Article contents
Conflicts of Competence Norms in EU Law and the Legal Reasoning of the ECJ
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 06 March 2019
Abstract
Defining competences in EU law has always been problematic, notwithstanding the inclusion since the Treaty of Maastrict of the principle of conferred powers as central to the constitutional character of the EU. Under the principle of conferral, the Union only has those powers actually conferred by the Treaties. However, the concepts of a common market or of ‘ever-closer Union’ have a conceptual scope that potentially, in effect, negates the principle of conferral. This article argues that the framework of norm conflict offers conceptual insight into the dynamics of determining and limiting EU competence. In particular, it draws on the distinction between lex specialis and lex generalis to understand different ways of treating competence norms in legal reasoning. Following a discussion of the concept of competence norms, this conceptual framework is applied to two case studies: (1) on the right to strike and (2) the general law of external relations.
- Type
- Articles
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © 2010 by German Law Journal GbR
References
1 See in particular Pollack, Mark A., Creeping Competence: The Expanding Agenda of the European Community, 14(2) Journal of Public Policy 95 (1994); Stephen Weatherill, Competence Creep and and Competence Control, 23 Yearbook of European Law 1, 5–12 (2004).Google Scholar
2 Alan Dashwood, The Limits of European Community Powers, 21 European Law Review (ELR) 113, 113 (1996).Google Scholar
3 Id., 128.Google Scholar
4 Richard Schütze, From Dual To Cooperative Federalism: The Changing Structure Of European Law 130 (2009).Google Scholar
5 The variety of which has been described as an ‘archipelago’ by former Italian Prime Minister and Foreign Minister Lamberto Dini: CONV 1234/02, 19t June 2002, 6, as cited in Stephen Weatherill, Competence and Legitimacy, in The Outer Limits of European Union Law 19 (C. Barnard & O. Odudu eds., 2009).Google Scholar
6 See, e.g. Case 7/71, Commission v. France, 1971 E.C.R. 1003, 1018.Google Scholar
7 See Obradovic, D., Repatriation of Powers in the European Community, 34 Common Market Law Review (CMLRev) 59 (1997). Articles 10(4)–(5) of the Protocol on Transitional Provisions to the Lisbon Treaty permit the UK to repudiate existing Third Pillar measures: see Dougan, Michael, The Treaty of Lisbon 2007: Winning Minds, Not Hearts, 45 CMLREV 617, 683 (2008).Google Scholar
8 In this article, the term ‘Community’ is used where it is found in existing caselaw and ‘Union’ is used in more general discussion. For the most part, references are to provisions of the European Community Treaty (ECT) (replaced by Lisbon with the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union or TFEU) and Treaty on European Union (TEU) pre-Lisbon, as the Treaty of Lisbon has only come into effect since 1 December 2009 and so must caselaw pre-date the changes that Lisbon introduced (the Article numbers as amended by Lisbon are also generally given for ease of reference).Google Scholar
9 Mayer, Z.C., Competences – Reloaded? The Vertical Division of Powers in the EU and the new European Constitution, 3(2) International Journal of Constitutional Law (IJCL) 493, 493 (2005), noting it is a recurring issue in EU law.Google Scholar
10 Article 2 TFEU.Google Scholar
11 The Future of the EU: Declaration of Laeken, document of the Belgian presidency, 15 December 2001, part 11A.Google Scholar
12 Leonor Moral Soriano, Vertical Judicial Disputes over Legal Bases, 30(2) West European Politics 321, 324 (2007).Google Scholar
13 See generally J-P. Jacqué, The Principle of Institutional Balance, 41 CMLRev 383, 384 (2004); Alan Dashwood, The Institutional Framework and the Institutional Balance, in 50 Years of the European Treaties: Looking Back and Thinking Forward (Michael Dougan & S. Currie eds., 2009).Google Scholar
14 The German Federal Constitutional Court has noted that Article 308 ECT could be used to extend competence: Brunner, BVerfGE 89, 155; [1994] 1 CMLRev 57, para. 210.Google Scholar
15 Opinion 2/94 Re Accession of the Community to the European Convention on Human Rights, 1996 E.C.R. 1–1759.Google Scholar
16 Id., para. 30.Google Scholar
17 Gráinne de Búrca & Bruno de Witte, The Delimitation of Powers Between the EU and its Member States, in Accountability and Legitimacy in the European Union 216 (Anthony Arnull & Daniel Wincott eds., 2002).Google Scholar
18 The Treaty of Lisbon modified this by requiring the consent of the European Parliament. Further, compared to Article 308 ECT, the wording of Article 352 TFEU is broader in referring to the objectives of the Union in toto, not just to the common market. However, as Dougan notes, this may make little practical difference given the broad reading of Article 308: Dougan, supra note 7, 655. Article 352 TFEU also excludes its application to the Common Foreign and Security Policy (CFSP), as well as requiring the Commission to bring proposals to the attention of national parliaments.Google Scholar
19 Dashwood, supra note 2, 124. Dashwood based his comments on his own experience working in the Council Secretariat.Google Scholar
20 Joseph H.H. Weiler, The Transformation of Europe 100(8) Yale Law Journal (Yale LJ) 2403, 2445–2446 (1991).Google Scholar
21 Id., 217. Schütze notes that the extensive use of the provisions runs the risk of subverting the idea of enumerated powers: Schütze, supra note 4, 134.Google Scholar
