Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T05:10:02.808Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Cultural evolution: A review of theoretical challenges

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 February 2024

Ryan Nichols*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, CSU Fullerton, Fullerton, CA, USA Center for the Study of Human Nature, CSU Fullerton, Fullerton, CA, USA
Mathieu Charbonneau
Affiliation:
Africa Institute for Research in Economics and Social Sciences, Université Mohammed VI Polytechnique, Rabat, Morocco
Azita Chellappoo
Affiliation:
School of Social Sciences and Global Studies, Open University, Milton Keynes, UK
Taylor Davis
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Purdue University, West Lafayette, IN, USA
Miriam Haidle
Affiliation:
Research Center ‘The Role of Culture in Early Expansions of Humans’, Heidelberg Academy of Sciences and Humanities, Heidelberg, Germany
Erik O. Kimbrough
Affiliation:
Smith Institute for Political Economy and Philosophy, Chapman University, Orange, CA, USA
Henrike Moll
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, University of Southern California, Los Angeles, CA, USA
Richard Moore
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Warwick, Coventry, England, UK
Thom Scott-Phillips
Affiliation:
Ikerbasque, Basque Foundation for Science, Institute for Logic, Cognition, Language & Information, Bilbao, Spain
Benjamin Grant Purzycki
Affiliation:
Benjamin Grant Purzycki, Department of the Study of Religion, Aarhus University, Aarhus, Denmark
Jose Segovia-Martin
Affiliation:
M6 Polytechnic University, Rabat, Morocco Complex Systems Institute, Paris Île-de-France, Paris, France
*
Corresponding author: Ryan Nichols; Email: rnichols@fullerton.edu

Abstract

The rapid growth of cultural evolutionary science, its expansion into numerous fields, its use of diverse methods, and several conceptual problems have outpaced corollary developments in theory and philosophy of science. This has led to concern, exemplified in results from a recent survey conducted with members of the Cultural Evolution Society, that the field lacks ‘knowledge synthesis’, is poorly supported by ‘theory’, has an ambiguous relation to biological evolution and uses key terms (e.g. ‘culture’, ‘social learning’, ‘cumulative culture’) in ways that hamper operationalization in models, experiments and field studies. Although numerous review papers in the field represent and categorize its empirical findings, the field's theoretical challenges receive less critical attention even though challenges of a theoretical or conceptual nature underlie most of the problems identified by Cultural Evolution Society members. Guided by the heterogeneous ‘grand challenges’ emergent in this survey, this paper restates those challenges and adopts an organizational style requisite to discussion of them. The paper's goal is to contribute to increasing conceptual clarity and theoretical discernment around the most pressing challenges facing the field of cultural evolutionary science. It will be of most interest to cultural evolutionary scientists, theoreticians, philosophers of science and interdisciplinary researchers.

Type
Review
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided that no alterations are made and the original article is properly cited. The written permission of Cambridge University Press must be obtained prior to any commercial use and/or adaptation of the article.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

The growing attraction of cultural evolutionary science stems from the fact that cultural evolutionary processes operate in ways that can be described as ‘descent with modification’. Such processes, like language, exhibit dynamics similar to biological evolutionary processes. This paper serves the research community as a review of theoretical challenges (with occasional suggestions) in cultural evolutionary science across four domains: conceptual challenges; methodological issues, including modelling, experimentation and field studies; topical challenges; and implications and applications. In the remainder of this section, we define terms and restate survey results conducted by the Cultural Evolution Society, results which we use to motivate the rest of the discussion.

The term ‘cultural evolutionary science’ (abbreviated ‘CES’) refers to an interdisciplinary field of inquiry using an array of scientific methods to study culture and the interactions between cultural and biological evolutionary processes. Contents of cultural evolutionary science include observation statements, methodological commitments, presuppositions about varieties of statistical tests, and more. ‘Cultural evolutionary theory’ (‘CET’) refers to the subset of cultural evolutionary science composing laws, generalizations and hypotheses, and their derivations and entailments. The events, processes and objects in the world that physically and mentally instantiate the transmission and evolution of culture across persons, populations and generations we refer to simply as ‘cultural evolution’ or ‘cultural evolutionary processes’.

Numerous reviews of CES have been written. Creanza et al. (Reference Creanza, Kolodny and Feldman2017) review CES results broadly relevant for demography and genetics. Legare (Reference Legare2017) reviews adaptations for teaching and imitation and their cultural representation. Mesoudi (Reference Mesoudi2016) makes a broad review of findings in CES. Singh et al. (Reference Singh, Acerbi, Caldwell, Danchin, Isabel, Molleman and Derex2021) review CES findings that, per the title, go ‘beyond social learning’. Smith (Reference Smith2020) reviews theory and findings about cultural group selection. Tamariz (Reference Tamariz2017) focuses on cultural language evolution. Whiten (Reference Whiten2019) reviews experimental findings pertaining to culture in non-animals. Smolla et al. (Reference Smolla, Jansson, Lehmann, Houkes, Weissing, Hammerstein and Enquist2021) focus on underappreciated features of cultural evolution. However, these papers have not attempted to diagnose theoretical problems in CES whose varied instantiations animate the discussion below. This is no criticism since the aims of these other review papers are mainly to summarize recent empirical results (usually within one sub-area of CES) and identify potential hypotheses for further testing. The present contribution is instead a critical review of the needs and challenges facing the body of theory accompanying CES, which we refer to as cultural evolutionary theory.

An efficient means for researchers concerned with CET to contribute to improvements in the field is to take account of and respond to the most pressing stated challenges facing the field. As a result, the present critical review of theoretical needs takes its cue from results of a recent survey of the membership of the Cultural Evolution Society about the field's ‘grand challenges’ (Brewer et al., Reference Brewer, Gelfand, Jackson, MacDonald, Peregrine and Richerson2017). Published results of this survey detail two varied sets of challenges. The first set was drawn from semantic analysis of topics directly from survey results. (Subsequent references to ‘survey results’ are to this paper.) Its most pressing challenge, revealed to be about twice as important as the next topic, was with ‘knowledge synthesis’. The authors state that this topic relates ‘primarily to issues of theoretical integration and speaks to the idea that while many behavioural scientists and humanities scholars see culture as a defining feature of humankind, different subfields rarely read each other's work or build interdisciplinary research programmes to explore how human cultures differ from those of other animals’ (Brewer et al., Reference Brewer, Gelfand, Jackson, MacDonald, Peregrine and Richerson2017: 1). Additional topics of appreciable concern in the first set of results were topics labelled ‘culture definition’, ‘theory’, ‘shared language’ across the disciplines, ‘pro-sociality’ and ‘cultural transmission’.

The second set of ‘grand challenges’ were produced by co-authors of the report following their reflection on the first set of results and the clustered relations amongst those results. In the second set are:

  1. (C1) understanding ‘social adaptation’ and what drives it;

  2. (C2) understanding ‘the role of cultural evolution in the context of organic evolution’ in light of the fact that ‘culture is strongly influenced by biology’;

  3. (C3) overcoming problems involved in ‘modelling culture as a complex adaptive system’;

  4. (C4) ‘identifying processes of transmission and accumulation of cultural traits’ to reach ‘consensus on the mechanisms underlying’ mathematical models of cultural evolution;

  5. (C5) ‘integrating methods, data, and results across disciplines’, which is reported to necessitate ‘shared conceptual references and vocabulary’;

  6. (C6) creating ‘organizational and funding structures’;

  7. (C7) ‘identifying cultural evolutionary processes that address significant social, economic, and political problems’ including ‘climate change’; and

  8. (C8) ‘educating policymakers’ and developing a public understanding of results of cultural evolutionary research (Brewer et al., Reference Brewer, Gelfand, Jackson, MacDonald, Peregrine and Richerson2017: 3).

One problem is symptomatic of several of these challenges.

Often CES research teams identify a concept representing some coarse-grained phenomenon; the concept is operationalized for use in modelling, laboratory experiments and/or field studies; corresponding empirical research is conducted and intriguing results are found. Often this occurs without a definition or formal analysis of (i.e. without providing a set of necessary and sufficient conditions to govern) the concept. (See Lewens Reference Lewens, Kampourakis and Uller2020; we thank Tim Lewens for crystallizing this problem for us.) Tokens of this type of what we will call the ‘general problem’ not infrequently issue in enigmatic results, methodological challenges, misinterpretation or miscommunication. The presence of this general problem is unsurprising to those who believe that even the term ‘cultural evolution’ is ‘confused’ because it is ‘being used to indicate both a phenomenon – culture changing through time – and an approach to study it’ (Micheletti et al., Reference Micheletti, Brandl and Mace2022: 667). Echoes of this general problem lurk behind problems of ‘knowledge synthesis’ and ‘theory’, and concerns with definitions of ‘culture’, ‘cumulative culture’ and ‘social learning’, as well as challenges (C1)–(C5).

The primary goal of this paper is to contribute to improving future research in CES by increasing the conceptual clarity and theoretical discernment around several of the most pressing challenges facing CES as revealed by these survey results. These challenges range widely and frequently overlap, which informs the paper's eclectic organization. Section 2 opens with some case studies to establish the utility of a focus on theoretical issues. Section 3 reviews germane developments in the philosophy of science. Section 4 focuses attention on methods challenges in CES, especially on issues of integration as found in (C5). Section 5 discusses two topical issues, culture in human and non-human animals and the nature of ‘selection’ in linguistics. Taking a cue from (C7) and (C8), Section 6 discusses challenges facing application of CES to policy, with attention to climate change.

2. Case studies in the value of theory and conceptual analysis for CES

To motivate the utility of critical discussion of the field's theoretical challenges, we lead with three abbreviated case studies. Each represents one area in which survey results have pointed to a ‘grand challenge’. Each case study anticipates a subsequent section of the paper.

2.1. Conceptual challenges

Conceptual challenges are typically problems of definitional scope. The importance of establishing clear definitions of terms is obvious from survey results that lament the field's lack of ‘shared conceptual references and vocabulary’ and its need to find ‘common language’ (Brewer et al., Reference Brewer, Gelfand, Jackson, MacDonald, Peregrine and Richerson2017: 3). Meanings of ‘copying’, ‘imitation’ and ‘social learning’ are used equivocally across CES, impeding consistent operationalization in experiments. An influential formal model of cultural transmission purports to show that ‘environmental learning’ does not, but ‘social learning’ does, produce the ‘empirical ‘S-shaped’ cumulative adoption curves that dominate the diffusion of innovations literature’ (Henrich, Reference Henrich2001: 992). (The term ‘S-shaped curve’ refers to a sigmoid curve plotting data about the adoption of innovations characterized by, first, lengthy, laboured growth of early adopters followed by a quick increase in adoption, creating a high slope, and concluded by a slowly increasing phase with low slope and many adopters.) Tim Lewens argues (2015: 114–118) that this model treats its concepts of ‘environmental learning’ and ‘social learning’ as mutually exclusive. Henrich's definition of ‘environmental learning’ reads: ‘individuals acquire and evaluate payoff-relevant information about alternative behavioural options by action and interaction in their local social, economic and ecological environments’ (Henrich, Reference Henrich2001: 992). As defined, the meaning of ‘environmental learning’ overlaps with the meaning of ‘social learning’. That is, the two are not independently defined. This entails that ‘environmental learning’ could also be modelled to yield S-shaped curves. This appears inconsistent with Henrich's conclusions from the model.

If the definitions of ‘social learning’ and ‘environmental learning’ are not retooled, subsequent modelling and experimentation using these definitions are unlikely to overcome challenge (C3). This conceptual misstep appears to inform pointed empirical criticisms of the model's explanation (Henrich, Reference Henrich2004) of the contraction of the Tasmanian toolkit (Read, Reference Read2011; Vaesen et al., Reference Vaesen, Collard, Cosgrove and Roebroeks2016a, Reference Vaesen, Collard, Cosgrove and Roebroeksb; Henrich et al., Reference Henrich, Boyd, Derex, Kline, Mesoudi, Muthukrishna and Thomas2016). This preliminarily demonstrates the value of critical philosophical attention on definitions in CES; see Section 3 below.

2.2. Methods

‘Cumulative cultural evolution’, a topic of significant concern in survey results pertaining to the dynamics of cultural systems (Brewer et al., Reference Brewer, Gelfand, Jackson, MacDonald, Peregrine and Richerson2017: 2), refers to a process in which traditions are modified and improved over time with a performance capacity that is beyond what an individual could generate on her own. This marks a necessary condition for a process to represent cumulative culture, a necessary condition widely repeated amongst experimentalists. For example, in their experimental attempt to understand what they call ‘cumulative culture’, Derex et al. (Reference Derex, Beugin, Godelle and Raymond2013) repeat this condition in their first paragraph by writing that cumulative culture is that which ‘no individual could have invented alone’ (p. 389). This necessary condition on cumulative culture was first articulated by Boyd and Richerson (Reference Boyd and Richerson1996: 80), who wrote that for a process to be properly cumulative, it must lead human cultures to ‘accumulate changes over many generations, resulting in culturally transmitted behaviors that no single human individual could invent on his own’ (Boyd & Richerson, Reference Boyd and Richerson1996: 80; our italics). Thus, to test whether a cumulative effect has been obtained, an experiment must at minimum compare how a solitary individual and a diffusion chain fare on the same task using equivalent time resources (Miton & Charbonneau, Reference Miton and Charbonneau2018: 3).

