Published online by Cambridge University Press: 06 March 2019
European Union citizenship is derived from Member State nationality. This fact often has been considered a “birth defect” to be overcome by either disconnecting EU citizenship from Member State citizenship or by reversing the relationship in a federal model so that Member State citizenship would be derived from that of the Union. I argue in this essay that derivative citizenship in a union of states can be defended as a potentially stable and democratically attractive basic feature of the architecture of the EU polity where EU citizenship is perceived of as one layer in a multi-level model of democratic membership in a union of states such as the EU. This perspective is not a defense of the status quo, but rather allows for—or even requires—a series of reforms addressing a number of inconsistencies and democratic deficiencies in the current citizenship regime.
Most academics writing about Union citizenship tend to compare it to that which they know best: Nation State citizenship. It then comes as no surprise when they conclude that the current construction of EU citizenship is internally incoherent, externally not sufficiently inclusive, and also lacking in democratic legitimacy. To a certain degree, I agree with this criticism; however, such authors often apply the wrong standard of comparison and therefore are likely to promote faulty solutions. As the EU Treaties clearly have spelled out since the 1997 Treaty of Amsterdam, EU citizenship is complementary or additional to Member State nationality without replacing it. National citizenship is a constitutive element of EU citizenship and therefore cannot serve as an external standard of comparison.
1 See Pettit, Philip, Republicanism. A Theory of Freedom and Government (1997); Quentin Skinner, Liberty Before Liberalism (1998).Google Scholar
2 Brubaker, William Rogers, Citizenship Struggles in Soviet Successor States, 26(2) Int'l Migration Rev. 269, 277–84 (1992).Google Scholar
3 See Bauböck, Rainer, Temporary Migrants, Partial Citizenship and Hypermigration, 14(5) Critical Rev. of Int'l Soc. & Pol. Phil. 665, 685 (2011).Google Scholar
4 This is a relatively recent development. Birthright citizenship in municipalities (Heimatrecht) in late 19th century Austria and Germany was used to restrict internal migration by denying poverty relief and access to local public services to citizens residing outside their municipality of birth. Switzerland's Bürgergemeinden, in which membership is acquired at birth, is a historical remnant of this system. Today's hukou system in the Peoples' Republic of China is an extreme case of local birthright citizenship as an instrument of exclusion from social welfare. This is based on ius sanguinis so that rural hukou status is even inherited by the second generation of migrant-descent born in cities.Google Scholar
5 See Shaw, Jo, The Transformation of Citizenship in the European Union: Electoral Rights and the Restructuring of Political Space 77–80 (2007).Google Scholar
6 See Schönberger, Christoph, Unionsbürger: Europas föderales Bürgerrrecht in vergleichender Sicht 122–24 (2005).Google Scholar
7 In the United States of America, birthright citizenship was established as a federal power through the 14th Amendment of 1868. Withdrawal of citizenship remained largely under the control of state courts and comprehensive protection against denaturalization was only provided by a 1967 landmark decision of the Supreme Court. See Afroim v. Rusk, 387 U.S. 253 (1967); Patrick Weil, The Sovereign Citizen: Denaturalization and the Origins of the American Republic (2013).Google Scholar
8 Eva Ersb&ll, Nationality Law in Denmark, Finland, and Sweden, in Towards a European Nationality: Citizenship, Immigration and Nationality Law in the EU 230, 233–34 (Randall Hansen & Patrick Weil eds., 2001).Google Scholar
9 Janko Rottmann v. Freistaat Bayern, CJEU Case C-135/08, 2010 E.C.R. I-1449.Google Scholar
10 Gerardo Ruiz Zambrano v. Office national de l'emploi, CJEU Case C-34/09, 2011 E.C.R. I-1177.Google Scholar
11 For a debate on this question, see Rainer Bauböck, Philippe Cayla & Catriona Seth, Should EU citizens living in other member states vote there in national elections? (RSCAS Working Paper No. 32, 2012), http://eudo-citizenship.eu/docs/RSCAS_2012_32.pdf.Google Scholar
12 Stevens, Jacqueline, States Without Nations: Citizenship for Mortals (2001).Google Scholar
13 Carens, Joseph H., Aliens and Citizens: The Case for Open Borders, 49(2) The Rev. of Pol. 251, 252 (1987); Ayelet Shachar, The Birthright Lottery: Citizenship and Global Inequality 8–13 (2009).Google Scholar
14 See supra text accompanying note 4.Google Scholar
15 United Nations, International Migration Report 2006: A Global Assessment, E. a. S. A. P. Division (2006).Google Scholar
16 EU Citizenship - Statistics on Cross-border Activities, Eurostat (May 19, 2014), http://epp.eurostat.ec.europa.eu/statistics_explained/index.php/EU_citizenship_-_statistics_on_cross-border_activities.Google Scholar
17 See Pedroza, Luicy, Citizenship Before Nationality: How Democracies Redefine Citizenship by Debating the Extension of Voting Rights to Settled Immigrants (2012) (unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, University of Bremen) (on file with author).Google Scholar
18 On 4 July 2012, the German Constitutional Court abolished the three-month German residence requirement for external voting in German elections. Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG - Federal Constitutional Court], Case No. 2 BvC 1/11, 132 Entscheidungen des Bundesverfassungsgerichts [BVerfGE] 39 (Apr. 7, 2012). In the 2013 national elections, German citizens without prior residence in Germany could vote if they could demonstrate some familiarity with German politics and that they were affected by it, see http://www.konsularinfo.diplo.de/wahlen.Google Scholar
19 See Bauböck, Rainer, Stakeholder Citizenship and Transnational Political Participation: A Normative Evaluation of External Voting, 75(5) Fordham L. Rev. 2393, 2446 (2007).Google Scholar