22 Although Article 308 ECT (now Article 352 TFEU) has hardly ever been articulated officially or in academic discussion as a fallback from lex specialis, Dashwood noted that “There has never been any doubt that the absence of a specific legal basis in the Treaty is a legal condition precedent for recourse to Article 235”, citing Case 242/87, ERASMUS, 1989 E.C.R. 1425: Dashwood, supra note 2, 123.Google Scholar
23 See de Búrca & de Witte (note 17), 215–216. Unlike Article 308 ECT, Article 95 did not require unanimity in the Council (though as Dashwood, quoted above, indicates, the extent of unanimity as a restraint on Union enterprises of ambition is questionable). See further generally, H.G. Krenzler & C. Pitschas, Progress or Stagnation? The Common Commercial Policy after Nice, 6 European Foreign Affairs Review (EFAR) 291 (2001); Schütze, supra note 4, 143–151.Google Scholar
24 See, e.g. discussion in Schütze, supra note 4, 143, relates ‘establishment’ to the elimination of obstacles to trade and ‘functioning’ to the removal of distortions on competition. Article 114 TFEU now refers to the ‘internal market', instead of common market, though the difference seems slight given the scope of the free movement and competition principles.Google Scholar
25 Case C-350/92, Spain v Council, 1995 E.C.R. I-1985, para. 35. See discussion in Schütze, supra note 4, 144–146.Google Scholar
26 Case C-376/98, Germany v. Parliament and Council, 2000 E.C.R. I-8419.Google Scholar
27 This reasoning is in sharp contrast with that which prevailed in Laval and Viking, discussed further below.Google Scholar
28 Mayer, supra note 9, 501; Dougan, supra note 7, 654; Schütze supra note 4, 144–151. Schütze describes the test in Tobacco Advertising as one of ‘a centre of gravity', 150.Google Scholar
29 As described by Dougan, supra note 7, 654.Google Scholar
30 Article 352 TFEU, which replaces Article 308 ECT, expressly prevents its use to circumvent specific exclusions of harmonization. It provides in paragraph 3 that ‘[m]easures based on this Article shall not entail harmonization of Member States’ laws or regulations in cases where the Treaties exclude such harmonisation”. See Schütze, supra note 4, 150–151, at n. 91.Google Scholar
31 Mayer, supra note 9, 501; Dougan, supra note 7, 654.Google Scholar
32 Joined Cases C-402/05 P and C-415/05 P, Kadi and al Barakaat International Foundation v. Council [2008] ECR I-6351,paras. 211, 213, 216, 222–227, 229–230. See generally M. Karayigit, The Yusuf and Kadi Judgments: The Scope of the EC Competence in Respect of Restrictive Measures, 33 Legal Issues of European Integration 379 (2006); Alan Dashwood, Article 308 EC as the Outer Limit of Expressly Conferred Community Competence in Barnard & Odudu (eds.), supra note 5, 41–42. Dashwood suggests that the extension of measures from States, as envisaged in Articles 60 and 301 ECT, to individuals, as provided by the contested measures in Kadi, amounted to the enhancement of an existing mechanism and thus did not go beyond the general framework of the Treaties. Nonetheless, it might be argued that given the punitive effect of the sanctions, their novelty as legal instruments, and the significant qualitative difference with sanctions imposed on States, a stricter approach to construction might have been warranted. The wording of Article 60 ECT has been broadened under Lisbon to include sanctions against natural persons: see Article 75 TFEU.Google Scholar
33 Case 22/70, Commission v. Council (Re European Road Transport Agreement) (‘ERTA')), 1971 E.C.R. 263, paras. 17–19, 28–31.Google Scholar
34 Case 8/74, Procureur du Roi v. Dassonville, 1974 E.C.R. 837, paras. 5–9; Case 120/78, Rewe-Zentrale AG (Cassis de Dijon), 1979 E.C.R. 649, paras. 8–14.Google Scholar
35 Dashwood suggests that the term ‘internal market’ should be preferred in Article 235 European Economic Community (EEC) Treaty (as Article 308 ECT was numbered pre-Maastricht) to the “notoriously open-textured concept” of a common market: Dashwood, supra note 2, 123. It might be thought that ‘internal market', for instance, would seem not to obviously include, on the surface, external relations. However, as the European Court of Justice (ECJ) has drawn a link between internal and external powers through the doctrine of parallelism, the drafting change might not make much difference in practice, though it seems worth making in principle. By comparison, Article 352 TFEU, introduced by the Lisbon Treaty, refers to neither the ‘common market’ nor ‘internal market’ and instead simply refers to the ‘policies defined in the Treaties', which is possibly broader still than ‘common market'.Google Scholar
36 Weatherill, supra note 5, 19–20, noting that the likelihood of preventing obstacles to free movement as a basis for legislative competence “is so lacking in precision and predictability that … one may readily regard the Court's stance as now more concerned with ‘competence-enhancing'…”.Google Scholar
37 Gareth Davies, Subsidiarity: The Wrong Idea, In the Wrong Place, At the Wrong Time, 43 CMLRev 63, 63, 65 (2006). See also Paul Craig, Competence and Subsidiarity in EU Administrative Law 40–44 (2006); Armin Von Bogdandy & Jürgen Bast, The Union's Powers: A Question of Competence. The Vertical Order of Competences and Proposals for its Reform, 38 CMLRev 227, 238 (2002); Soriano, supra note 12, 329.Google Scholar
38 Davies, id. Google Scholar
39 See, e.g. Weatherill, supra note 5, 18.Google Scholar
40 Mayer, supra note 9, 511. The Convention on the Future of Europe drew up the text of the un-ratified Treaty Establishing a Constitution for Europe (29th October 2004, CIG 87/2/04 REV), which was the basis nonetheless for much of the Lisbon Treaty.Google Scholar
41 Suggesting that competence claims will necessarily differ from case to case, see Craig, supra note 37, 404. See also Soriano, supra note 12, 325.Google Scholar