Study of cumulative culture is done through a variety of methods including modelling, field studies, experiments and more, but this issues in a challenge of creating necessary and sufficient conditions (see (C5) at Brewer et al., Reference Brewer, Gelfand, Jackson, MacDonald, Peregrine and Richerson2017: 3) that are clear, consistent and integrated across methods. According to Miton and Charbonneau (Reference Miton and Charbonneau2018), this is yet to happen in the study of cumulative culture. Specifically, a crucial difference emerged between theory-based analysis of the cumulative culture concept, in which the necessary condition was identified, and its operationalization in experiments and models. The necessary condition stated above is infrequently operationalized in experiments. And when it is (as in Derex et al., Reference Derex, Godelle and Raymond2014; Mesoudi, Reference Mesoudi2011), it risks misleading readers. Suppose a solitary individual and a group in a diffusion chain are each given one hour to complete the same task, and suppose that the group completes the task faster. Is the necessary condition met by this operationalization? No. Miton and Charbonneau (Reference Miton and Charbonneau2018: 3) argue that this is ‘insufficient to warrant the conclusion that observed differences in performance are the results of a genuinely cumulative process’ because these control conditions cannot distinguish between performance capacity (evidence of cumulative culture) and its confound of improvement speed. This is because participants might have their individual skill development accelerated by learning in a social context (improvement speed), and complete a puzzle, even though social collaboration across generations is unnecessary (performance capacity) for completion of the puzzle (Miton & Charbonneau, Reference Miton and Charbonneau2018: 3). Section 4 includes discussion of challenges (C3), (C4) and (C5) pertaining to three common methods in CES research, modelling, experimentation and field studies.

2.3. Topical challenges

Sub-disciplines within CES face messy challenges when researchers port coarse-grained focal concepts from one subfield to another. In the Cultural Evolution Society survey (Brewer et al., Reference Brewer, Gelfand, Jackson, MacDonald, Peregrine and Richerson2017: 1–2), the challenge of synthesizing knowledge across diverse research areas was rated as the field's most pressing concern. Consider the status of a prominent CES explanation of ‘cooperation’, which says that cooperation within groups emerged because of psycho-social consequences of belief in punitive gods (Johnson, Reference Johnson2005; Norenzayan, Reference Norenzayan2013). This causal claim was supported by diverse studies ranging from anthropological databases that identified statistical relations between a culture's adoption of a moralistic high god and markers of cooperation (Roes & Raymond, Reference Roes and Raymond2003) to economic games experiments that showed priming with religious concepts raised offers to strangers (Shariff & Norenzayan, Reference Shariff and Norenzayan2007), and from cognitive science of religion research on minimally counterintuitive ideas (Norenzayan et al., Reference Norenzayan, Atran, Faulkner and Schaller2006, although see Purzycki & Willard, Reference Purzycki and Willard2016) to psychological studies of agent-based teleological thinking (Kelemen, Reference Kelemen1999).

Yet CES-inspired study of religion and cooperation can succumb to the aforementioned challenges. As part of a wider problem in the social sciences, religious priming studies have suffered from multiple failures to replicate (e.g. Gomes & McCullough, Reference Gomes and McCullough2015; Miyatake & Higuchi, Reference Miyatake and Higuchi2017). While cross-cultural experimental evidence bolsters the supernatural punishment–cooperation relationship (Lang et al., Reference Lang, Purzycki, Apicella, Atkinson, Bolyanatz, Cohen and Henrich2019), the purported causal relation between supernatural punishment and social complexity (an index of broader cooperation) remains unclear (Watts et al., Reference Watts, Greenhill, Atkinson, Currie, Bulbulia and Gray2015) and more basic conceptual concerns about presumed psychological mechanisms linger (Schloss & Murray, Reference Schloss and Murray2011). Echoing our ‘general problem’, critics argue that the concept of ‘cooperation’ at work in models and experiments about effects of belief in supernatural punishment on cooperation often equivocates because within-group parochiality is confused with cooperation between non-kin (Galen, Reference Galen2016).

Critics might argue that research on this topic is consistent with scientific progress owing to its self-correcting nature, and as a result, the community does not require theory-driven re-evaluation of the subfield but more detail-oriented diligence. While we could be incorrect, it seems that focus on prosaic aspects of CES research can camouflage hurdles still thwarting progress. Most hypotheses tested in this subfield were not logical derivatives from a principled theory in part because the concept of a ‘high god’ lacks adequate formality and consistency across operationalizations. Some advocates define the term ‘high gods’ as ‘gods who cared about cooperative – and harmony – enhancing behavior’ (Shariff, Norenzayan, & Henrich, Reference Shariff, Norenzayan, Henrich, Schaller, Norenzayan, Heine, Yamagishi and Kamedda2010: 124); others defined ‘high gods’ as deities specifically responsible for creating reality, and who may or may not be ‘specifically supportive of human morality’ (Swanson, Reference Swanson1960). Confusions of this type put researchers’ ability to falsify causal hypotheses about religious beliefs and cooperation at risk since, if a correlation was not discovered in a dataset, the former circular definition warrants the inference that the dataset represented a ‘low’ not a ‘high’ god (Nichols et al. (Reference Nichols, Slingerland, Nielbo, Kirby and Logan2020: 4), and see Table 1 in that paper for similar logical problems in this subfield; see Lightner et al. (Reference Lightner, Bendixen and Purzycki2023), on the empirical implications of these conflations). Below, Section 5 analyses theoretical difficulties as found in the topical areas of non-human culture and language.

2.4. Implications and applications

There are many appreciable consequences of CES findings for public policy, social change, well-being and research ethics. Aside from a few exceptions (e.g. Wilson, Reference Wilson2011) these implications have not been thoroughly studied. Section 5 seeks to open this area with discussion of one application (about norms) and one implication (about human uniqueness).

These case studies provide ample justification for the value of theoretical and philosophical attention given to major challenges to CES. To improve the conceptual clarity and theoretical discernment in ongoing CES research, and because it may be unfamiliar to readers, we next encapsulate extant philosophy of science research devoted to challenges voiced in the survey results above.

3. Developments in the philosophy of science for cultural evolution

The contemporary field of cultural evolutionary science has its formal origins in the work of Luigi Luca Cavalli-Sforza and Marcus Feldman (Reference Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman1973) and Marcus Feldman and Cavalli-Sforza (Reference Feldman and Cavalli-Sforza1976). Borrowing modelling strategies from population genetics and epidemiology, they identified analogies between biological and cultural evolution and transmission, exploring culture as a distinct form of inheritance. Subsequent generations of researchers have fleshed out this modelling approach, developing it further in multiple directions and identifying new explanatory projects – opportunistically borrowing tools from evolutionary biology, quantitative and cultural sociology, anthropology and cognitive psychology, among others. As a result, even the foundational status of formal mathematical models has not led to anything like a single, paradigmatic approach in CET. Instead, the field's development reflects its eclectic opportunism, leaving a vibrant patchwork of loosely related approaches vulnerable to the aforementioned challenges, as well as to explicitly theoretical problems not mentioned in survey results but raised in recent philosophy of science.

In the first wave of theoretical and philosophy of science work on cultural evolution, applications to culture of the Modern Synthesis in biology were developed (see Griesemer, Reference Griesemer1988; Hull, Reference Hull1988; Wimsatt, Reference Wimsatt1999). A second wave emerged at the end of the twentieth century. While continuing to involve reapplication of tools from biology to culture (e.g. see Skyrms, Reference Skyrms2014 on evolutionary game theory), in this period additional effort was placed on analysis of competing theoretical frameworks for CET (see Sterelny, Reference Sterelny2017), understanding conditions for culture in non-human animals (e.g. Ramsey et al., Reference Ramsey, Bastian and Van Schaik2007; Sterelny, Reference Sterelny, Laland and Galef2009) and evaluating the special character of cultural evolutionary explanations (e.g. Godfrey-Smith, Reference Godfrey-Smith2012). Currently, a third wave of theoretical work in CET is starting to swell (see e.g. Lewens, Reference Lewens2015) in response to the emergence of problems for CES without precursors in biology. Theoreticians and philosophers of science are now elaborating methods specific to CET, including modelling, experimentation and field studies, observing operational challenges in each that follow from the use of concepts like ‘culture’ and ‘cumulative culture’ (Buskell, Reference Buskell2022; Sterelny, Reference Sterelny2021; Vaesen & Houkes, Reference Vaesen and Houkes2021), ‘prestige bias’ (Chellappoo, Reference Chellappoo2021) and ‘cultural attractors’ (Driscoll, Reference Driscoll2011; Buskell, Reference Buskell2017). We contextualize then highlight three sets of philosophical problems that, in effect, we seek to add to the list of grand challenges facing the field.

First, CES sources generally deny the claim, originally by Dawkins (Reference Dawkins1989) about ‘memes’, that cultural transmission is replicative (Lewens & Buskell, Reference Lewens, Buskell, Zalta and Nodelman2023; see Henrich et al., Reference Henrich, Boyd and Richerson2008 & Sperber, Reference Sperber and Aunger2000; Dennett, Reference Dennett2017 is an exception). Nonetheless, many CES researchers appeal to ‘high-fidelity copying’ to explain complexity and diversity in human culture. Befitting the early growth of a new scientific endeavour, we generally welcome explanatory pluralisms (Charbonneau, Reference Charbonneau2020), yet in this case it represents a theoretical problem for the field. In biology, since genotype to phenotype mapping exists, and since transmission occurs from genotype to genotype, a principled ‘grain’ of description exists to guide the scientific study of transmission. This is absent in culture. The following example illustrates the ‘grain’ problem, which can be considered an example of the general problem noted above. ‘Suppose Andrew sings a line from a song, and Tim attempts to copy him: does “high fidelity” learning require Tim to reproduce the same melody, must he sing in the same key, must he sing with the same words, and the same emotional emphases?’ (Lewens & Buskell, Reference Lewens, Buskell, Zalta and Nodelman2023: section 6.2). If Tim sings with different words, in a dissimilar key, or with new accompaniment, under what conditions is it appropriate to reason that he has ‘copied’ Andrew? The specific means by which CES researchers measure fidelity or copying often lead to incompatible and incommensurable results, challenging the idea that fidelity would be a general, natural property of human cultural learning, let alone a causal one (Charbonneau & Bourrat, Reference Charbonneau and Bourrat2021).

Second, the advent of CES practised in broad spatiotemporal frames includes projects that consolidate historical and cross-cultural data in large databases (Slingerland et al., Reference Slingerland, Atkinson, Ember, Sheehan, Muthukrishna, Bulbulia and Gray2020), efforts in evolutionary archaeology and cognitive archaeology (Killin & Pain, Reference Killin and Pain2023), and in cultural macroevolution more generally (Gray & Watts, Reference Gray and Watts2017). While surveyed members of the Cultural Evolution Society regard the definition of ‘culture’ as a vexed but important problem (see Driscoll, Reference Driscoll2017; Ramsey & De Block, Reference Ramsey and De Block2015), a corollary often goes unnoticed, viz. that individuating cultures is distinct from the problem of defining ‘culture’ simpliciter. So what are ‘cultures’ or ‘cultural groups’ and how should they be individuated? Are cultures natural kinds? The latter metaphysical question is not idle: many working in political philosophy have long alleged that talking about ‘cultural groups’ is erroneously essentialist (Patten, Reference Patten2014). If we wish to avoid essentialist characterizations of specific ‘cultures’, then how can cultural groups be taxonomized in modelling or experimentation? Related, how do various elements of cultures, for instance, texts and material technologies, relate to one another (Buskell et al., Reference Buskell, Enquist and Jansson2019)?

Third is a set of issues emerging from the role of values in science, including epistemic values, absent from survey results. ‘Epistemic values’ is a term referring to normative traits of theories or methods themselves. Different methods and theories implicitly prioritize some values or purposes over others. For example, experimental collider physics prioritizes certainty over generalizability owing to its endorsement of a 5σ criterion of statistical significance. Cultural evolutionary science tends to emphasize the epistemic value of generalizability in part because of its origins in modelling. Generalizability can motivate the development of thin, abstract and largely ahistorical theories (Fracchia & Lewontin, Reference Fracchia and Lewontin1999). Epistemic values of CES in turn support characterizations of human cognition that are automatic and ‘kinetic’ (Lewens, Reference Lewens2015), a term used to refer to the population modelling approach to cultural evolution as akin to treating individuals as undifferentiated molecules familiar from the kinetic theory of gasses, and thus, far easier to formally model. Extant, ‘thin’ characterizations of cognition can pose a special problem in CES because they may misrepresent actual enculturation and transmission of cognitive contents, and also because they may feed narratives about culture and cultural change according to which individuals, perhaps especially in non-Western cultures (Wolf, Reference Wolf2005; Chellappoo, Reference Chellappoo, Ludwig, Koskinen, Mncube, Poliseli and Reyes-Galindo2022a), lack agency. Generally, what are the proper roles of personal and sub-personal processes in formal explanations of cultural transmission? This question gets to the heart of differences between the CES frameworks of cultural attractor theory and of population modelling (see Buskell, Reference Buskell2019). Is it appropriate for ‘population-thinking’ models to minimize agency by emphasizing roles of copying and imitation while neglecting to model roles of coercion or institutions (Boyd & Richerson, Reference Boyd and Richerson1985)? Does ‘cultural attractor theory’ (Sperber, Reference Sperber1996) in contrast attribute to agents too much capacity to modify cultural items while transmitting them? Increased efforts to integrate modelling with subtler accounts of encultured human cognition and transmission, in which they are sometimes rational, effortful and culturally inflected, will probably improve the field.

Finally, current research in philosophy of science points to the promise of bootstrapping CES and CET research into a philosophy of nature, i.e. formulating an ‘overall picture of the natural world that science […] seems to be giving us’ (Godfrey-Smith, Reference Godfrey-Smith, Oyama, Gray and Griffiths2001: 284). Important contributions include Kim Sterelny's (Reference Sterelny2012, Reference Sterelny2021) work aimed at outlining the natural history of human beings and their hominin ancestors, and work making sense of the striking increase in technological complexity of hominins (Pain & Brown, Reference Pain, Brown and Stein2021). This marks a promising shift that some have described in terms of movement from a constrained form of behavioural innovation to one that is ‘open-ended’ (Borg et al., Reference Borg, Buskell, Kapitany, Powers, Reindl and Tennie2022; Charbonneau, Reference Charbonneau2015), perhaps in a way analogous to the open-ended possibilities afforded by genetic recombination (Charbonneau, Reference Charbonneau2016).

