Francesconi, Enrico, et al., Legislative XML for the Semantic Web. Principles, Models, Standards for Document Management (Dordrecht: Springer, 2011).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
7 Núria Casellas, Legal Ontology Engineering. Methodologies, Modelling Trends, and the Ontology of Professional Judicial Knowledge (Berlin-Heidelberg: Springer, 2011).
8 Pagallo, Ugo, “Designing Data Protection Safeguards Ethically”, 2(2) Information (2011a), pp. 247 et sqq.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
9 Leenes, Ronald and Lucivero, Federica, “Laws on Robots, Laws by Robots, Laws in Robots: Regulating Robot Behaviour by Design”, 6(2) Law, Innovation and Technology (2014), pp. 193 et sqq.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
10 RoboLaw, Guidelines on Regulating Robotics. EU Project on Regulating Emerging Robotic Technologies in Europe: Robotics facing Law and Ethics (22 September 2014).
11 Cavoukian, Ann, “Privacy by Design: The Definitive Workshop”, 3(2) Identity in the Information Society (2010), pp. 247 et sqq.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
12 Flanagan, Mary, Howe, Daniel C. and Nissenbaum, Helen, “Embodying Values in Technology: Theory and Practice”, in Jeroen van den Hoven and John Weckert (eds.), Information Technology and Moral Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, New York, 2008), pp. 322 et sqq.Google Scholar
13 Pagallo, Ugo, “Cracking down on Autonomy: Three Challenges to Design in IT Law” 14(4) Ethics and Information Technology 2012), pp. 319 et sqq.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
14 Zittrain, Jonathan, “Perfect Enforcement on Tomorrow's Internet” in Roger Brownsword and Karen Yeung (eds.), Regulating Technologies: Legal Futures, Regulatory Frames and Technological Fixes, (London: Hart, 2007), pp. 125 et sqq.Google Scholar
15 Lawrence Lessig, Free Culture: The Nature and Future of Creativity (Penguin: New York, 2004), p. 152.
16 Karen Yeung, “Towards an Understanding of Regulation by Design”, in Brownsword, Regulating Technologies,supra note 14, pp. 79 et sqq.
17 Koops, Bert–Jaap and Leenes, Ronald, “Privacy Regulation Cannot Be Hardcoded: A Critical Comment on the “Privacy by Design” Provision in Data Protection Law”, 28 International Review of Law, Computers & Technology (2014), pp. 159 et sqq.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
18 Kelsen, Hans, General Theory of the Law and the State, trans. A. Wedberg (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1949).Google Scholar
19 Pagallo, Ugo, “Online Security and the Protection of Civil Rights: A Legal Overview”, 26(4) Philosophy & Technology (2011b), pp. 381 et sqq.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
20 Pagallo, Ugo, The Laws of Robots: Contracts, Crimes, and Torts (Dordrecht: Springer, 2013).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
21 Reed, Chris, Making Laws for Cyberspace (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), pp. 82 et sqq.Google Scholar
22 Koops, “Privacy Regulation Cannot Be Hardcoded”, supra note 17.
23 Durante, Massimo, “Dealing with Legal Conflicts in the Information Society. An Informational Understanding of Balancing Competing Interests”, 26(4) Philosophy & Technology (2013), pp. 437 et sqq.Google Scholar
24 Dautenhahn, Kerstin, “Socially intelligent robots: dimensions of human–robot interaction”, 362(1480) Philosophical Transactions (2007), at p. 699.Google Scholar
25 Hart, Herbert, The Concept of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1961), at p. 121.Google Scholar
26 Kahneman, Daniel, Thinking Fast and Slow (New York: MacMillan, 2011).Google Scholar
27 Hart, The Concept of Law, supra note 26; Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1977);Google Scholar Shapiro, Scott J., “The ‘Hart-Dworkin’ debate: a short guide for the perplexed”, 77 Public Law and Legal Theory Working Paper Series (2007) (Michigan Law School).Google Scholar
28 Hart, The Concept of Law,supra note 26.
29 Durante, Massimo, “What Is the Model of Trust for Multi–agent Systems? Whether or Not E-Trust Applies to Autonomous Agents”, 23(3-4) Knowledge, Technology & Policy (2010), pp. 347 et sqq.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- 22
- Cited by