42 Eugenio Bulygin, On Norms of Competence, 11(3) Law and Philosophy (L. & P.) 201, 201 (1992). See further generally on competence norms: Herbert LA. Hart, The Concept Of Law (2nd ed. 1994); Torben Spaak, The Concept of Competence (1994); Torben Spaak, Norms that Confer Competence, 16(1) Ratio Juris (RJ) 89 (2003), Torben Spaak, Explicating the Concept of Legal Competence, Social Science Research Network Working Paper (2008), available at < http://ssrn.com/abstract=1014402 > (last accessed 31 May 2010). Generally on competence in EU law, see, e.g. Pollack, supra note 1; Dashwood, supra note 2; Obradovic, supra note 7; Krenzler & Pitschas, supra note 23; Von Bogdandy & Bast, supra note 37; de Búrca & de Witte, supra note 17; Gareth Davies, The Post-Laeken Division of Competences, 28 ELR 686 (2003); Alan Dashwood, The Relationship Between the Member States and the European Union, 41 CMLRev 355 (2004); Paul Craig, Competence: Clarity, Conferral, Containment and Consideration, 29 ELR 323–344 (2004); Robin White, Conflicting Competences: Free Movement Rules and Immigration Laws, 29 ELR 385–396 (2004); Weatherill, supra note 1; Stephen Weatherill, Better Competence Monitoring, 30 ELR 23 (2005); Mayer, supra note 9; Derek Wyatt, The Growing Competence of the European Community, 16(3) European Business Law Review (EBLR) 483 (2005); Craig, supra note 37; Karayigit, supra note 32; Soriano, supra note 12; E. Herlin-Karnell, Light Weapons’ and the Dynamics of Art 47 TEU – The EC's Armoury of Ever Expanding Competences, 71(6) Modern Law Review (MLR) 987–1014 (2008); S. Sieberson, Dividing Lines between the European Union AND ITS Member States (2008); D. Eisenhut, Delimitation of EU-Competences under the First and Second Pillar: A View Between ECOWAS and the Treaty of Lisbon, 10(5) German Law Journal (GLJ) 585 (2009); Schütze, supra note 4; Stephen Weatherill, supra note 5; Dashwood, supra note 32; Herwig C.H. Hofmann, Which Limits? Control of Powers in an Integrated Legal System, in C. Barnard & O. Odudu eds., supra note 5.+(last+accessed+31+May+2010).+Generally+on+competence+in+EU+law,+see,+e.g.+Pollack,+supra+note+1;+Dashwood,+supra+note+2;+Obradovic,+supra+note+7;+Krenzler+&+Pitschas,+supra+note+23;+Von+Bogdandy+&+Bast,+supra+note+37;+de+Búrca+&+de+Witte,+supra+note+17;+Gareth+Davies,+The+Post-Laeken+Division+of+Competences,+28+ELR+686+(2003);+Alan+Dashwood,+The+Relationship+Between+the+Member+States+and+the+European+Union,+41+CMLRev+355+(2004);+Paul+Craig,+Competence:+Clarity,+Conferral,+Containment+and+Consideration,+29+ELR+323–344+(2004);+Robin+White,+Conflicting+Competences:+Free+Movement+Rules+and+Immigration+Laws,+29+ELR+385–396+(2004);+Weatherill,+supra+note+1;+Stephen+Weatherill,+Better+Competence+Monitoring,+30+ELR+23+(2005);+Mayer,+supra+note+9;+Derek+Wyatt,+The+Growing+Competence+of+the+European+Community,+16(3)+European+Business+Law+Review+(EBLR)+483+(2005);+Craig,+supra+note+37;+Karayigit,+supra+note+32;+Soriano,+supra+note+12;+E.+Herlin-Karnell,+Light+Weapons’+and+the+Dynamics+of+Art+47+TEU+–+The+EC's+Armoury+of+Ever+Expanding+Competences,+71(6)+Modern+Law+Review+(MLR)+987–1014+(2008);+S.+Sieberson,+Dividing+Lines+between+the+European+Union+AND+ITS+Member+States+(2008);+D.+Eisenhut,+Delimitation+of+EU-Competences+under+the+First+and+Second+Pillar:+A+View+Between+ECOWAS+and+the+Treaty+of+Lisbon,+10(5)+German+Law+Journal+(GLJ)+585+(2009);+Schütze,+supra+note+4;+Stephen+Weatherill,+supra+note+5;+Dashwood,+supra+note+32;+Herwig+C.H.+Hofmann,+Which+Limits?+Control+of+Powers+in+an+Integrated+Legal+System,+in+C.+Barnard+&+O.+Odudu+eds.,+supra+note+5.>Google Scholar
43 Anglo-American legal theory tends to use the term ‘power’ instead of ‘competence': Bulygin, id, 202.Google Scholar
44 Wesley Hohfeld, Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions As Applied in Judicial Reasoning, 23 Yale LJ 16, 55 (1913–1914).Google Scholar
45 Hart, supra note 42, 30–35.Google Scholar
46 See Pauwelyn, Joost, Conflict of Norms in Public International law, 278–326 (2003); Spaak (2003), supra note 42, 91–92. Spaak suggests the idea of competence is necessary to understand the concept of validity.Google Scholar
47 See, e.g. Weatherill (2009), supra note 42, 17.Google Scholar
48 Hans Kelsen, General Theory of Law and State, 63 (1949).Google Scholar
49 Hart, supra note 42, 38.Google Scholar
50 See Bulygin, supra note 42, 204.Google Scholar
51 Hart, supra note 42, 38.Google Scholar
52 Id. 40.Google Scholar
53 Id., 41. Bulygin noted he was convinced by Hart's arguments: supra note 42, 204.Google Scholar
54 Spaak (2003), supra note 42, 102.Google Scholar
55 Spaak considers reasons for action or guidance for human behaviour as implicit in Hart's internal point of view: Spaak (2003), supra note 42, 93; generally Joseph Raz, Practical Reasons and Norms (2nd ed. 1990).Google Scholar
56 Spaak (2003), supra note 42, 94.Google Scholar
57 Georg H. Von Wright, Norm and Action, 7–8 (1963), discussed in Spaak (2003), supra note 42, 92–94.Google Scholar
58 These are competence norms simpliciter, saying that by performing a certain kind of act in a certain kind of situation they can bring about a certain change in legal positions: Spaak, id., 94.Google Scholar
59 More briefly, Soriano makes a similar distinction between enabling (equivalent to competence conferring norms) and standard-setting norms (equivalent to competence norms): Soriano, supra note 12, 323.Google Scholar
60 Spaak (2003), supra note 42, 90.Google Scholar
61 Id. “To exercise a competence is to bring about the intended change of legal positions by performing a competence-exercising act”: Id., 90. See further Spaak (1994), chap. 5, supra note 42.Google Scholar
62 Hartley, T., The Foundations of European Community Law, 106 (5th ed. 2003).Google Scholar