4. Methods: Models, experiments and field studies

In this section, we discuss challenges pertaining to three common methods in CES. Giant strides have been made in the refinement and sophistication of these scientific techniques in recent decades. The body of local theory tethered to a single method is used to warrant choices in modelling (e.g. about framework or scale), in experimentation (e.g. about deriving from theory a hypothesis for testing) and in field studies (e.g. about operationalizing ‘social learning’ in archaeological contexts). The local theoretical reflection on decision-making about model type, parameterization and more, is rich and growing richer. This type of ‘method-specific’ theory is distinct from and narrower in scope than the cross-disciplinary theory essential for improving knowledge integration and meeting other needs of the CES research community. For example, even though an agent-based model might be exquisitely motivated on its own terms, there are rarely to be found theoretical tools that provide a principled structure for how the results of such a model are to be validated using data or results from experiments or field studies, even when those methods are used to explore ostensibly similar research questions.

4.1. Models in cultural evolution

As cultural evolution developed into a scientific field, innovative mathematical and computational techniques were devised to represent intricate features of cultural processes (Kandler et al., Reference Kandler, Perreault and Steele2012). Broadly speaking, three important modelling frameworks have helped to improve our theoretical understanding of evolutionary processes. The first framework is composed of gene–culture coevolution models, which assume a continuous, bidirectional interaction between genes and culture (Cavalli-Sforza & Feldman, Reference Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman1981; Boyd & Richerson, Reference Boyd and Richerson1985). Next are cultural neutral models, which assume that all variants are equally likely to be adopted, and attempt to understand cultural evolution in the absence of selective forces by assuming that changes in cultural variants are due solely to random drift and innovation (Bentley et al., Reference Bentley, Hahn and Shennan2004; Blythe, Reference Blythe2012; Reali & Griffiths, Reference Reali and Griffiths2009). Finally, the cultural selection framework assumes that some variants spread more rapidly than others, making evolution a process that is not neutral, but subject to biases (e.g. systematic cognitive and transmission patterns deviating from rationality) or selection pressures (e.g. environmental factors that affect fitness of variants) (Boyd & Richerson, Reference Boyd and Richerson1985; Hagen & Hammerstein, Reference Hagen and Hammerstein2006; Henrich & McElreath, Reference Henrich, McElreath, Barrett and Dunbar2007; Vale et al., Reference Vale, Flynn, Kendal, Rawlings, Hopper and Schapiro2017).

While modelling frameworks make distinctive assumptions about the nature of cultural processes, these frameworks can each be instantiated at either of two common scales. Regarding the scale used to model cultural evolution, researchers in the field have distinguished between two general classes (Van Dyke Parunak et al., Reference Parunak, Savit, & Riolo and L1998; Kandler et al., Reference Kandler, Perreault and Steele2012). The first is composed of micro-scale models, which aim to simulate how individual units in a system behave and interact with one another. The best-known type of micro-scale model is the agent-based model, which consists of a system composed of a set of autonomous units called agents, which simulates the decision-making, behaviour and interactions of agents to understand how patterns emerge at the population level. Such models have been used to study segregation dynamics (Schelling, Reference Schelling1971), the emergence of cooperation (Axelrod & Hamilton, Reference Axelrod and Hamilton1981), the evolution of language (Centola et al., Reference Centola, Gonzalez-Avella, Eguiluz and San Miguel2007; Kirby et al., Reference Kirby, Griffiths and Smith2014) and network dynamics (Segovia-Martín et al., Reference Segovia-Martín, Walker, Fay and Tamariz2020), and to adjudicate between competing explanations for biocultural phenomena like footbinding (Chowdhury et al., Reference Chowdhury, Zhang and Nichols2022).

The second class is composed of macro-scale models, which attempt to capture the overall behaviour of the system. Macro-scale models may consist of ordinary or partial differential equations that contain one or more functions with their derivatives. In this context, the functions represent quantities (e.g. populations A and B), the derivatives define their rates of change and the equation defines the relationship between both variables. These models have been used to study topics such as language competition (Abrams & Strogatz, Reference Abrams and Strogatz2003), political competition (Misra, Reference Misra2012), the evolution of religiosity (Rowthorn, Reference Rowthorn2011), the distribution of cultural traits (Manrubia & Zanette, Reference Manrubia and Zanette2002) and innovation (Kandler & Laland, Reference Kandler and Laland2009), among other social issues (see Brown, Reference Brown2007). Other macro-models, such as phylogenetic or statistical inference models, are oriented to encompass the broader evolutionary relationships between organisms and groups using existing experimental, historical and archaeological data (Turchin et al., Reference Turchin, Whitehouse, Francois, Slingerland and Collard2012).

An appreciable challenge facing the use of modelling to draw substantive inferences about actual cultural processes is that varied costs involved in selection of a framework and a scale for analysis often limit the inferential range of the model's results. Micro-scale models allow more control over the properties of individual entities in the system, generally at the expense of higher computational cost and greater complexity of formalization, which limits their reproducibility and generalizability. Macro-scale models, on the other hand, allow greater control over population variables and the evaluation and formalization of the dynamical system, although at the cost of a lack of control over the individual entities of the system. From these two types of models emerged a general theoretical concern over how to integrate their results.

Of very special consideration in models of cultural evolution is the development of techniques to represent multivariate causal interactions between phenomena at both micro- and macro-levels, e.g. the ‘ratchet effect’ (Tennie et al., Reference Tennie, Call and Tomasello2009), often regarded as indispensable for explaining cumulative cultural evolution. Recent formal developments enabling the combination of micro- and macro-models are allowing modellers to meet this need and, consequently, they will stimulate high-quality research in CES and assist in overcoming challenge (C3). Micro- and macro-models can be combined by building adaptive dynamics models or with multilevel selection models where both events at the individual level generate effects at the group level and events at the group level affect the individual properties of the system (Mullon & Lehmann, Reference Mullon and Lehmann2017; Fishwick, Reference Fishwick1995; McElreath & Henrich, Reference McElreath, Henrich, Barrett and Dunbar2007; Waring et al., Reference Waring, Goff and Smaldino2017; Segovia-Martin & Tamariz, Reference Segovia-Martin and Tamariz2021). This represents the future of modelling in cultural evolution, but it is not itself without challenges.

Despite numerous advantages, joint micro-macro models are now confronting novel theoretical problems. These include reconciling the role of individual-level behaviours with aggregate-level phenomena; addressing emergent properties that cannot be explained by the actions of individual agents alone; accounting for feedback loops between the micro- and macro-levels; and specifying the content, behavioural influence and population-level effects of ‘regulatory traits’, i.e. traits governing cultural transmission of other traits (Acerbi et al., Reference Acerbi, Ghirlanda, Enquist, Cagnoni, Mirolli and Villani2014). Given their content, progress on these problems would benefit from formal analyses of concepts like collective action, coercion and institutions, which would facilitate operationalization in models.

4.2. Experiments in cultural evolution

Challenge (C3) focuses on the need to overcome several problems facing the effort to model culture as a complex, adaptive system. In their report of survey results, authors wisely distinguish this from a corollary challenge, (C4), which involves the need to develop an evidential bridge between modelling results and research on the psycho-social mechanisms instantiating cultural transmission in the world. Given the ascendant place of modelling in CES, validating models against data from experiments and field studies has remained a persistent challenge. This challenge for CES typically has one of four points of inception: (i) a lack of data, making validation unfeasible; (ii) a conceptual gulf between model and empirical data; (iii) limitations of the model's ability to properly describe new, previously unseen data; and (iv) a lack of parallelism between model mechanisms and actual mechanisms, making models of little use in capturing the causal interactions between real evolutionary processes (see Weisberg, Reference Weisberg2007, on assignment, scope and fidelity). Mechanisms for cultural evolution like social learning biases have of course been proposed (Boyd & Richerson, Reference Boyd and Richerson1985), modelled (Denton et al., Reference Denton, Ram, Liberman and Feldman2020) and experimented upon (Efferson et al., Reference Efferson, Lalive, Richerson, Mcelreath and Lubell2008). Yet CES nonetheless faces several problems integrating theory and modelling with experimentation often owing to the absence of a set of criteria for a measurable outcome that is commensurable across methods.

Take, for example, research that frames lab- and field-based experiments (see Mesoudi & Whiten, Reference Mesoudi and Whiten2008 and Tamariz, Reference Tamariz2017 for reviews). Cultural transmission has been a focus of laboratory experiments, many of which examine whether or not some of the postulated learning biases exist. Other studies pit multiple learning biases against each other to assess which are more powerful explanations of cultural retention and transmission. While some experiments focus on biased social learning, including, among others, content- (e.g. Boyer & Ramble, Reference Boyer and Ramble2001; Broesch et al., Reference Broesch, Barrett and Henrich2014) and prestige-biased cultural transmission (e.g. Jiménez & Mesoudi, Reference Jiménez and Mesoudi2019) in the retention and recall of stimuli, others utilize sequential transmission chains to examine ostensibly unique properties of human cultural evolution such as cumulative evolution and problem-solving (e.g. Caldwell & Millen, Reference Caldwell and Millen2008; Jiménez & Mesoudi, Reference Jiménez and Mesoudi2020). In step with the classic experiments of Bartlett (Reference Bartlett1932), many of these studies follow the logic and structure of ‘telephone’, a game that exploits distortion of information across chains of multiple learner-teachers. Other experiments stress communication and group coordination through actively and collectively aligning individual behaviours, such as drumming and movement, and examining downstream behaviour (e.g. Tunçgenç & Cohen, Reference Tunçgenç and Cohen2016; Wood et al., Reference Wood, Caldwell-Harris and Stopa2018). Aptly, but unsystematically, the range of participants’ agency varies significantly across cultural transmission experiments. This also applies to studies of cultural evolution in non-human animals, where a variety of evidence stemming from controlled experiments and anchored in social learning models has been observed (Whiten, Reference Whiten2019).

Much of the behavioural experimental work that falls under the rubric of cultural evolution assesses the magnitude and scope of cooperation that is unique to our species. By measuring individual decisions in allocating money and other resources, experiments in cross-cultural behavioural economics suggest that culture and cultural institutions play a significant role in promoting more cooperative strategies (Pisor et al., Reference Pisor, Gervais, Purzycki and Ross2020) or, less appreciated in CES, in reducing cooperation (cf. Akbari et al., Reference Akbari, Bahrami-Rad and Kimbrough2019). Studies that deploy the same experimental game but have culturally salient treatment conditions show that when made culturally relevant, salient beliefs and values can alter the course of interpersonal behaviour (Cronk, Reference Cronk2007; Gerkey, Reference Gerkey2013; Lightner et al., Reference Lightner, Barclay and Hagen2017). In such experiments, the outcome variable is cooperation, not whatever cultural information that is purportedly inducing it, and certainly not the transmission of such cultural information. Yet some paradigms have exploited such experiments, and rather than using beliefs and cultural framings to predict behaviour, some have reversed this structure and examined how game outcomes can predictably shift the content and structure of extant beliefs (Purzycki et al., Reference Purzycki, Stagnaro and Sasaki2020). Neither of these experimental paradigms directly speaks to transmission, however; one seeks to explain the evolution of cooperation and the other seeks to explain the evolution of beliefs as responses to threats to cooperation.

While the ultimate theory that motivates such studies posits that cultural norms can co-evolve with problems of cooperation, there remains a notable deficit in just how little of this work specifically attends to cultural transmission and the co-variation between cooperation and tradition. Experiments about variability of dynamics in transmission across cultures are infrequently motivated by integration with cross-cultural psychology and so, albeit with exceptions (e.g. Mesoudi et al., Reference Mesoudi, Chang, Murray and Lu2014, which found significant cross-cultural variation in the adoption rate of success-based social copying), they generally do not motivate or test explicit hypotheses about cultural differences in transmission. Many such studies might assess the cultural mechanisms that promote or reduce cooperation but do nothing in the way of accounting for the diffusion or maintenance of such beliefs. In other words, while we might see co-varying effects of cultural information and behaviour in the lab, and while this might make certain explanations or theories more plausible, it remains unclear what this has to do with the evolution and persistence of the cultural part of the dynamics. Are particular cultural strains prevalent because they promote (or reduce) cooperation? Do the social benefits of cooperation contribute to the prevalence and maintenance of particular cultural mechanisms? Such questions are ripe for serious experimental treatment, and returning to challenge (C4), the results of such experiments are expected to inform representations of subtle, varied causal interactions in future micro–macro models.

4.3. Field studies

Field studies fall into various kinds. Ethological field studies concern cultural performances beyond our species. Archaeological and palaeoanthropological excavations provide insight into the deep past and into the emergence of cultural evolution of hominins from australopithecines and different Homo species up to anatomically modern humans. Anthropological field studies, often separated into cultural anthropology and evolutionary anthropology, examine social and material interactions in present-day human groups and societies and their cultural products. Although these three fields differ markedly in the nature and acquisition of their basic data as well as in their theoretical presuppositions, they share important commonalities. Key features of all three approaches are: adoption of long-term data collection methods and analysis; attention to facts about the material, ecological and behavioural contexts of cultural behaviours; and interest in identifying a potential variety of contributing elements. Field studies in CES aim to gain a broad overview of cultural performances and their environmental conditions, and to examine the differences between distinct social and ecological settings in order to increase understanding of the historical and biological circumstances of cultural evolution. Field studies in CES incorporate fuzzy evidence about multi-faceted entanglements between agents, environments and behaviours, captured with a variety of data types ranging from anecdotal reports to behaviour coding to structured research protocols, within which meaningful patterns of relations and development can be detected.

