Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T16:55:33.343Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Ciceronian Jurisprudence and the Law of Nations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 October 2023

Jeffrey Dymond*
Affiliation:
Historisches Seminar, University of Zurich, Zurich, Switzerland
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

At the turn of the seventeenth century, jurists such as Alberico Gentili (1552–1608) and Hugo Grotius (1583–1645), began to advance a novel account of the law of nations (ius gentium) as a law that binds a world of sovereign states. That they would produce such a theory is surprising, however, considering that sovereign states were neither the dominant form of political organization at the time, nor did conventional medieval jurisprudence treat them as the normative standard. This article traces this evolution to a broader transformation in legal interpretation. In an effort to put Roman law on a more rational foundation, jurists such as François Connan (1508–51) and Hugues Doneau (1527–91) connected the origin of law to the unfolding of a certain account of human sociability, with the result that a conception of the state as an autonomous body acquired a normative status within their version of the global legal order. It then argues that we should see Gentili’s work on the ius gentium as part of this tradition. In so doing, the article demonstrates how the innovations of a particular school of legal interpretation, by combining Roman law with a distinctive social theory, contributed to making the sovereign state the legal norm.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

The period from the late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries was a pivotal moment in the history of the ‘law of nations’ (ius gentium). After entering Roman jurisprudence in the third century BCE as a body of private law institutions, the ius gentium went through a number of evolutions throughout its history. But it was in the early modern period, in the work of figures such as Alberico Gentili (1552–1608) and Hugo Grotius (1583–1645), that it began to assume a dramatically different appearance, and one which it would sustain for several centuries: as a body of law that binds a world of states, regulating the relations between them and defining the obligations of their governments.Footnote 1 Historians link this evolution to the collapse, in the aftermath of the Renaissance and the Reformation, of the old medieval conception of universal empire, and the approximately simultaneous rise to prominence of the idea that the world is divided into independent, or sovereign, states.Footnote 2 It was within this context that jurists then turned to the law of nations as a source of principles for understanding the nature of sovereign states, as well for regulating the relations between them.Footnote 3

It is surprising, however, that legal argument in the sixteenth century would adopt the assumption that the world is divided into individual autonomous states. The political reality of the time still appeared very medieval, in fact: a patchwork of city-states, kingdoms, feudalities, religious bodies, and empires, with the composite nature of the early modern Holy Roman Empire as perhaps the most prominent example. Even within increasingly centralized monarchies such as France, the monarch’s position still depended on negotiations between, and privileges for, various nobles and, on occasion, cities.Footnote 4 If the jurists had attempted to make the law match reality, they should have adopted a different approach. With this in mind, my aim here is to offer some explanation for how and why the ius gentium came to assume a world of states, and thus an explanation for how and why the independent state came to be seen as the legal norm.

Some historians have suggested that this contrast between political reality and legal theory could in fact be a function of jurists following the internal drive of the law. Annabel Brett and Nehal Bhuta have each made distinctive arguments showing how Hugo Grotius’s state theory reflects this tension between an idea of the state as a single locus of sovereignty, which he apparently derived from strict legal reasoning, and his contemporary political situation, defined by heterogeneous political forms.Footnote 5 However, when we turn towards the history of the ius gentium, the idea that it would treat a particular state concept as the normative political body appears a distinctively early modern innovation. Such an idea was, in fact, foreign to both ancient and medieval writing on the ius gentium. When the ius gentium first emerged as Rome’s empire began to grow, it was created as a means to resolve disputes between citizens and the growing group of non-citizens. It was concerned with individuals, not political bodies.Footnote 6 Far from being, as it would eventually become, a source of rights for states against the imperialist pretensions of others, the ius gentium at its origin was very much the product of empire, designed explicitly to govern individual imperial subjects.Footnote 7

The status of political bodies under medieval jurisprudence is more complicated, but, even with these developments, the ius gentium was still far from assuming a world of independent states. There is an established tradition of historical argument which holds that the idea of the independent state as a juridical entity capable of bearing its own rights and obligations is an outgrowth of medieval ius gentium literature.Footnote 8 The key figures in this development are the so-called ‘Commentators’, most famously Bartolus of Saxoferrato (1313–57) and his student Baldus de Ubaldis (1327–1400). With the circumstances of northern Italian city-states in mind, they appealed to two passages in the Digest – 1.1.5 and 1.1.9 – to argue that, in the event that a city does not obey the Holy Roman Emperor, it possesses a right under the ius gentium as a ‘people’ to govern itself.Footnote 9 Baldus’s idea would then go on to structure many influential sixteenth-century works on political theory, including serving as the basis for Jean Bodin’s (1530–96) immensely important theory of the sovereign state.Footnote 10 It is Bodin’s concept of sovereignty, in particular, that many historians argue enabled later jurists to sort through the contemporary mix of political bodies and award higher standing to one form over the others.Footnote 11