63 Weiler commented that the extent of the use of ex Article 308 ECT “… was simply not consistent with the narrow interpretation of the Article as a codification of implied powers doctrine in its instrumental sense”: Weiler, supra note 20, 2445. See also Dashwood, supra note 2, 124, noting that an extensive doctrine of implied powers would not be consistent with the principle of attributed or conferred powers. On the role of implication in law generally, see Claus, Lawrence, Implication and the Concept of a Constitution, 69(11) Australian Law Journal 887 (1995), also distinguishing between broad and narrow approaches.Google Scholar
64 See generally Julius Stone, The Ratio of the Ratio Decidendi, 22(6) Modern Law Review 597 (1959). In an EU context, see Conway, Gerard, Levels of Generality in the Legal Reasoning of the European Court of Justice, 14(6) European Law Journal 787 (2008).Google Scholar
65 John H. Ely, Democracy and Distrust, 56–60 (1980).Google Scholar
66 See generally, e.g. Weatherill (2009), supra note 42, 25–27, linking flexible competences to effective problem-solving. On input legitimacy, see Fritz W. Scharpf, Governing in Europe: Effective or Democratic?, 9 et seq (1999).Google Scholar
67 Case 8/55, Fédération Charbonnière de Belghique v. High Authority, 1956 E.C.R. 245, 280. See also Case 165/87, Commission v. Council, 1988 E.C.R. 5545.Google Scholar
68 Cases 281, 283–5, 287/85, Germany v. Commission, 1987 E.C.R. 3203, where the ECJ held that the Commission had an implied legislative power obliging the Member States to consult and inform it regarding draft measures and agreements in the social field given that the Treaty stated “the Commission shall have the task of promoting close cooperation between Member States in the social field” The ECJ stated the test for the existence of an implied power was that it was indispensable in order to carry out a task assigned by the Treaty (para. 28). See also, e.g. Case C-176/03, Commission v. Council, 2005 E.C.R. I-7879.Google Scholar
69 Regarding parallelism, see, e.g. Dashwood (1996), supra note 2, 125.Google Scholar
70 Mayer, supra note 9, 494, 508–509.Google Scholar
71 Case C-186/01, Alexander Dory v. Bundesrepublik, 2003 E.C.R. I-2479, discussed id. Spaak (2008), supra note 42, 11, uses the term regulatory competence in a different sense to mean an exercise of an existing competence norm, as opposed to the creation of a competence norm.Google Scholar
72 Mayer, supra note 9, 494, 508–509, 511.Google Scholar
73 Gilbert Guillaume, The Proliferation of International Judicial bodies: The Outlook for the International Legal Order, Speech to the Sixth Committee of the UN General Assembly by His Excellency Judge Gilbert Guillaume (President of the International Court of Justice), 27 October 2004, 4, available online at < http://www.icj-cii.org/presscom/index.php?p1=6&p2=1&pr=85&search=%22nagymaros%22 > (last visited 7 December 2009) and cited in Pauwelyn, supra note 46, 1.+(last+visited+7+December+2009)+and+cited+in+Pauwelyn,+supra+note+46,+1.>Google Scholar
74 I.e. the distinction between substantive primary rules and secondary rules that govern how (substantive) primary rules (rules of change, rules of adjudication, rule of recognition) come into being and are changed, enforced, and judged. The distinction is of course attributable to Hart: Hart, supra note 42, 80–81.Google Scholar
75 See generally Jeremy Waldron, Law and Disagreement (1999); Samantha Besson, The Morality of Conflict: Reasonable Disagreement and the Law (2006). See also Pauwelyn, supra,note 46, 102–103.Google Scholar
76 See, e.g. Karen McAuliffe, Enlargement at the European Court of Justice: Law, Language and Translation, 14(6) European Law Journal 806 (2008).Google Scholar
77 See generally Francis E. Dowrick, Overlapping European Laws, 27(3) International & Comparative Law Quarterly 629 (1978); Toni Joris & Jan Vandenberghe, The Council of Europe and the European Union: Natural Partners or Uneasy Bedfellows?, 15(1) Columbia Journal of European Law 1 (2008–2009).Google Scholar
78 Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire, 228–258 (1986). See Zucca, Lorenzo, Constitutional Dilemmas: Conflicts of Fundamental Legal Rights in Europe and the USA, 12 (2007), noting that both Alexy and Dworkin assume a coherent order of values.Google Scholar
79 Joseph Raz, The Relevance of Coherence, in Ethics in the Public Domain, 280 (1994).Google Scholar
80 Stefano Bertea, The Arguments from Coherence: Analysis and Evaluation, 25(3) Oxford Journal of Legal Studies (OJLS) 369–391 (2005) (‘Bertea, 2005a'). See also Stefano Bertea, ‘Looking for Coherence within the European Community', 11(2) European Law Journal 154 (2005).Google Scholar
81 Bertea (2005a), id., 383.Google Scholar
82 Id., 379, 387.Google Scholar
83 Zucca, supra note 78, 5.Google Scholar
84 Hart, supra note 42, 268.Google Scholar
85 Pierre Schlag, Authorizing Interpretation, 30(3) Connecticut Law Review 1065, 1087 (1998).Google Scholar
86 Dworkin, supra note 78, 285.Google Scholar
87 Julie Dickson, Interpretation and Coherence in Legal Reasoning, Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (Summer 2005 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.) URL = < http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-reas-interpret/ > (last accessed 29 January 2008), citing Barbara Levenbook, The Role of Coherence in Legal Reasoning, 3(3) L. & Phil. 355 (1984). For a response (though not citing Leavenbook), see Dworkin, supra note 78, 251–256.+(last+accessed+29+January+2008),+citing+Barbara+Levenbook,+The+Role+of+Coherence+in+Legal+Reasoning,+3(3)+L.+&+Phil.+355+(1984).+For+a+response+(though+not+citing+Leavenbook),+see+Dworkin,+supra+note+78,+251–256.>Google Scholar