Field studies have played and will continue to play the most prominent role in CES responses to challenge (C8), which encompass the need to convince policymakers of the need to conserve animal cultures. Until the second half of the twentieth century, culture had only been ascribed to humans. Since the expansion of the definition of culture to make it applicable to non-human animals (McGrew, Reference McGrew1992), and subsequent studies on behavioural traditions in chimpanzees (Whiten et al., Reference Whiten, Goodall, McGrew, Nishida, Reynolds, Sugiyama and Boesch1999), which combined field research from several groups in search of differences of occurrences of behaviour across sites under similar environmental conditions, ethological field studies with cultural evolutionary scope have been on the rise. The variety of animal species examined as well as evidence of performances with basic cultural features have markedly increased. Ethological research has produced studies on the pace of animal innovations, as found in seasonal changes in songs of humpback whales (Schulze et al., Reference Schulze, Denkinger, Oña, Poole and Garland2022), on cultural transmission in the manufacture of tools, as in New Caledonian crows (Hunt & Gray, Reference Hunt and Gray2003), and on the adoption of new behavioural elements from resident individuals when they must adapt to new habitats after dispersal, as in male orangutans (Mörchen et al., Reference Mörchen, Luhn, Wassmer, Kunz, Kulik, Noordwijk and Schuppli2023). The current state of the field suggests that there is a variety of basic cultural performances in a wide array of animal orders from invertebrates to birds and mammals (Whiten, Reference Whiten2021) and that the number of (unspecified) cases of ‘culture’ is underestimated (Schuppli & Van Schaik, Reference Schuppli and Van Schaik2019).

In contrast to field studies on animal behaviour and ethnography, which include direct observations of performances, primary data from archaeological field studies provide only indirect insights into past human behaviour through trace material evidence. Performances, and thus also group-specific patterns and their development, must be inferred from finds via multiple analytical steps before interpretation (Perrault, Reference Perrault2019). The chronological frame of archaeological field studies spans more than 3 million years. Research focused on distinct spans of time within this epochal stretch has enabled data collection from the material record to respond to quite different questions about cultural evolutionary processes. Inspired by behavioural studies on animals, evolutionary archaeological research focusing on an early phase up to 500,000 years ago (Shennan, Reference Shennan2008) is dominated by the distinction of primate and hominin cultural capacities (Tennie et al., Reference Tennie, Premo, Braun and McPherron2017), long-lasting technical traditions and convergent evolution in technologies (O'Brien et al., Reference O'Brien, Buchanan and Eren2018), and the development of simple stages of communication and cooperation (Gärdenfors & Högberg, Reference Gärdenfors and Högberg2017). For a middle phase between 500,000 and 100,000 years ago, the research focus shifts to the study of evidence for the increasing complexity of technical expressions (Lombard & Haidle, Reference Lombard and Haidle2012) and the necessity of advanced forms of cultural transmission (Stolarczyk & Schmidt, Reference Stolarczyk and Schmidt2018), group structures and the advent of ritual behaviour (Dapschauskas et al., Reference Dapschauskas, Göden, Sommer and Kandel2022). In a late phase from 100,000 years on, relations of techno-complexes and social systems as well as the development of group identities (Vanhaeren & d'Errico, Reference Vanhaeren and d'Errico2006) and belief systems become increasingly important. The analysis of spatial, material and social networks and their dynamics (Mills, Reference Mills2017) aligns with other anthropological approaches to questions about the biocultural evolution of our species.

Ethnographic field studies are a major means for collecting data within cultural anthropological research. Although the method of participant-observation has well-known limitations (Howell, Reference Howell and Stein2018), this is not the only tool in the anthropological tool kit. Complementing participant-observation are long-term and open-ended participatory methods that allow for individuals within the studied population to speak for themselves. Alongside these are tools like qualitative and structured interviews, genealogy and network analyses (Beer & König, Reference Beer and König2020; Seligmann & Estes, Reference Seligmann and Estes2020). Ethnology, the comparative study of peoples, represents another approach to answering canonical CES-inspired questions under the field study umbrella. Although ethnology has also long been subject to critique, it has never been absent from anthropological research (Schnegg, Reference Schnegg2014). More recently, comparative methods have become supercharged by the increased accumulation and availability of cross-cultural data together with rigorous comparative methods (Fox & Gingrich, Reference Fox and Gingrich2002). Such methods are now applied to a broad anthropological domain, expanded by inclusion of urban settings, the digital world and specific groups (e.g. professional, religious, gender) within larger communities. With a growing interest in the universality of human rights (Nagengast, Reference Nagengast1997), relations of performance and cognition (Antweiler, Reference Antweiler, Meusburger, Freytag and Suarsana2016), and the origins and evolution of broader concepts such as religion and morality (Purzycki et al., Reference Purzycki, Henrich, Apicella, Atkinson, Baimel, Cohen and Norenzayan2018), more universal perspectives have been taken.

Contributions of evolutionary anthropology (EA) and its sister, human behavioural ecology (HBE) (differences between which are left aside here) prize coherence with other methods of knowledge discovery and prioritize theoretical relations to natural selection. Unlike some areas of evolutionary science, work in EA and HBE generally avoids optimality assumptions that often characterize evolutionary psychology (about this see Fessler et al., Reference Fessler, Clark, Clint and Buss2016: 1030). The frameworks of EA and HBE occupy an unusually high-traffic crossroads within CES and, to extend the analogy, these crossroads are located near wide bridges traversing the waters between cultural and biological evolution. Despite their pluralistic use of methods and their ecumenical approach to research questions, EA and HBE are unified by the assumption, put roughly, that concepts from evolutionary biology have considerable utility in explanations of gene–culture co-evolutionary phenomena. Evolutionary anthropologists might study modifications of the hip, pelvis and spine revealed in the hominin archaeological record (Lovejoy, Reference Lovejoy2005a, Reference Lovejoyb), or information about ancestral pathogen loads across regions in relation to present-day, culturally variable social psychological traits (Fincher et al., Reference Fincher, Thornhill, Murray and Schaller2008; Faulkner et al., Reference Faulkner, Schaller, Park and Duncan2004). Modifications of the hominin body plan supporting bipedality, and cross-cultural variation in social-psychological factors in relation to pathogen load, are hypothesized to result, in the end, from their consequences on biological fitness. The ready explanatory pluralism of HBE and EA has probably contributed to their nuanced awareness of evolutionary trade-offs at play across human life history, e.g. between current and future reproduction and quantity and quality of offspring (Hill & Kaplan, Reference Hill and Kaplan1999); their attention to both uniformity and difference between primate ‘proto-shame’ and human shame systems (Fessler, Reference Fessler, Tracy, Robins and Tangney2007); and their pleasing, simultaneous concern with multiple dimensions of a single scientific explanation, dimensions such as physical realization, causation and phylogeny, which are often treated autonomously elsewhere in CES.

Working with results of field studies in the context of findings from elsewhere in CES makes a special contribution to challenges about knowledge synthesis and interdisciplinary integration (C5). This is not least because it is in the form of field studies that the bulk of research on non-human culture occurs. Operationalizing the culture concept across archaeology, biological anthropology and ethology, and applying it to behaviourally modern humans, earlier humans and non-humans, each requires improvements to this common but coarse-grained concept. Without more unanimity on the culture concept, survey results suggest that ‘siloing’ will continue (on the problems of disciplinary ‘siloing’ see Brewer et al., Reference Brewer, Gelfand, Jackson, MacDonald, Peregrine and Richerson2017: 2). Perhaps, for example, a law-like systematicity links the roles that social learning plays in the transmission of behavioural traits within different animal species and within hominin groups, but the underlying theory and methods issues have yet to be adequately resolved to support law-like cross-species generalizations about necessary conditions for the ontogeny of culture.

5. Unresolved theoretical issues in specific areas of cultural evolutionary science

In this section we focus on theoretical challenges faced in two core areas of CES: culture in other animals, and languages as culturally evolving systems. Our goal is just to show, with specific examples, that many unanswered or poorly framed scientific questions in cultural evolution would benefit from attention to theory.

5.1. Culture in other animals

The existence of behavioural traditions passing (not necessarily replicating) between generations through social learning in animals – a working characterization of ’culture’ – is now uncontroversial. As a result, questions of interest to researchers have moved to focus on the mechanisms that support cultural transmission in animals, and questions about the methods with which animal cultures are studied. Answers to these questions can tell us whether human forms of culture – not least cumulative culture – are likely to be found in the animal kingdom.

Historically, animal cultures have been studied via the ‘method of exclusion’ (Whiten et al., Reference Whiten, Goodall, McGrew, Nishida, Reynolds, Sugiyama and Boesch1999; later refined by Langergraber et al., Reference Langergraber, Boesch, Inoue, Inoue-Murayama, Mitani, Nishida and Vigilant2011). This identifies behavioural patterns as cultural when they differ between geographically diverse groups of the same species. If genetic differences between these groups can be ruled out (e.g. because of inter-group migration), and behavioural differences cannot be attributed to local ecological conditions, then behavioural patterns are likely to be products of social learning – and so are indicative of variant cultural traditions. While influential, this method has been criticized as insufficiently informative, and as resting on a conceptual problem, specifically a false dichotomy between nature and culture (Rogoff, Reference Rogoff2003). First, it probably undercounts culture, where behaviours are universal (and so do not differ between populations) but are nonetheless socially learned. Second, it gives no insight into the kinds of social learning mechanisms that support cultural transmission (Sterelny, Reference Sterelny, Laland and Galef2009; Acerbi et al., Reference Acerbi, Snyder and Tennie2022). This criticism is important because some higher fidelity social learning processes, such as imitation (aka ‘process copying’ Buskell & Tennie, Reference Buskell and Tennie2022, or ‘know-how copying’ Tennie, Reference Tennie2023), are thought to play an important (if not always necessary) role in the emergence of cumulative culture (Tennie et al., Reference Tennie, Call and Tomasello2009; Moore, Reference Moore2013). These may be missing in other species, or too inconsequential to produce and maintain similar cultures.

Tennie and colleagues have developed a series of paradigms designed to test whether putatively cultural behaviours in our nearest relatives, the great apes, are a product of imitation. Early paradigms established that chimpanzees do not acquire behaviours whose transmission requires high-fidelity transmission chains (Tennie et al., Reference Tennie, Call and Tomasello2009). More recent studies show that many great ape behaviours can be explained as products of serial reinvention (often through trial-and-error learning) (e.g. Bandini et al., Reference Bandini, Grossmann, Funk, Albiach-Serrano and Tennie2021). Since naïve apes spontaneously reinvent these behaviours when left alone with the necessary apparatus, they cannot depend on social learning. Tennie and colleagues call these behaviours ‘latent solutions’. They do not deny that some forms of social learning support the transmission of great ape behaviours (Tennie et al., Reference Tennie, Bandini, Van Schaik and Hopper2020). However, they argue that great apes do not copy new forms of ‘know-how’ from peers. Rather, for the most part, great ape social learning occurs because features of the environment are made salient through the actions of others. On this account, the presence of others in a learning environment is conceived of as a ‘probabilistic difference maker’ (Scarantino, Reference Scarantino2015): a non-essential but nonetheless causally significant factor. It may facilitate the acquisition of behaviours without being essential for their development.

While it should now be uncontroversial that great apes do not, in their natural habitat, engage in high-fidelity know-how copying, the finding that great apes can learn to imitate (e.g. Pope et al., Reference Pope, Taglialatela and Hopkins2017) raises the question of whether their lack of imitation is itself a product of their developmental environment, and so potentially a culturally evolved ‘cognitive gadget’ (Heyes, Reference Heyes2018). Nonetheless, even trained apes seem unable to retain cultural inventions over successive generations (Tennie, Reference Tennie2019). This means that chimpanzees must often reinvent their ancestors’ technologies in ways that human communities need not, and explains why cumulative culture is rare, at best, in great ape communities. Tentative reports of cumulative culture in whales and monkeys suggest that further empirical research is needed to determine whether and how animal cultures can gain in complexity over time. Theoretical research specifying what would constitute evidence of cumulative culture (and how ‘acultural’ explanations from natural selection would be ruled out) must precede or at least accompany additional field studies. A valuable contribution by theoreticians here would be to assist in fixing the social and cognitive conditions that are necessary and sufficient for cumulative culture, and by developing hypotheses about the kinds of mechanistic changes that support the development of higher fidelity social learning in non-human animals (Berio & Moore, Reference Berio and Moore2023).

A final question asks whether non-human animals, and especially apes, are capable of understanding norms. Norm cognition is taken to be a prerequisite of many of our culturally evolved social institutions (e.g. institutions of justice). While some are sceptical that norm cognition is present in great apes (Schlingloff & Moore, Reference Schlingloff and Moore2017), others have argued that this scepticism is driven by an intellectualized account of the cognition required for normativity, suggesting a need for minimal models of norm cognition (Westra & Andrews, Reference Westra and Andrews2022). A further obstacle remains for investigating norm cognition in animals. The best method for identifying norms is through third party enforcement of perceived norm violations – and this is strikingly absent from great apes (Schlingloff & Moore, Reference Schlingloff and Moore2017). The theoretical formulation of alternative methods for identifying normative behaviours would thus constitute a valuable contribution to the field.

5.2. Languages as culturally evolving systems

Until not long ago, discussion of language ‘evolution’ was somewhat taboo. As recent as 1994, textbooks observed that ‘Evolution … has become a “dirty word” in modern linguistic theory’ (McMahon, Reference McMahon1994: 314). This is because through the twentieth century the nomenclature of evolution risked some allusion to outdated, often racist, views about how some languages – and by extension some social groups – might be ‘more evolved’ than others. It is now uncontroversial within linguistics that no language is inherently ‘better’ or ‘more useful’ than others. So, while vigilance must be maintained, the socio-political risks associated with evolutionary talk have begun to fade, and in the past 30 or so years evolutionary approaches to languages have grown dramatically in prominence (Tallerman & Gibson, Reference Tallerman and Gibson2011; Dediu & de Boer, Reference Dediu and de Boer2016).

Today, the expression ‘language evolution’ is widely used to describe at least two distinct phenomena and one methodological advance. The two phenomena are: the biological process by which humans, and apparently only humans, became a ’language-ready’ species; and the set of cultural – or ‘cultural evolutionary’ – processes by which relatively simple and unstructured systems become highly structured, and hence acquire some of the common, characteristic properties of languages, such as symbolism, compositionality and duality of patterning. The methodological advance is the application of phylogenetic tools, derived from population genetics, to study language history and language change. All three of these literatures are now very large, comprising thousands of papers each. Multiple past papers review, summarize and synthesize them (e.g. Mace & Holden, Reference Mace and Holden2005; Tomasello & Call, Reference Tomasello and Call2019; Greenhill et al., Reference Greenhill, Heggarty and Gray2020; Haspelmath, Reference Haspelmath2020; Roberts & Sneller, Reference Roberts and Sneller2020; Scott-Phillips & Heintz, Reference Scott-Phillips and Heintz2023; Scott-Phillips & Kirby, Reference Scott-Phillips and Kirby2010). Here we focus on a philosophical issue arising from this growing influence of evolutionary thinking.

The challenge, put simply, is: what exactly does the evolutionary perspective bring that other approaches do not? The biology of language, language emergence and language change have all been important topics for language science for a long time, and a great deal of what has been uncovered by evolutionary approaches has previously been investigated and described in other terms. Research adopting an evolutionary perspective has enriched our understanding, provided new methods and added many new findings, but does it fundamentally alter our understanding of what the empirical phenomenon is and how it works?

One answer might be that a relatively faithful transposition of the Darwinian model – where variation, selection and inheritance combine to generate natural selection and hence the appearance of design in nature – is possible, and brings with it new insights, explanations and tools. With languages, there is something like variation (linguistic items vary enormously), there is something like selection (some items become more common than others) and there is something like inheritance (we learn from the previous generation). Some linguists indeed propose that linguistic items, of some sort or another, could be identified as units of selection closely analogous to genes (e.g. Croft, Reference Croft2008; Ritt, Reference Ritt2004; Tamariz, Reference Tamariz2019). However, deeper analysis raises difficult questions, and the issue is contentious: a decade ago, a group paper on language as a culturally evolving system observed that, ‘Various scholars have proposed that concepts, cultural behaviors, or artifacts may function as replicators. It remains to be seen whether any, all, or some combination of these entities are reasonable candidates for cultural replicators’ (Dediu et al., Reference Dediu, Cysouw, Levinson, Baronchelli, Christiansen, Croft and Lieven2013: 314). The situation has not changed substantially since.

Another response to this question would be to adopt only specific parts of the Darwinian toolkit. That is, one could reduce the role of an analogy between variation in language and variation in genes while retaining other parts of Darwinism (Claidière et al., Reference Claidière, Scott-Phillips and Sperber2014). For instance, there might be scope for perspectives that adopt population thinking and some commitment to selectionism, but without the stronger commitment to replicators.

Languages are arguably the cultural domain par excellence for population thinking because languages are, more than any other cultural phenomena, especially amenable to ‘atomization’ – to being studied in terms of discrete items – and hence to identification and analysis of the types and their changing frequencies over time. As such, an emergent and pressing theoretical question is: how best can linguistic types and tokens be precisely identified to facilitate cultural evolutionary study and modelling? Constructionist approaches to grammar, which describe grammars as networks of form–function pairs (Goldberg, Reference Goldberg2003; Hilpert, Reference Hilpert2014, inter alia), may be especially suitable for this goal. However, because there is little research developing this idea, treating constructions as the targets of population thinking (partial exceptions are Kirby, Reference Kirby1999; Steels, Reference Steels2016) remains necessary.

6. Implications and applications of CET

The authors of the Cultural Evolution Society's report of survey results stated that one grand challenge involves the identification and study of cultural evolutionary processes that address ‘significant social, economic, and political problems’ (Brewer et al. Reference Brewer, Gelfand, Jackson, MacDonald, Peregrine and Richerson2017: 3), challenge (C8), which explicitly mentions climate change as an example. A growing number of scientists have begun focusing on such practical implications of CES, often concerning the role of norms. We define ‘norms’ as the shared values and rules that are enforced within a group, and which we contrast with the individual values or preferences of members. Reward and punishment are the basic means by which political entities and groups exert control over their members, organize them into roles and maintain order. For instance, reliable enforcement of norms against harming others reduces mutual fear among group members, making it easier to live together and making it more likely that individuals will survive. Indeed, from the perspective of both genetic and cultural evolution, theorists converge on cooperation and coordination as the general function of norms. Thus, practical implications of CES on social, economic and political challenges often concern the importance of norms in social life, yet coarse-grained concepts like norm or cooperation norm fall into the general conceptual problem mentioned above. Although modellers and experimentalists often refer to ‘norms’, the precise conditions under which norms (let alone different types of norms) are psychologically instantiated have yet to be perspicaciously individuated.

Adopting one approach to human cooperation defended within CES (Boyd & Richerson, Reference Boyd and Richerson2009), philosophers Sripada and Stich (Reference Sripada and Stich2006) attempted to address this challenge with the development of a theory of norm psychology that distinguishes between intrinsic and instrumental psychological motivations to follow and enforce norms. Instrumental motives focus on gaining rewards and avoiding punishment, while intrinsic motives concern the rightness or wrongness of an act itself, independently of any punishment or reward. A desire to comply with the speed limit may be instrumentally motivated, as a desire to avoid being fined as punishment, or it may be intrinsically motivated, as a desire to avoid doing something wrong by putting others at risk. Both motives can occur simultaneously, but research suggests that these are distinct functional capacities, with distinct inputs and outputs, and distinct ontogenies. Intrinsic motivations to follow norms evolved specifically in response to the adaptive problems posed by norm enforcement (Chudek & Henrich, Reference Chudek and Henrich2011), so they could only have evolved quite recently, presumably after cultural learning capacities became sophisticated enough to support the widespread sharing of enforcement practices. This is neither the history nor the function of the various instrumental motivations involved in norm compliance, such as desire for social status, fear of pain, concern for mating prospects, the role of self-interest, etc. With a formal analysis of norms in hand, CES researchers could better test implications hypothesized to follow from one or another type of norm.

Davis et al. (Reference Davis, Hennes and Raymond2018) opened up this research by studying the intrinsic–instrumental motivational distinction as it operates within the sustainability movement. They discovered that too little attention is paid to the potential of intrinsic motives, and suggested clear ways to test the strength and frequency of intrinsic motives, and subsequently, methods to increase intrinsic motivation. Similarly, Kline et al. (Reference Kline, Waring and Salerno2018) use the same theoretical framework to examine group structure and organization by analysing the norms of groups, organizations and institutions involved in suppressing free riding in sustainability contexts. For this they introduce novel models of cultural multilevel selection that address the competing pressures operating at different levels or scales of social organization. These attempts to apply CET to sustainability concerns have met with some uptake among practitioners in civil engineering, who face problems of free riding addressed at multiple levels of government. Hydrologists modelling social-ecological systems have urged the adoption of a norm psychology framework informed by CES findings to address cooperation problems surrounding water scarcity and conservation (Yu et al., Reference Yu, Chang, Davis, Hillis, Marston, Oh and Waring2020).

The use of CET in sustainability science represents little more than proof of concept for the potential value of applying results in CES, and it is important not to dress old solutions up in the clothes of new theories (Chellappoo, Reference Chellappoo2022b). However, the case also illustrates a broader strategy of focusing theoretically perspicacious CES research upon norm-based social ills. For instance, as norms of democracy have come under threat from authoritarianism around the world (Norris & Inglehart, Reference Norris and Inglehart2019), it has become salient that commitments to the rightness of democracy itself really matter. Without them, voters and officials often use their democratic powers to make governments less democratic or non-democratic. Addressing this problem requires the internalization of democratic norms, not instrumental reasons for following them. Another important form of intervention focuses on cases where conflicting norms exist in an equilibrium within a population. In such contexts changing the minds of a relatively small portion of the population can serve as a tipping point, initiating a cascade that quickly shifts the rest of the population to one side of the conflict (Andreoni et al., Reference Andreoni, Nikiforakis and Siegenthaler2021). Against this background, Vogt et al. (Reference Vogt, Mohmmed Zaid, Ahmed, Fehr and & Efferson2016) elegantly show how entertainment programming can be effective in shifting a few people's attitudes in one direction. In Sudan, they carefully embedded arguments against female genital cutting within a controlled series of telenovelas and found that viewers’ attitudes toward uncut girls substantially improved. The demonstrably effective use of CES research to exploit mechanisms of cultural transmission to alter norms, and through them behaviour, augurs its own problems and might be received too optimistically (Wilson, Reference Wilson2011). This represents just one of several areas of CES in which knotty moral questions are rapidly arising, in this case about the role of CES in generating findings that allow political, corporate or military leaders to more effectively seed swiftly spreading, behaviour-altering cultural content through social and electronic media.

In addition to practical implications on individual attitudes and behaviours, cultural evolutionary processes have indelibly influenced human nature, for example by making human nature especially ‘open-ended’ (see Section 3 above), a continuing avenue for future CES and CET research (Hannon & Lewens, Reference Hannon and Lewens2018; Ramsey, Reference Ramsey2023). According to Kern and Moll (Reference Kern and Moll2017), the evolution of capacities for shared intentionality has transformed our species. Humans are the only species whose members have an awareness of themselves as embodying a unique, collectively structured form of life. The fact that culture accumulates over historical time has exerted remarkable effects on humans’ understanding of self and other. There appears to be a sharp division between species whose culture ‘ratchets up’ in the way human culture does, and others, whose behavioural patterns are not preserved across generations. Importantly, with the dawn of cultural evolutionary processes, humans developed a consciousness of themselves as being part of a community whose members are interdependent in their learning (Moll & Kern, Reference Moll and Kern2020; Moll, Reference Moll2020). Bjorklund (Reference Bjorklund2021) and other evo-devo scholars argue that what most drastically changed over the course of human evolution is our ontogeny, i.e. the processes by which we become mature individuals. We claim that hominin ontogeny was transformed such that children began to take a vested interest in their social learning and started to turn to adults as models and teachers. Adults, likewise, developed awareness of their role as teachers and authorities. Csibra and Gergely (Reference Csibra and Gergely2009, Reference Csibra and Gergely2011) have discussed the evolution of a unique pedagogical communication system, whereby adults signal to learners their intent to transmit knowledge to them, and, in response, learners adopt a learning stance in which they assume the general relevance of what they are being shown or taught. Parents and their offspring thus not only became interdependent in unique ways but also developed an awareness of their interdependence and of their need to cooperate within a transmission system that serves to preserve lifeways that would otherwise disappear. This points to a possible constraint on cumulative cultural evolution worthy of further reflection: for culture to get preserved cross-generationally, there had to be a transformation in the cognitive apparatus and in the self-representation of the agents who are at once the ‘movers’ and ‘recipients’ of this process.

7. Conclusion

Although our review is broad, the field of cultural evolution is broader still, and several key areas and pressing problems were not adequately discussed above. We conclude by emphasizing two problems lurking near the ungainly relationship between cultural and biological evolution voiced in challenge (C2).

Since genes are fundamental units of selection in biological evolution, improving the relation between cultural and biological evolution, and integrating results across fields of inquiry inclusive of biology (see (C4) above), may necessitate increasing use of genetics research in CES. Scientists in cultural genomics research have identified countless neuro-functional differences across descent groups relevant for emotion and cognition at the levels of individuals and groups (Han, Reference Han2017; Chen & Moyzis, Reference Chen and Moyzis2018). A recent, thorough review of genetic contributions to ‘moral performance’ found allelic variation in polymorphic genes linked to culturally characterizable descent groups. Functions of these polymorphisms related to neurohormone support, prosocial behaviour and aggressive behaviour. These neurohormones included oxytocin (regulated via polymorphic genes OXTR and CD38), dopamine (via COMPT, DRD3 and DRD4), serotonin (via TPH2 and 5-HTTLPR) and testosterone (via AR) (Wang & Su, Reference Wang, Su and Nichols2022). Many moral cautions and epistemological objections accompany the use of gene × culture data, as they should. This area has met with its share of methodological missteps. For example, Chiao and Blizinsky's (Reference Chiao and Blizinsky2010) remarkable finding of a strong statistical relation between the ratio of several distinct serotonin transporter polymorphisms distributed across descent groups with the position of specific groups on the individualism–collectivism spectrum led authors to explain the relationship as a case of culturally infused biological selection. This result was subsequently invalidated (Eisenberg & Hayes, Reference Eisenberg and Hayes2011). Even so, many findings in this field appear well warranted. Indeed, the statistical relationship just mentioned was later largely vindicated by Chiao, Blizinsky and co-authors through retesting on a much larger sample inclusive of not only European and East Asian but also African samples (Mrazek et al., Reference Mrazek, Chiao, Blizinsky, Lun and Gelfand2013). We surmise that growth in this subfield is hindered by uncertainty and possible moral hazards. Compared with fields like anthropology and zoology, whose leading academic organizations have published statements governing research ethics, as a nascent field, cultural evolution may be relatively unprepared to deal with moral challenges implicitly raised by gene × culture research. At least, problems of this kind did not register as concerns in the Cultural Evolution Society's survey results (Brewer et al., Reference Brewer, Gelfand, Jackson, MacDonald, Peregrine and Richerson2017).