88 Samantha Besson, How International is the European Legal Order: Retracing Tuori's steps in the exploration of European legal pluralism, 5 No Foundations–Journal of Extreme Legal Positivism 50, 57 (April 2008).Google Scholar
89 Lawrence Alexander & Kenneth Kress, Against Legal Principles, in Law and Interpretation: Essays in Legal Philosophy, 313–314 (Andrei Marmor ed., 1995).Google Scholar
90 Raz, J., The Role of Coherence, in Ethics in the Public Domain, 294 (2nd ed. 1994).Google Scholar
91 Id., 318–320.Google Scholar
92 Id., 318.Google Scholar
93 Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, 24–25 (rev. ed. 1978). Dworkin also characterizes principles as relating to rights only, preferring the term ‘policy’ to indicate considerations relating to the general or collective interest (see, e.g. id, 90).Google Scholar
94 Thomas Hickman, The Substance and Structure of Proportionality, Public Law 694 (2008), 716, referring to proportionality.Google Scholar
95 See, e.g. Alexander & Kress, supra note 89, esp. 301–309 (there is no correct way of defining the weight to be attached to legal principles and that legal principles tend to collapse into equivalence to moral principles); Dimitrios Kyritsis, Principles, Policies and the Power of Courts, 20(2) Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 379, 383–385 (2007) (policies may justify the restriction of rights and that policies may be the basis of legal rights through creating a legitimate expectation).Google Scholar
96 Suggesting they are a matter of custom, see John W. Harris, Kelsen and Normative Consistency, in, Essays on Kelsen, 213 (Richard Tur & William Twining eds., 1986).Google Scholar
97 On the universal character of legal reasoning in general, see e.g. Neil MacCormick, Legal Theory and Legal Reasoning, 6, 99 (1978), respectively linking universalizability and rationality to the principle of formal justice that like cases be treated alike; Alexander Peczenik, Moral and Ontological Justification of Legal Reasoning, 4(2) Land P 289, 293–298 (1985); Robert Alexy, A Theory of Legal Argumentation, 191–195, 292–297 (1989); Jeana Sharankova, The Principle of Universalizability and its Semiosis, 13(1) International Journal of the Semiotics of Law 29(2000); Ronald Dworkin, Hart's Postscript and the Character of Legal Philosophy, 24(1) OJLS1, 36(2004).Google Scholar
98 See, e.g. the discussion of rules of change in Hart (note 41), 95–96.Google Scholar
99 See Pauwelyn, note 46, 161–164.Google Scholar
100 On the Kantian background to Kelsen's thinking and his use of the transcendental method, see, e.g. Stanley Paulson, The Neo-Kantian Dimension of Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law, 12(3) OJLS 311 (1992).Google Scholar
101 See, e.g. Hans Kelsen, The Pure Theory of Law, its Method and Fundamental Concepts, 50 Law Quarterly Review (LQR) 474 (1934) and 51 LQR 517 (1935) (perhaps a counter-intuitive use of the term ‘pure’ in disconnecting it from morality).Google Scholar
102 In particular, see the well-known judgments of the German Federal Constitutional Court Wüensche Handelsgesellschaft, 1987 3 CMLRev. 225; Brunner v. European Treaty, 1994 1 CMLRev. 57; Lisbon Treaty Case, BVerfG, 2 BvE 2/08, judgment of 30th June 2009, available at: <http://www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/entscheidungen/es200906302bve000208en.html< (in English, last accessed 22 January 2010).Google Scholar
103 The term ‘jus singulare' from Roman law is sometimes also used: see, e.g. Ferdinand Mackeldey, Roman Law (trans by MA. Dropsie) (1883), secs. 196–197, cited in Hohfeld, supra note 44, 38.Google Scholar
104 The principle is expressed in Article 55 of the Articles on State Responsibility adopted by the International Law Commission in 2001, UN GAOR, 56th Sess, Supp No 10, 43, UN Doc A/56/10 (2001).Google Scholar
105 Emer de Vattel, Les droits des gens ou principes de la loi naturelle (1758) (reprinted 1916), Liv. II, Chap. VII, para. 316.Google Scholar
106 The International Court of Justice has recognized the principle in a number of cases: Hungary v. Slovakia (‘Gabčíkovo-Nagymaros Project'), ICJ Reports 1997, para. 12, holding a treaty to be lexspecialis relative to the law on State responsibility; Nicaragua v. US (Military and Paramilitary Activities In and against Nicaragua) (Merits), ICJ Reports 1986, para. 274, describing treaties as lex specialis relative to custom. The ECJ has also recognized the principle explicitly in a range of cases, typically in the case of secondary legislation: see e.g. Case C-444/00, Mayer Parry Recycling, 2003 E.C.R. I-6163, paras. 51 and 57, where the Court held that “Directive 94/62 must be considered to a special provision (a lexspecialis) vis-à-vis Directive 75/442, so that its provisions prevail over those of Directive 75/442 in situations which it specifically seeks to regulate.” See also, e.g. Case C-252/05, R (Thames Water Utilities Ltd.) v. Bromley Magistrates’ Court (Interested party: Environment Agency), judgment of 10 May 2007, paras. 39–41 (where the validity of lex specialis was recognized but held not to apply to the provisions in issue). It recognised lex specialis implicitly in interpreting the EC Treaty in Case C-376/98, Tobacco Advertising, supra note 26.Google Scholar
107 See generally Lawrence Tribe & Michael C. Dorf, On Reading the Constitution (1988), 21–23; Conway, supra note 64.Google Scholar
108 International Law Commission/Martii Koskenniemi, Fragmentation of International Law: Difficulties Arising from the Diversification and Expansion of International Law, A/CN.4/L.682, 13th April 2006, paras. 89–92. For a contrary view, see Pauwelyn, supra note 46, 410–412.Google Scholar