We finally turn to multi-level selection. The Cultural Evolution Society survey report identifies the topic of ‘theory’ and ‘integration’ as two of the most pressing issues facing the field (Brewer et al., Reference Brewer, Gelfand, Jackson, MacDonald, Peregrine and Richerson2017: 2). This pair forcefully collides when it comes to the status of multi-level selection theory in CES and evolutionary psychology. Recent work in evolutionary psychology contends that individual-level punishment explains substantial amounts of human cooperation (Krasnow et al., Reference Krasnow, Delton, Cosmides and Tooby2015); that third-party punishment is shown to arise from defence of personal interests (Kraswow et al., Reference Krasnow, Delton, Cosmides and Tooby2016); and that the threat of targeted conspiratorial killing selected for groupishness (Wrangham, Reference Wrangham2021). Unifying these results is their support of the conclusion that biological selection on individual human organisms leads to group-level norms as by-products. These findings raise sceptical questions about the status of multi-level, especially group-level, adaptations in explanations of cooperation. Group-functional traits like language and norms are considered mere by-products of individual-level factors in evolutionary psychology (Gangestad et al., Reference Gangestad, Haselton and Buss2006, underappreciated in CES despite its authoritative authorship). In CES, though, group-level ‘traits’ are often treated as products of cultural adaptation and explanatorily irreducible to individual-level biological adaptations (Richerson et al., Reference Richerson, Baldini, Bell, Demps, Frost, Hillis and Zefferman2016). Evidence for group-level adaptations has been provided by theory (Sober & Wilson, Reference Sober and Wilson2003), modelling (Richerson et al., Reference Richerson, Baldini, Bell, Demps, Frost, Hillis and Zefferman2016) and experiment (Shariff & Norenzayan, Reference Shariff and Norenzayan2007), but it is contested.

The disputed status of group selection and problems consequent from the use of this and allied coarse-grained terms is a significant cause of the wide gap and lack of knowledge integration between CES and fields like theoretical biology and evolutionary psychology and biology. This is epitomized by Krasnow and Delton's (Reference Krasnow and Delton2016: e43) argument that CES lacks a theoretical core capable of generating unambiguous, falsifiable predictions, is overly dependent on modelling and offers merely retrodictive redescriptions of group-level traits as group adaptations. What developments could bring about a rapprochement between CES and the evolutionary human sciences? The study of evolutionary transitions in individuality holds prospects for more productive disagreement and engagement (see Carmel et al., Reference Carmel, Shavit, Lamm and Szathmáry2023 and the issue of which it is a part). A more promising approach is likely to be creatively drawing and judiciously testing entailments of inclusive fitness theory to understand culture's role in cooperation – and biology's role in culture. (Of the 18,121 publications currently recorded in Web of Science as representing the ‘topic’ of ‘cultural evolution’, a mere 47 refer to ‘inclusive fitness’, suggesting untapped potential.) We suspect that, if the influence and authority of evolutionary anthropology and human behavioural ecology, pluralistic fields capable of a wide embrace, continue to grow within CES and CET, productive steps towards greater theoretical coherence with evolutionary sciences will follow.

Acknowledgements

The authors thank the John Templeton Foundation for funding the ‘Philosophy of Science for Cultural Evolution’ virtual research network (62377; Nichols, PI), which supported the writing of this article. We thank Andrew Buskell, Tim Lewens, Grant Ramsey, Kim Sterelny, two anonymous referees and the editor of this journal for valuable commentary on previous versions. The first author thanks Justin Barrett, Alex Arnold, Bryon Cunningham, and William Melanson for insightful conversations that improved thinking represented in this paper.

Author contributions

RN acquired funding to support the article and led its composition. All authors participated in the conception of and writing of sections of the article.

Financial support

Funding was received from John Templeton Foundation grant 62377.

Conflict of interest

The authors declare none.

Research transparency and reproducibility.

n/a.

References

Abrams, D. M., & Strogatz, S. H. (2003). Modelling the dynamics of language death. Nature, 424(6951), 900900. https://doi.org/10.1038/424900aCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Acerbi, A., Ghirlanda, S., & Enquist, M. (2014). Regulatory traits: Cultural influences on cultural evolution. In Cagnoni, S., Mirolli, M., & Villani, M. (Eds.), Evolution, complexity and artificial life (pp. 135147). Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-37577-4_9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Acerbi, A., Snyder, W. D., & Tennie, C. (2022). The method of exclusion (still) cannot identify specific mechanisms of cultural inheritance. Scientific Reports, 12(1), 21680.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Akbari, M., Bahrami-Rad, D., & Kimbrough, E. O. (2019). Kinship, fractionalization and corruption. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 166, 493528. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jebo.2019.08.012CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andreoni, J., Nikiforakis, N., & Siegenthaler, S. (2021). Predicting social tipping and norm change in controlled experiments. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 118(16), e2014893118.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Antweiler, C. (2016). Local knowledge as a universal social product: A general model and a case from Southeast Asia. In Meusburger, P., Freytag, T., & Suarsana, L. (Eds.), Ethnic and cultural dimensions of knowledge (pp. 165190). Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Axelrod, R., & Hamilton, W. D. (1981). The evolution of cooperation. Science, 211(4489), 13901396. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.7466396CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bandini, E., Grossmann, J., Funk, M., Albiach-Serrano, A., & Tennie, C. (2021). Naïve orangutans (Pongo abelii and Pongo pygmaeus) individually acquire nut-cracking using hammer tool. American Journal of Primatology, 83(9), e23304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartlett, F. C. (1932). Remembering: A study in experimental and social psychology. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Beer, B., & König, A. (Eds.). (2020). Methoden ethnologischer Feldforschung. Reimer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bentley, R. A., Hahn, M. W., & Shennan, S. J. (2004). Random drift and culture change. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences, 271(1547), 14431450.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Berio, L., & Moore, R. (2023). Great ape enculturation studies: A neglected resource in cognitive development research. Biology & Philosophy, 38(2), 17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bjorklund, D. (2021). How children invented humanity. The role of development in human evolution. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Blythe, R. A. (2012). Neutral evolution: A null model for language dynamics. Advances in Complex Systems, 15(03n04), 1150015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borg, J. M., Buskell, A., Kapitany, R., Powers, S. T., Reindl, E., & Tennie, C. (2022). Evolved open-endedness in cultural evolution: A new dimension in open-ended evolution research. ArXiv Preprint ArXiv:2203.13050.Google Scholar
Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (1985). Culture and the evolutionary process. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (1996). Why culture is common, but cultural evolution is rare. Proceedings of the British Academy, 88, 7793.Google Scholar
Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (2009). Culture and the evolution of human cooperation. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 364(1533), 32813288. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2009.0134CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boyer, P., & Ramble, C. (2001). Cognitive templates for religious concepts: Cross-cultural evidence for recall of counter-intuitive representations. Cognitive Science, 25(4), 535564. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15516709cog2504_2Google Scholar
Brewer, J., Gelfand, M., Jackson, J. C., MacDonald, I. F., Peregrine, P. N., Richerson, P. J., …, Wilson, D. S. (2017). Grand challenges for the study of cultural evolution. Nature Ecology & Evolution, 1(3), 0070. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41559-017-0070CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broesch, J., Barrett, H. C., & Henrich, J. (2014). Adaptive content biases in learning about animals across the life course. Human Nature, 25, 181199. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12110-014-9191-1CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brown, C. (2007). Differential equations: A modeling approach (Vol. 150). Sage.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buskell, A. (2017). What are cultural attractors?. Biology and Philosophy, 32(3), 377394. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-017-9570-6CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Buskell, A. (2019). Looking for middle ground in cultural attraction theory. Evolutionary Anthropology: Issues, News, and Reviews, 28(1), 1417. https://doi.org/10.1002/evan.21762CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Buskell, A. (2022). Cumulative culture and complex cultural traditions. Mind & Language, 37(3), 284303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buskell, A., Enquist, M., & Jansson, F. (2019). A systems approach to cultural evolution. Palgrave Communications, 5(1), 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buskell, A., & Tennie, C. (2022). Mere recurrence and cumulative culture at the margins. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 717776. https://doi.org/10.1086/717776CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caldwell, C. A., & Millen, A. E. (2008). Experimental models for testing hypotheses about cumulative cultural evolution. Evolution and Human Behavior, 29(3), 165171. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2007.11.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carmel, Y., Shavit, A., Lamm, E., & Szathmáry, E. (2023). Human socio-cultural evolution in light of evolutionary transitions: Introduction to the theme issue. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 378(1872), 20210397. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2021.0397Google Scholar
Cavalli-Sforza, L. L., & Feldman, M. W. (1973). Cultural versus biological inheritance: Phenotypic transmission from parents to children. (A theory of the effect of parental phenotypes on children’s phenotypes). American Journal of Human Genetics, 25(6), 618637.Google ScholarPubMed
Cavalli-Sforza, L. L., & Feldman, M. W. (1981). Cultural transmission and evolution: A quantitative approach. Princeton University Press.Google ScholarPubMed
Centola, D., Gonzalez-Avella, J. C., Eguiluz, V. M., & San Miguel, M. (2007). Homophily, cultural drift, and the co-evolution of cultural groups. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 51(6), 905929.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charbonneau, M. (2015). All innovations are equal, but some more than others: (Re)integrating modification processes to the origins of cumulative culture. Biological Theory, 10(4), 322335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charbonneau, M. (2016). Modularity and recombination in technological evolution. Philosophy & Technology, 29(3), 373392.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charbonneau, M. (2020). Understanding cultural fidelity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 71(4), 12091233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charbonneau, M., & Bourrat, P. (2021). Fidelity and the grain problem in cultural evolution. Synthese, 199, 58155836.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chellappoo, A. (2021). Rethinking prestige bias. Synthese, 198(9), 81918212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chellappoo, A. (2022a). Cultural evolution: A case study in global epistemologies of science. In Ludwig, D., Koskinen, I., Mncube, Z., Poliseli, L., & Reyes-Galindo, L. (Eds.), Global epistemologies and philosophies of science (pp. 208219). Routledge.Google Scholar
Chellappoo, A. (2022b). When can cultural selection explain adaptation? Biology & Philosophy, 37(1), 2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chen, C.-Y., & Moyzis, R. K. (2018). Cultural genomics: Promises and challenges. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 49(5), 764788.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chiao, J. Y., & Blizinsky, K. D. (2010). Culture–gene coevolution of individualism–collectivism and the serotonin transporter gene. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 277(1681), 529537. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2009.1650CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chowdhury, L. S., Zhang, Y., & Nichols, R. (2022). Footbinding and its cessation: An agent-based model adjudication of the labor market and evolutionary sciences hypotheses. Evolution and Human Behavior, 43(6), 475489. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2022.08.005CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chudek, M., & Henrich, J. (2011). Culture–gene coevolution, norm-psychology and the emergence of human prosociality. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15(5), 218226.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Claidière, N., Scott-Phillips, T. C., & Sperber, D. (2014). How Darwinian is cultural evolution? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 369, 20130368.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Creanza, N., Kolodny, O., & Feldman, M. W. (2017). Cultural evolutionary theory: How culture evolves and why it matters. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 114(30), 77827789. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1620732114CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Croft, W. (2008). Evolutionary linguistics. Annual Review of Anthropology, 37, 219234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cronk, L. (2007). The influence of cultural framing on play in the trust game: A Maasai example. Evolution and Human Behavior, 28(5), 352358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2009). Natural pedagogy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(4), 148153. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2009.01.005CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2011). Natural pedagogy as evolutionary adaptation. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 366(1567), 11491157. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2010.0319CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dapschauskas, R., Göden, M. B., Sommer, C., & Kandel, A. W. (2022). The emergence of habitual ochre use in Africa and its significance for the development of ritual behavior during the Middle Stone Age. Journal of World Prehistory, 35(2), 233319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, T., Hennes, E. P., & Raymond, L. (2018). Cultural evolution of normative motivations for sustainable behaviour. Nature Sustainability, 1(5), 218224. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41893-018-0061-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawkins, R. (1989). The selfish gene (New ed). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dediu, D., Cysouw, M., Levinson, S. C., Baronchelli, A., Christiansen, M. H., Croft, W., ... Lieven, E. (2013). Cultural evolution of language. In Cultural evolution: Society, technology, language & religion. Strüngmann Forum Reports (Vol. 12, pp. 303–332). MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dediu, D., & de Boer, B. (2016). Language evolution needs its own journal. Journal of Language Evolution, 1(1), 15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (2017). From bacteria to Bach and back: The evolution of minds. WW Norton.Google Scholar
Denton, K. K., Ram, Y., Liberman, U., & Feldman, M. W. (2020). Cultural evolution of conformity and anticonformity. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 117(24), 1360313614. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2004102117CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Derex, M., Beugin, M. P., Godelle, B., & Raymond, M. (2013). Experimental evidence for the influence of group size on cultural complexity. Nature, 503(7476), 389391.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Derex, M., Godelle, B., & Raymond, M. (2014). How does competition affect the transmission of information? Evolution and Human Behavior, 35(2), 8995. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2013.11.001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Driscoll, C. (2011). Fatal attraction? Why Sperber's attractors do not prevent cumulative cultural evolution. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(2), 301322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Driscoll, C. (2017). The evolutionary culture concepts. Philosophy of Science, 84(1), 3555. https://doi.org/10.1086/688934CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Efferson, C., Lalive, R., Richerson, P., Mcelreath, R., & Lubell, M. (2008). Conformists and mavericks: The empirics of frequency-dependent cultural transmission⋆. Evolution and Human Behavior, 29(1), 5664. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2007.08.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eisenberg, D. T. A., & Hayes, M. G. (2011). Testing the null hypothesis: Comments on Culture–gene coevolution of individualism–collectivism and the serotonin transporter gene. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 278(1704), 329332. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2010.0714CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Faulkner, J., Schaller, M., Park, J. H., & Duncan, L. A. (2004). Evolved disease-avoidance mechanisms and contemporary xenophobic attitudes. Group Processes & Intergroup Relations, 7(4), 333353. https://doi.org/10.1177/1368430204046142CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, M. W., & Cavalli-Sforza, L. L. (1976). Cultural and biological evolutionary processes, selection for a trait under complex transmission. Theoretical Population Biology, 9(2), 238259. https://doi.org/10.1016/0040-5809(76)90047-2CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fessler, D. (2007). From appeasement to conformity: Evolutionary and cultural perspectives on shame, competition, and cooperation. In Tracy, J. L., Robins, R. W., & Tangney, J. P. (Eds.), The self-conscious emotions: Theory and research (pp. 174193). Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Fessler, D. M. T., Clark, J. A., & Clint, E. K. (2016). Evolutionary psychology and evolutionary anthropology. In Buss, D. M. (Ed.), The handbook of evolutionary psychology (2nd ed., Vol. 2, pp. 10291046). John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Fincher, C. L., Thornhill, R., Murray, D. R., & Schaller, M. (2008). Pathogen prevalence predicts human cross-cultural variability in individualism/collectivism. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 275(1640), 12791285. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2008.0094CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fishwick, P. A. (1995). Simulation model design and execution: Building digital worlds. Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Fox, R. G., & Gingrich, A. (Eds.). (2002). Anthropology, by comparison. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fracchia, J., & Lewontin, R. C. (1999). Does culture evolve? History and Theory, 38(4), 5278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galen, L. W. (2016). Big gods: Extended prosociality or group binding? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 39. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X15000436CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gangestad, S., Haselton, M., & Buss, D. (2006). Evolutionary foundations of cultural variation: Evoked culture and mate preferences. Psychological Inquiry, 17(2), 7595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gärdenfors, P., & Högberg, A. (2017). The archaeology of teaching and the evolution of Homo docens. Current Anthropology, 58(2), 188208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerkey, D. (2013). Cooperation in context: Public goods games and post-Soviet collectives in Kamchatka, Russia. Current Anthropology, 54(2), 144176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2001). On the status and explanatory structure of developmental systems theory. In Oyama, S., Gray, R. D., & Griffiths, P. E. (Eds.), Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution (pp. 283297). MIT Press.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2012). Darwinism and cultural change. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 367(1599), 21602170.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Goldberg, A. E. (2003). Constructions: A new theoretical approach to language. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(5), 219224.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gomes, C. M., & McCullough, M. E. (2015). The effects of implicit religious primes on dictator game allocations: A preregistered replication experiment. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 144(6), e94e104. https://doi.org/10.1037/xge0000027CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gray, R.D. and Watts, J. (2017). Cultural macroevolution matters. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 114(30), 78467852.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Greenhill, S. J., Heggarty, P., & Gray, R. D. (2020). Bayesian phylolinguistics. The handbook of historical linguistics, 2, 226253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griesemer, J. R. (1988). Genes, memes, and demes. Biology and Philosophy, 3, 179184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hagen, E. H., & Hammerstein, P. (2006). Game theory and human evolution: A critique of some recent interpretations of experimental games. Theoretical Population Biology, 69(3), 339348.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Han, S. (2017). The sociocultural brain: A cultural neuroscience approach to human nature. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hannon, E., & Lewens, T. (2018). Why we disagree about human nature (1st ed). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haspelmath, M. (2020). Human linguisticality and the building blocks of languages. Frontiers in Psychology, 10. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2019.03056CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Henrich, J. (2001). Cultural transmission and the diffusion of innovations: Adoption dynamics indicate that biased cultural transmission is the predominate force in behavioral change. American Anthropologist, 103(4), 9921013. https://doi.org/10.1525/aa.2001.103.4.992CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henrich, J. (2004). Demography and cultural evolution: How adaptive cultural processes can produce maladaptive losses – the Tasmanian case. American Antiquity, 69(02), 197214. https://doi.org/10.2307/4128416CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Derex, M., Kline, M. A., Mesoudi, A., Muthukrishna, M., …, Thomas, M. G. (2016). Understanding cumulative cultural evolution. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 113(44). https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1610005113CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Henrich, J., Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (2008). Five misunderstandings about cultural evolution. Human Nature, 19(2), 119137. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12110-008-9037-1CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Henrich, J., & McElreath, R. (2007). Dual-inheritance theory: The evolution of human cultural capacities and cultural evolution. In Barrett, L. & Dunbar, R. (Eds.), Oxford handbook of evolutionary psychology (pp. 555570). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Heyes, C. M. (2018). Cognitive gadgets: The cultural evolution of thinking. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hill, K., & Kaplan, H. (1999). Life history traits in humans: Theory and empirical studies. Annual Review of Anthropology, 28(1), 397430. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.anthro.28.1.397CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hilpert, M. (2014). Construction grammar & its application to English. Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Howell, S. (2018). Ethnography. In Stein, F. (Ed.), The open encyclopedia of anthropology. Facsimile of the first edition in The Cambridge encyclopedia of anthropology. https://doi.org/10.29164/18ethnoCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, D. L. (1988). A mechanism and its metaphysics: An evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. Biology and Philosophy, 3, 123155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hunt, G. R., & Gray, R. D. (2003). Diversification and cumulative evolution in New Caledonian crow tool manufacture. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences, 270(1517), 867874.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jiménez, Á. V., & Mesoudi, A. (2019). Prestige-biased social learning: Current evidence and outstanding questions. Palgrave Communications, 5(1), 112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jiménez, Á. V., & Mesoudi, A. (2020). Prestige does not affect the cultural transmission of novel controversial arguments in an online transmission chain experiment. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 20(3–4), 238261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, D. D. P. (2005). God's punishment and public goods: A test of the supernatural punishment hypothesis in 186 world cultures. Human Nature, 16(4), 410446. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12110-005-1017-0CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kandler, A., & Laland, K. N. (2009). An investigation of the relationship between innovation and cultural diversity. Theoretical Population Biology, 76(1), 5967.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kandler, A., Perreault, C., & Steele, J. (2012). Cultural evolution in spatially structured populations: A review of alternative modeling frameworks. Advances in Complex Systems, 15(01n02), 1203001.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelemen, D. (1999). Why are rocks pointy? Children's preference for teleological explanations of the natural world. Developmental Psychology, 35(6), 14401452. https://doi.org/10.1037/0012-1649.35.6.1440CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kern, A., & Moll, H. (2017). On the transformative character of collective intentionality and the uniqueness of the human. Philosophical Psychology, 30(3), 315333. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2017.1295648CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Killin, A., & Pain, R. (2023). How WEIRD is Cognitive Archaeology? Engaging with the Challenge of Cultural Variation and Sample Diversity. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 14(2), 539–563. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-021-00611-zCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirby, S. (1999). Function, selection, and innateness: The emergence of language universals. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirby, S., Griffiths, T., & Smith, K. (2014). Iterated learning and the evolution of language. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 28, 108114.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kline, M. A., Waring, T. M., & Salerno, J. (2018). Designing cultural multilevel selection research for sustainability science. Sustainability Science, 13(1), 919.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Krasnow, M. M., & Delton, A. W. (2016). The sketch is blank: No evidence for an explanatory role for cultural group selection. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, e43, 39.Google Scholar
Krasnow, M. M., Delton, A. W., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2015). Group cooperation without group selection: Modest punishment can recruit much cooperation. PLOS ONE, 10(4), e0124561.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Krasnow, M. M., Delton, A. W., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2016). Looking under the hood of third-party punishment reveals design for personal benefit. Psychological Science, 27(3), 405418. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797615624469CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lang, M., Purzycki, B. G., Apicella, C. L., Atkinson, Q. D., Bolyanatz, A., Cohen, E., …, Henrich, J. (2019). Moralizing gods, impartiality and religious parochialism across 15 societies. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 286(1898), 20190202. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2019.0202Google ScholarPubMed
Langergraber, K. E., Boesch, C., Inoue, E., Inoue-Murayama, M., Mitani, J. C., Nishida, T., …, Vigilant, L. (2011). Genetic and ‘cultural’ similarity in wild chimpanzees. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 278(1704), 408416. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2010.1112CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Legare, C. H. (2017). Cumulative cultural learning: Development and diversity. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 114(30), 7877–7883. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1620743114Google ScholarPubMed