109 The issue has not yet been squarely confronted by the House of Lords (now the Supreme Court), but the Administrative Court has suggested that a later, ordinary or ‘non-constitutional’ Act of Parliament can only repeal an earlier Act of Parliament of a constitutional nature by express repeal: Thoburn v. Sunderland City Council, 2002 EWHC 195 (Admin), paras. 60–67 (per Laws U.).Google Scholar
110 Soriano, supra note 12, 331–332; Paul Craig & Gráinne de Búrca, EU LAW: Text, Cases, and Materials (4th ed. 2008), 105.Google Scholar
111 See Wyatt, supra note 42, 487–488, criticizing the ECJ for thus being selective about the constitutional values it promotes.Google Scholar
112 Article 5(3) EU Treaty:Google Scholar
** “Under the principle of subsidiarity, in areas which do not fall within its exclusive competence, the Union shall act if and in so far as the objectives of the proposed action cannot be sufficiently achieved by the Member States, either at central level or regional level or local level, but can rather by reason of the scale or effects of the proposed action, be better achieved at Union level”.Google Scholar
** Article 5(3) TEU also refers to Protocol on the Application of the Principles of Subsidiarity and Proportionality. An equivalent clause was included in the Single European Act 1986, inserting Article 130r(4) EEC Treaty, specifically for environmental matters. See Schütze, supra note 4, 248.Google Scholar
113 See Obradovic, supra note 7, 77–78. A very large body of literature has developed on subsidiarity and the following list refers to the more frequently cited and/or more recent contributions: Theodore Schilling, Subsidiarity as a Rule and a Principle, or: Taking Subsidiarity Seriously, New York University Jean Monnet Working Paper No. 10/1995 (1995); Gráinne de Búrca, The Principle of Subsidiarity and the Court of Justice as an Institutional Actor, 36(2) Journal of Criminal Market Studies 217 (1998); Andreas F⊘llesdal, Subsidiarity and Democratic Deliberation, ARENA Working Papers No. 21/99 (1999); Antonio Estella, The EU Principle of Subsidiarity and ITS Critique (2002); Nick Barber, The Limited Modesty of Subsidiarity, 11(3) ELJ 308 (2005); Matthias Kumm, Constitutionalising Subsidiarity in Integrated Markets: the Case of Tobacco Regulation in the European Union, 12(4) ELJ 503 (2006); Davies, supra note 37; Ester Herlin-Karnell, Subsidiarity in the Area of EU Justice and Home Affairs Law – A Lost Cause?, 15(3) ELJ 351 (2009). See further references in Schütze (2009), 244, n. 7.Google Scholar
114 Case C-233/94, Germany v. European Parliament and Council, 1997 E.C.R. I-2405, paras 26–28.Google Scholar
115 Case C-103/01, Commission v. Germany, 2003 E.C.R. I-5369, paras. 46–47. Similarly, see Case C-491/01, R v. Secretary of State for Health, ex parte British American Tobacco (Investments) Ltd., 2002 E.C.R. 1–11453, paras. 177–185; Case C-154/04, The Queen, on the application of Alliance for Natural Health and Nutri-Link Ltd. v. Secretary of State for Health, 2005 E.C.R. I-6451, paras. 106–108.Google Scholar
116 As noted by, e.g. Soriano, supra note 12, 331; Schütze, supra note 4, 254, describing this line of reasoning by the ECJ as an ‘ontological tautology'. This general point was made by the ECJ itself in Tobacco Advertising in relation to the scope of Community competition law, where it observed that if any potential impact on competition was enough to bring a matter within the competence of the Community, its “legislative competence would be practically unlimited”: Case 376/98, Germany v. Parliament, supra note 26, paras. 106–107. Following Case C-300/89 Commission v. Council Titanium Dioxide, 1991 E.C.R. I-2867, para. 23, the ECJ said such an impact must be ‘appreciable': Case 376/98, Germany v. Parliament, id., para. 106. The decision in Kadi seems open to the criticism of not articulating how the appreciable impact standard applied to the inclusion of sanctions against individuals under the First Pillar as an internal market issue: see, Joined Cases C-402/05 P and C-415/05 P, Kadi, supra note 32, paras. 228–231.Google Scholar
117 Estella, supra note 113, 114–115.Google Scholar
118 See, e.g. Craig, supra note 37, 426–427.Google Scholar
119 Kumm, supra note 113. See also Davies, supra note 37, 76–77, noting that the Commission's application of subsidiarity does not give any explicit consideration to national autonomy.Google Scholar
120 Kumm, supra note 113, 524.Google Scholar
121 Id., 520.Google Scholar
122 See generally, recently, e.g. Anthony Giddens, Patrick Diamond & Roger Liddle, Global Europe Social Europe (2006); Brian Bercusson, European Labour Law (2nd ed. 2009), 5–12; Christian Joerges & Florian Rödl, Informal Politics, Formalised Law and the ‘Social Deficit’ of European Integration: Reflections after the Judgments of the ECJ in Viking and Laval, 15(1) ELJ 1–2 (2009), describing ‘Social Europe’ as “the ensemble of European social and labour law and policy and social rights…. A wide and opaque field…”.Google Scholar
123 See Case 80/70, Defrenne v. Belgian State ('Defrenne I'), 1971 E.C.R. 1-445; Case 43/75, Defrenne v. SABENA (‘Defrenne II'), 1976 E.C.R. 455; Case 149/77, Defrenne v. SABENA, 1978 E.C.R. 1365 ('Defrenne III') interpreting Article 119EEC Treaty (now Article 157 TFEU).Google Scholar
124 Case C-438/05, The International Transport Workers’ Federation and The Finnish Seamen's Union v. Viking Line ABP and Oil Viking Line Eesti, 2007 E.C.R. I-10779. The facts concerned collective action taken by a Finnish trade union and by the International transport Workers’ Federation against a Finnish ferry operator, which reflagged a vessel from Finland to Estonia in order to reduce labour costs. The ECJ held that whether such a restriction on the freedom to provide services could be justified in the circumstances was matter for the national court (id., para. 81 onwards) according to the test established in previous caselaw for such restrictions (id., para. 75).Google Scholar
125 Case C-341/05, Laval un Partneri Ltd. v. Svenska Byggnadsarbetareföbundet, 2007 E.C.R. I-11767. The facts concerned collective action taken by a Swedish trade union against a Latvian company, which had a Swedish subsidiary to which workers were posted to provide a building service in Sweden, in an attempt by the trade union to enforce the provision of a Swedish collective agreement concerning minimum pay. For academic discussion of Viking and Laval, see, e.g. Anne C.L. Davies, One Step Forward, Two Steps Back? The Viking and Laval Cases in the ECJ, 37(2) Industrial Law Journal 126 (2008); Alicia Hinarejos, Laval and Viking: The Right to Collective Action versus EU Fundamental Freedoms, 8(4) Human Rights Law Review 714 (2008); Norbert Reich, Free Movement v. Social Rights in an Enlarged Union – The Laval and Viking Case before the ECJ, 9(2) GLJ 125–161 (2008); Rebecca Zahn, The Viking and Laval Cases in the Context of European Enlargement, 3 Web Journal of Current Legal Issues (2008); and from a constitutional perspective, Joerges & Rödl, supra note 122.Google Scholar
126 The scope of free movement has also recently become a point of contention in the context of the rights of spouses of EU citizens from third countries: see, e.g. Steve Peers, Free Movement, Immigration Control and Constitutional Conflict, 5(2) European Constitutional Law Review 173 (2009).Google Scholar
127 Case C-438/05, Viking, supra note 124, paras. 39–40. See also the Opinion of Advocate General Maduro in Viking, at paras. 23–28; Case C-341/05, Laval, supra note 125, paras. 87–88.Google Scholar
128 Case 376/98, Germany v. Parliament, supra note 26, paras. 106–107. See, e.g. Dougan, supra note 7, 654, referring to the ‘new judicial wind’ on competence issues in light of Tobacco Advertising. Google Scholar
129 Case C-376/98, Germany v. Parliament and Council, supra note 26, para. 66.Google Scholar
130 Criticising the vagueness of the ECJ criteria in Laval and Viking, see Zahn, supra note 124.Google Scholar
131 Case C-341/05, Laval, supra note 125, para. 70.Google Scholar
132 Case C-341/05, Laval, id, the EG held that free movement principles might legitimately be restricted by the fundamental right to strike (para. 57), but that “… however, as regards the specific obligations, linked to signature of the collective agreement for the building sector, which the trade unions seek to impose on undertakings established in other Member States by way of collective action such as that at issue in the case in the main proceedings, the obstacle which that collective actions forms cannot be justified with regard to such an objective” (para 108). When such an objective could have justifying force is unclear. Compared to Viking, the ECJ decision in Laval seems to leave national courts with less autonomy or discretion in balancing the free movement principle with legitimate exceptions (e.g. compare para. 65 in Viking). Google Scholar
133 Case C-67/96, Albany, 1999 E.C.R. I-5751, paras. 59–64. The facts concerned a collective agreement between organisations representing employers and workers setting up a sectoral pension fund to which affiliation was made compulsory.Google Scholar
134 See para. 27 of the Opinion of Advocate General Maduro.Google Scholar
135 For a broad view as to the scope of Article 81 EC Treaty, suggesting that factors other than purely economic in the narrow sense should be considered relevant, see Whish, Richard, Competition Law (5th ed. 2003), 152–155.Google Scholar
136 See, e. g. Joerges & Rödl, supra note 122, 17–18, criticising the decision on this ground and noting that Advocate General Mengozzi negated too the effects of Article 137(5) ECT.Google Scholar
137 Joerges & Rödl, supra note 122, 18.Google Scholar
138 Currently, Article 153(5) TFEU (ex Article 137(5) ECT) states that “The provisions of this Article shall not apply to pay, the right of association, the right to strike or the right to impose lock-outs.”Google Scholar
139 Joerges & Rödl, supra note 122, 15, and referring to “European usurpation of Member States’ labour constitutions”.Google Scholar
140 Another significant effect of Laval and Viking was to extend horizontal direct effect to trade unions: see ibid, 13–15; Hinarejos, supra note 125, 722.Google Scholar
141 This section is concerned with external relations arising from what was previously the Community Pillar, rather than with the CFSP. For recent discussion of the boundary line between the CFSP and general external relations pursuant to the common market, see e.g. Eisenhut, supra note 42; Herlin-Karnell, supra note 113.Google Scholar
142 Case 22/70, ERTA, supra note 33, paras. 17–19, 28–31. The Court also held in ERTA that the implied external competence entailed by the doctrine of parallelism could arise where the Community had not yet exercised any internal competence if Member State action could place in jeopardy or undermine the Community objective sought to be attained, although it seemed to place more weight on the latter requirement in Opinion 1/94 Re WTO Agreement, 1994 E.C.R. I 5267.Google Scholar
143 Case 22/70, ERTA, supra note 33, paras. 12,17.Google Scholar
144 Id., para. 11.Google Scholar
145 See, e.g. the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY) in Prosecutor v. Stanislav Galic, IT-98-29-T, Trial Chamber I, 5th December 2003, para. 91. See also Brunno Simma & Dirk Pulkowski, Of Planets and the Universe: Self-contained Regimes in International Law, 17(3) European Journal of International Law 483, 505, 507 (2006).Google Scholar