Lewens, T. (2015). Cultural evolution: Conceptual challenges. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewens, T. (2020). How can conceptual analysis contribute to scientific practice?: The case of cultural evolution. In Kampourakis, K. & Uller, T. (Eds.), Philosophy of science for biologists (1st ed., pp. 146167). Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108648981.009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewens, T., & Buskell, A. (2023). Cultural evolution. In Zalta, E. & Nodelman, U. (Eds.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2023/entries/evolution-cultural/Google Scholar
Lightner, A. D., Barclay, P., & Hagen, E. H. (2017). Radical framing effects in the ultimatum game: The impact of explicit culturally transmitted frames on economic decision-making. Royal Society Open Science, 4(12), 170543.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lightner, A. D., Bendixen, T., & Purzycki, B. G. (2023). Moralistic supernatural punishment is probably not associated with social complexity. Evolution and Human Behavior, 44(6), 555565.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lombard, M., & Haidle, M. N. (2012). Thinking a bow-and-arrow set: Cognitive implications of Middle Stone Age bow and stone-tipped arrow technology. Cambridge Archaeological Journal, 22(2), 237264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lovejoy, C. O. (2005a). The natural history of human gait and posture. Gait & Posture, 21(1), 113124. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.gaitpost.2004.06.010CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lovejoy, C. O. (2005b). The natural history of human gait and posture. Gait & Posture, 21(1), 95112. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.gaitpost.2004.01.001Google ScholarPubMed
Mace, R., & Holden, C. J. (2005). A phylogenetic approach to cultural evolution. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 20(3), 116121.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Manrubia, S. C., & Zanette, D. H. (2002). At the boundary between biological and cultural evolution: The origin of surname distributions. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 216(4), 461477.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McElreath, R., & Henrich, J. (2007). Modelling cultural evolution. In Barrett, L. & Dunbar, R. (Eds.), Oxford handbook of evolutionary psychology (pp. 555570). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McGrew, W. C. (1992). Chimpanzee material culture: Implications for human evolution. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahon, A. M. S. (1994). Understanding language change. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mesoudi, A. (2011). Cultural evolution. University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mesoudi, A. (2016). Cultural evolution: A review of theory, findings and controversies. Evolutionary Biology, 43(4), 481497. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11692-015-9320-0CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mesoudi, A., Chang, L., Murray, K., & Lu, H. J. (2014). Higher frequency of social learning in China than in the West shows cultural variation in the dynamics of cultural evolution. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 282(1798), 2014220920142209. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2014.2209CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mesoudi, A., & Whiten, A. (2008). The multiple roles of cultural transmission experiments in understanding human cultural evolution. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 363(1509), 34893501.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Micheletti, A. J. C., Brandl, E., & Mace, R. (2022). What is cultural evolution anyway? Behavioral Ecology, 33(4), 667669. https://doi.org/10.1093/beheco/arac011CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mills, B. J. (2017). Social network analysis in archaeology. Annual Review of Anthropology, 46, 379397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Misra, A. K. (2012). A simple mathematical model for the spread of two political parties. Nonlinear Analysis: Modelling and Control, 17(3), 343354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miton, H., & Charbonneau, M. (2018). Cumulative culture in the laboratory: Methodological and theoretical challenges. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 285(1879), 20180677. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2018.0677Google ScholarPubMed
Miyatake, S., & Higuchi, M. (2017). Does religious priming increase the prosocial behaviour of a Japanese sample in an anonymous economic game?: Religion and prosociality in Japan. Asian Journal of Social Psychology, 20(1), 5459. https://doi.org/10.1111/ajsp.12164CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moll, H. (2020). How young children learn from others. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 54(2), 340355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moll, H., & Kern, A. (2020). Learning from another. Inquiry. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2020.1731593CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, R. (2013). Imitation and conventional communication. Biology & Philosophy, 28, 481500.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mörchen, J., Luhn, F., Wassmer, O., Kunz, J. A., Kulik, L., Noordwijk, Van, …, Schuppli, C. (2023). Migrant orangutan males use social learning to adapt to new habitat after dispersal. Frontiers in Ecology and Evolution, 11, 1158887. https://doi.org/10.3389/fevo.2023.1158887CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mrazek, A. J., Chiao, J. Y., Blizinsky, K. D., Lun, J., & Gelfand, M. J. (2013). The role of culture–gene coevolution in morality judgment: Examining the interplay between tightness–looseness and allelic variation of the serotonin transporter gene. Culture and Brain, 1(2–4), 100117. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40167-013-0009-xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mullon, C., & Lehmann, L. (2017). Invasion fitness for gene–culture co-evolution in family-structured populations and an application to cumulative culture under vertical transmission. Theoretical Population Biology, 116, 3346. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tpb.2017.06.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagengast, C. (1997). Women, minorities, and indigenous peoples: Universalism and cultural relativity. Journal of Anthropological Research, 53(3), 349369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, R., Slingerland, E., Nielbo, K. L., Kirby, P., & Logan, C. (2020). Supernatural agents and prosociality in historical China: Micro-modeling the cultural evolution of gods and morality in textual corpora. Religion, Brain & Behavior. https://doi.org/10.1080/2153599X.2020.1742778CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norenzayan, A. (2013). Big gods: How religion transformed cooperation and conflict. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Norenzayan, A., Atran, S., Faulkner, J., & Schaller, M. (2006). Memory and mystery: The cultural selection of minimally counterintuitive narratives. Cognitive Science, 30(3), 531553. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15516709cog0000_68CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Norris, P., & Inglehart, R. (2019). Cultural backlash: Trump, Brexit, and authoritarian populism. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Brien, M. J., Buchanan, B., & Eren, M. I. (2018). Convergent evolution in stone-tool technology. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pain, R., and Brown, R. L. (2021). Mind the gap: A more evolutionarily plausible role for technical reasoning in cumulative technological culture. In Stein, F. (Ed.), The open encyclopedia of anthropology. Facsimile of the first edition in The Cambridge encyclopedia of anthropology, 199(1–2), 24672489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parunak, Van Dyke, Savit, H., & Riolo, R., L, R.. (1998). Agent-based modeling vs. equation-based modeling: A case study and users’ guide. Multi-Agent Systems and Agent-Based Simulation: First International Workshop, MABS‘98, Paris, France, July 4–6, 1998. Proceedings (Vol. 1, pp. 10–25).Google Scholar
Patten, A. (2014). Equal recognition: The moral foundations of minority rights. Princeton University Press. https://doi.org/10.1515/9781400850433.Google Scholar
Perrault, C. (2019). The quality of the archaeological record. University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pisor, A. C., Gervais, M. M., Purzycki, B. G., & Ross, C. T. (2020). Preferences and constraints: The value of economic games for studying human behaviour. Royal Society Open Science, 7(6), 192090.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pope, S. M., Taglialatela, J. P., & Hopkins, W. D. (2017). Changes in mirror region connectivity following do-as-i-do training in chimpanzees. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 30(3), 111.Google ScholarPubMed
Purzycki, B. G., Henrich, J., Apicella, C. L., Atkinson, Q. D., Baimel, A., Cohen, E., & Norenzayan, A. (2018). The evolution of religion and morality: A synthesis of ethnographic and experimental evidence from eight societies. Religion, Brain & Behavior, 8(2), 101132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Purzycki, B. G., Stagnaro, M. N., & Sasaki, J. (2020). Breaches of trust change the content and structure of religious appeals. Journal for the Study of Religion, Nature and Culture, 14(1), 7194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Purzycki, B. G., & Willard, A. K. (2016). MCI theory: A critical discussion. Religion, Brain & Behavior, 6(3), 207248. https://doi.org/10.1080/2153599X.2015.1024915CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ramsey, G. (2023). Human nature. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ramsey, G., Bastian, M. L., & Van Schaik, C. P. (2007). Animal innovation defined and operationalized. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30, 393437.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ramsey, G., & De Block, A. (2015). Is cultural fitness hopelessly confused? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, axv047. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axv047CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Read, D. (2011, January 1). The misuse of a mathematical model: The Tasmanian case. Human Complex Systems UCLA, 2011. https://ssrn.com/abstract=2805822 or http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2805822CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reali, F., & Griffiths, T. L. (2009). Words as alleles: Connecting language evolution with Bayesian learners to models of genetic drift. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 277(1680), 429436.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Richerson, P., Baldini, R., Bell, A. V., Demps, K., Frost, K., Hillis, V., … Zefferman, M. (2016). Cultural group selection plays an essential role in explaining human cooperation: A sketch of the evidence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 39, e30. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X1400106XCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ritt, N. (2004). Selfish sounds & linguistic evolution: A Darwinian approach to language change. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, G., & Sneller, B. (2020). Empirical foundations for an integrated study of language evolution. Language Dynamics and Change, 10(2), 188229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roes, F., & Raymond, M. (2003). Belief in moralizing gods. Evolution and Human Behavior, 24(2), 126135. https://doi.org/10.1016/S1090-5138(02)00134-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rogoff, B. (2003). The cultural nature of human development. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rowthorn, R. (2011). Religion, fertility and genes: A dual inheritance model. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 278(1717), 25192527.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scarantino, A. (2015). Information as a probabilistic difference maker. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93(3), 419443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schelling, T. C. (1971). Dynamic models of segregation. Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 1(2), 143186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlingloff, L., & Moore, R. (2017). Do chimpanzees conform to social norms? In The Routledge handbook of philosophy of animal minds (pp. 381389). Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schloss, J. P., & Murray, M. J. (2011). Evolutionary accounts of belief in supernatural punishment: A critical review. Religion, Brain & Behavior, 1(1), 4699. https://doi.org/10.1080/2153599X.2011.558707CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schnegg, M. (2014). Anthropology and comparison: Methodological challenges and tentative solutions. Zeitschrift Für Ethnologie, 5572.Google Scholar
Schulze, J. N., Denkinger, J., Oña, J., Poole, M. M., & Garland, E. C. (2022). Humpback whale song revolutions continue to spread from the central into the eastern South Pacific. Royal Society Open Science, 9(8), 220158.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schuppli, C., & Van Schaik, C. P. (2019). Animal cultures: How we've only seen the tip of the iceberg. Evolutionary Human Sciences, 1, e2.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Scott-Phillips, T., & Heintz, C. (2023). Great ape interaction: Ladyginian but not Gricean. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 120(42), e2300243120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scott-Phillips, T. C., & Kirby, S. (2010). Language evolution in the laboratory. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14(9), 411417. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2010.06.006CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Segovia-Martin, J., & Tamariz, M. (2021). Synchronising institutions and value systems: A model of opinion dynamics mediated by proportional representation. PLoS One, 16(9), e0257525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Segovia-Martín, J., Walker, B., Fay, N., & Tamariz, M. (2020). Network connectivity dynamics, cognitive biases, and the evolution of cultural diversity in round-robin interactive micro-societies. Cognitive Science, 44(7), e12852.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Seligmann, L. J., & Estes, B. P. (2020). Innovations in ethnographic methods. American Behavioral Scientist, 64(2), 176197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shariff, A., Norenzayan, A., & Henrich, J. (2010). The birth of high gods: How the cultural evolution of supernatural policing influenced the emergence of complex, cooperative human societies, paving the way for civilization. In Schaller, M., Norenzayan, A., Heine, S. J., Yamagishi, T., & Kamedda, T. (Eds.), Evolution, culture, and the human mind (pp. 119136). Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Shariff, A. F., & Norenzayan, A. (2007). God is watching you: Priming god concepts increases prosocial behavior in an anonymous economic game. Psychological Science, 18(9), 803809. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9280.2007.01983.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shennan, S. (2008). Evolution in archaeology. Annual Review of Anthropology, 37, 7591.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singh, M., Acerbi, A., Caldwell, C. A., Danchin, É., Isabel, G., Molleman, L., … Derex, M. (2021). Beyond social learning. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 376(1828), rstb.2020.0050, 20200050. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2020.0050CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Skyrms, B. (2014). Evolution of the social contract. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slingerland, E., Atkinson, Q. D., Ember, C. R., Sheehan, O., Muthukrishna, M., Bulbulia, J., & Gray, R. D. (2020). Coding culture: Challenges and recommendations for comparative cultural databases. Evolutionary Human Sciences, 2, e29. https://doi.org/10.1017/ehs.2020.30CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smith, D. (2020). Cultural group selection and human cooperation: A conceptual and empirical review. Evolutionary Human Sciences, 2, e2. https://doi.org/10.1017/ehs.2020.2CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smolla, M., Jansson, F., Lehmann, L., Houkes, W., Weissing, F. J., Hammerstein, P., … Enquist, M. (2021). Underappreciated features of cultural evolution. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 376(1828), rstb.2020.0259, 20200259. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2020.0259CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sober, E., & Wilson, D. S. (2003). Unto others: The evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior (4th ed.). Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sperber, D. (1996). Explaining culture: A naturalistic approach. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sperber, D. (2000). An objection to the memetic approach to culture. In Aunger, R. (Ed.), Darwinizing culture: The status of memetics as a science (pp. 163173). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sripada, C. S., & Stich, S. (2006). A framework for the psychology of norms. In The innate mind Vol. 2: Cognition and culture (pp. 280301). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Steels, L. (2016). Agent-based models for the emergence and evolution of grammar. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 371(1701), 20150447.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sterelny, K. (2009). Peacekeeping in the culture wars. In Laland, K. N. & Galef, B. G. (Eds.), The question of animal culture (pp. 288304). Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, K. (2012). The evolved apprentice. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, K. (2017). Cultural evolution in California and Paris. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 62, 4250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, K. (2021). The Pleistocene social contract. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stolarczyk, R. E., & Schmidt, P. (2018). Is early silcrete heat treatment a new behavioural proxy in the Middle Stone Age? PLoS One, 13(10), e0204705.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Swanson, G. E. (1960). The birth of the gods: The origin of primitive beliefs. Univ. of Michigan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tallerman, M., & Gibson, K. R. (Eds.). (2011). The Oxford Handbook of Language Evolution. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tamariz, M. (2017). Experimental studies on the cultural evolution of language. Annual Review of Linguistics, 3, 389407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tamariz, M. (2019). Replication and emergence in cultural transmission. Physics of Life Reviews, 30, 4771.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tennie, C. (2019). Could non-human great apes also have cultural evolutionary psychology? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 42, e184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tennie, C. (2023). Reinforcing a Zone of Latent Solution (ZLS) account of the Oldowan. A commentary on Sterelny and Hiscock's ‘Cumulative culture, archaeology, and the Zone of Latent Solutions’. Current Anthropology, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Tennie, C., Bandini, E., Van Schaik, C. P., & Hopper, L. M. (2020). The zone of latent solutions and its relevance to understanding ape cultures. Biology & Philosophy, 35(1), 142.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tennie, C., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2009). Ratcheting up the ratchet: On the evolution of cumulative culture. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 364(1528), 24052415.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tennie, C., Premo, L. S., Braun, D. R., & McPherron, S. P. (2017). Early stone tools and cultural transmission: Resetting the null hypothesis. Current Anthropology, 58(5), 652672. https://doi.org/10.1086/693846CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomasello, M., & Call, J. (2019). Thirty years of great ape gestures. Animal cognition, 22, 461469.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tunçgenç, B., & Cohen, E. (2016). Movement synchrony forges social bonds across group divides. Frontiers in Psychology, 7, 782.Google ScholarPubMed
Turchin, P., Whitehouse, H., Francois, P., Slingerland, E., & Collard, M. (2012). A historical database of sociocultural evolution. Cliodynamics, 3(2).Google Scholar
Vaesen, K., Collard, M., Cosgrove, R., & Roebroeks, W. (2016a). Population size does not explain past changes in cultural complexity. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 113(16). https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1520288113CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vaesen, K., Collard, M., Cosgrove, R., & Roebroeks, W. (2016b). Reply to Henrich et al.: The Tasmanian effect and other red herrings. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 113(44), E6726–E6727. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1613074113CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vaesen, K., & Houkes, W. (2021). Is human culture cumulative? Current Anthropology, 62(2), 218238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vale, G. L., Flynn, E. G., Kendal, R., Rawlings, B., Hopper, L. M., Schapiro, S. J., …, Kendal, R. L. (2017). Testing differential use of payoff-biased social learning strategies in children and chimpanzees. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 284(1868), 20171751.Google ScholarPubMed
Vanhaeren, M., & d'Errico, F. (2006). Aurignacian ethno-linguistic geography of Europe revealed by personal ornaments. Journal of Archaeological Science, 33(8), 11051128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vogt, S., Mohmmed Zaid, N. A., Ahmed, El Fadil, Fehr, H., & Efferson, E., C. (2016). Changing cultural attitudes towards female genital cutting. Nature, 538(7626), 506509.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wang, Y., & Su, Y. (2022). Genetic contributions to East Asian morality. In Nichols, R. (Ed.), The Routledge international handbook of morality, cognition, emotion, and behavior in China (pp. 80100). Routledge.Google Scholar
Waring, T. M., Goff, S. H., & Smaldino, P. E. (2017). The coevolution of economic institutions and sustainable consumption via cultural group selection. Ecological Economics, 131, 524532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watts, J., Greenhill, S. J., Atkinson, Q. D., Currie, T. E., Bulbulia, J., & Gray, R. D. (2015). Broad supernatural punishment but not moralizing high gods precede the evolution of political complexity in Austronesia. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 282(1804), 2014255620142556. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2014.2556CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weisberg, M. (2007). Who is a modeler? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(2), 207233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Westra, E., & Andrews, K. (2022). A pluralistic framework for the psychology of norms. Biology & Philosophy, 37(5), 40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiten, A. (2019). Cultural evolution in animals. Annual Review of Ecology, Evolution, and Systematics, 50(1), 2748. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-ecolsys-110218-025040CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiten, A. (2021). The burgeoning reach of animal culture. Science, 372(6537), eabe6514.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Whiten, A., Goodall, J., McGrew, W. C., Nishida, T., Reynolds, V., Sugiyama, Y., …, Boesch, C. (1999). Cultures in chimpanzees. Nature, 399(6737), 682685. https://doi.org/10.1038/21415CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilson, D. S. (2011). The neighborhood project: Using evolution to improve my city, one block at a time (1st ed.). Little, Brown.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. C. (1999). Genes, memes, and cultural heredity. Biology & Philosophy, 14(2), 279310. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1006646703557CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolf, E. R. (2005). Europe and the people without history: With a new preface (reprinted). University of California Press.Google Scholar
Wood, C., Caldwell-Harris, C., & Stopa, L. (2018). The rhythms of discontent: Synchrony impedes performance and group functioning in an interdependent coordination task. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 18(1–2), 154179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wrangham, R. W. (2021). Targeted conspiratorial killing, human self-domestication and the evolution of groupishness. Evolutionary Human Sciences, 3, e26.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yu, D., Chang, H., Davis, T., Hillis, V., Marston, L., Oh, W. S., … Waring, T. M. (2020). Socio-hydrology: An interplay of design and self-organization in a multilevel world. Ecology and Society, 25(4).CrossRefGoogle Scholar