146 Mitchelde S.-O.-L'E. Lasser, Judicial Deliberations: A Comparative Analysis of Judicial Transparency and Legitimacy 103–115 (2004).Google Scholar
147 See, e.g. Dashwood, supra note 42, 357.Google Scholar
148 See generally Bruno de Witte, Rules of Change in International Law: How Special is the European Community?, 25 Netherlands Yearbook of International Law 299 (1994).Google Scholar
149 Cases 3, 4 & 6/76, Kramer, 1976 E.C.R. 1279.Google Scholar
150 Opinion 1/76Re Draft Agreement Establishing a Laying-up Fund for Inland Waterway Vessels, 1977 E.C.R. 741.Google Scholar
151 Opinion 1/94 Re WTO Agreement, supra note 142, at paras. 85–86.Google Scholar
152 Opinion 2/91 Re Convention No. 170 International Labour Organisation on Safety in the Use of Chemicals at Work, 1993 E.C.R. I-1061, para. 25.Google Scholar
153 See, e.g. Craig, supra note 37, 412.Google Scholar
154 Case C-467/98, Commission v. Germany, 2002 E.C.R. I-9855. See Craig, supra note 37, 414–415.Google Scholar
155 Opinion 1/91 Re European Economic Area Agreement I, 1991 E.C.R. 6079.Google Scholar
156 Id., at 6081–6082.Google Scholar
157 Jo Shaw, European Union Legal Studies in Crisis? Towards a New Dynamic, 16(2) OJLS 231, 239 (1996).Google Scholar
158 Valentin Constantinesco, The ECJ as Law-maker: Praeter aut Contra Legem?, in Judicial Review in European Law: Essays in Honour of Lord Slynn, 79 (David O'Keeffe & Antonio Bavasso eds., 2001).Google Scholar
159 See generally Karen Alter, Who are “Masters of the Treaties”? European Governments and the European Court of Justice, 52(1) International Oraganization 121 (1998).Google Scholar
160 Opinion 1/03 Re Lugano Convention, 2006 E.C.R. I–1145, paras. 124–126.Google Scholar
161 1950, ETS no. 05.Google Scholar
162 Opinion 2/94, supra note 15, para. 30.Google Scholar
163 Schütze, supra note 4, 142.Google Scholar
164 Stephen Weatherill, Activism and Restraint in the European Court of Justice, in Asserting Jurisdiction: International and European Legal Perspectives, 255, 271 (Patrick Capps, Malcolm Evans & Stratos Konstadinidis eds., 2003).Google Scholar
165 Craig, supra note 37, 408. The question has been superseded by Treaty amendment, with Article 6(2) TEU (post-Lisbon) providing for EU accession to the ECHR.Google Scholar
166 Opinion 1/94 Re WTO Agreement, supra note 142.Google Scholar
167 Id., para. 46.Google Scholar
168 Schütze, supra note 4, 172.Google Scholar
169 2001 E.C.R. I–9713. On the facts, the EG in effect applied lex specialis, holding that the environmental provisions of the EC Treaty related to the primary purpose of the international treaty in dispute and thus (ex) Article 175 ECT was the correct legal basis.Google Scholar
170 Id., para. 23.Google Scholar
171 Case C-459/03, European Commission v. Ireland (‘MOX Plant'), 2006 E.C.R. 1–4635. For discussion, see Cardwell, Paul James, Who Decides? The ECJ Judgment on Jurisdiction in the MOX Plant Dispute, 19(1) Journal of Environmental Law 121 (2006); Nicholas Lavranos, The MOX Plant and IJzeren Rijn Disputes: Which Court Is the Supreme Arbiter?, 19(1) Leiden Journal of International Law 223 (2006); Cesare PR. Romano, ‘(Case Note) Case C-459/03, Commission of the European Communities v. Ireland', 101(1) American Journal of International Law 171 (2007).Google Scholar
172 December 1982, 1833 UNTS 396.Google Scholar
173 Case C-459/03, MOXPIant, supra note 171, para. 154.Google Scholar
174 See id., para. 130.Google Scholar
175 In response to Ireland's argument that recourse to UNCLOS could be construed as a method of settlement within the scope of Article 292, the EG simply observed “an international agreement such as the Convention cannot affect the exclusive jurisdiction of the Court”: id., para. 132.Google Scholar
176 See Soriano, supra note 12, 331, noting with reference to the overall approach of the ECJ to competence (in its interpretation of Articles 95 and 308 ECT and of the subsidiarity principle), “The consequences for member states’ defence of their political interest could not be more negative…”.Google Scholar
177 The ECJ simply declared the risk to the Community order to be ‘manifest’ even though Ireland had offered an assurance that it would not seek to litigate any provisions of Community law in an arbitral tribunal: Case C-459/03, MOX Plant, supra note 171, para. 154–156. On the latter point, the Advocate General offered somewhat more explicit reasoning, suggesting the fact that provisions of Community law coincided with international rules that Ireland had asked to be adjudicated by a tribunal was enough to breach Article 292 ECT: see Opinion of Advocate General Maduro, 18th January 2006, para. 51. This line of reasoning, however, has potentially very extensive implications on a broad reading: any rule of international law that coincides with EU law cannot be litigated by a Member State before an international court or tribunal.Google Scholar
178 Opinion 1/03Re Lugano Convention, supra note 157.Google Scholar
179 Lugano Convention on Jurisdiction and Enforcement of Judgments in Civil and Commercial Matters 1988, 28 ILM 620 (1989).Google Scholar
180 Opinion 1/03, supra note 157, paras. 150–173.Google Scholar
181 Thalia Kruger, Opinion 1/03, Competence of the Community to conclude the new Lugano Convention on the Jurisdiction and the recognition and enforcement of judgments in civil and commercial matters, 12 Columbia Journal of European Law 189, 198–199 (2006–2007).Google Scholar
182 Obradovic, supra note 7, 84–85; Soriano, supra note 12, 333.Google Scholar
183 On the application of Article 308 ECT in this more specific sense, see Schütze, supra note 4, 136–137.Google Scholar
184 Dashwood (2004), supra note 42, 380.Google Scholar
- 6
- Cited by