Yet while the ius gentium of conventional medieval jurisprudence did indeed appear to grant distinctive rights to certain political bodies, it must be underlined that they were nevertheless held to remain under the de iure authority of the Holy Roman Emperor, and thus were not fully independent.Footnote 12 The medieval juridical picture of the world, very much like the medieval political world, was defined by overlapping layers of various sorts of jurisdictions, with the emperor (and sometimes the pope) on top.Footnote 13 The bodies whose self-government were defended by Bartolus and Baldus were thus one type of institution among others; they were not considered to be the natural norm, and accordingly they possessed no elevated standing in law.Footnote 14

It is my contention here that the evolution of the ius gentium into a law that assumes a world of independent states was enabled by another development in legal reasoning. I will argue in what follows that the early to mid-sixteenth century saw introduced into legal argument by a select group of jurists a social ontology, derived from the Roman political writer Cicero, to explain the origin of law, which had the effect of entrenching a particular idea of the nature and aims of the individual political community as normative within the global legal order. As I will demonstrate below, this generated a conception of the ius gentium in which a concept of the independent state became not merely a subject of that law, but in fact the very hinge of a system contained within it, bearing special rights and obligations related to its pre-eminent status. It is this revised account of the ius gentium, I argue, that then went on to structure some of the initial early modern works on the law of nations. It has been observed that the normative ideal of the state contained within this ius gentium literature shaped the behaviour of various contemporary actors, from the way European powers responded to events on the continent, such as the Dutch revolt, to how they operated in other parts of the world.Footnote 15 My goal here is to demonstrate on what grounds it acquired this status.

Properly acknowledging the significance of this development requires us to incorporate an additional group of jurists into our historical account of the ius gentium whose contribution has so far been overlooked. I will argue here that we must consider a group of jurists from France, François Connan (1508–51), Hugues Doneau (1527–91), and, to a lesser extent, Andrea Alciato (1492–1550), as key early examples of this new tendency in legal scholarship. These individuals are widely acknowledged to be important figures in ‘legal humanism’, a diverse movement of jurists who in various ways were critical of medieval scholastic methods, and who employed the philological and historical insights of the Renaissance in the study of Roman law.Footnote 16 Among the various tendencies of legal humanism, the most well known is one that used humanist methods to historicize Roman law, which, in turn, led some of them to question its relevance for contemporary society.Footnote 17 But there were other tendencies, as well, including one that saw the Roman law as an expression of a universal law, even if its exposition in the Corpus iuris was not systematic and rational. Connan’s and Doneau’s respective commentaries on the Corpus iuris, which will be central to the following argument, are among the most prominent examples of this genre.Footnote 18 As followers of this tendency, they made consequential revisions in their legal theories that enabled the independent state to become the juridical norm. For it was in their effort to reconstruct this universal law and present it in a systematic fashion that they appealed to the moral, philosophical, and rhetorical works of Cicero.Footnote 19 And it is due to the central place they attribute to Cicero’s account of natural reason and human nature in their account of universal law that they could construct a wider legal system which bestows a normative status to a naturally constituting, and thus independent, institution which they called the res publica.

In the article’s first section, I address how Connan and Doneau portrayed the origin of law, and of the ius gentium, in particular. I will demonstrate that they envisioned this process as a gradual, historical process, with the result that both the manner and the circumstances in which it unfolded shaped its contents. These contingencies produced a world dispersed into entities called gentes, understood as groupings of individuals bound by shared laws. In the second section, I show how the ius gentium further developed historically in a manner that transformed these entities from groups of individual legal subjects into rights-bearing subjects of the ius gentium themselves. This happens, I argue, because the ius gentium evolved to give gentes a particular function: they came to assume the role of enforcing the rights and obligations of their members.

Having established that the incorporation of this social ontology results in a significantly revised account of the ius gentium from what had been standard earlier, I then turn, in the third section, to argue that this same Ciceronian jurisprudence would go on to structure one of the classic early works on the ius gentium as a law that binds states. My example in this section will be Alberico Gentili, a canonical figure in the history of the early modern ius gentium who is considered to be among the first to structure his exposition of global law around the assumption that the world is a community of autonomous states. My aim here is not to argue that Gentili had Connan and Doneau as sources on this issue, although this is possible. It is to argue, instead, that the Ciceronian jurisprudence of which Connan and Doneau were early examples had come to constitute a foundation for the same kind of universal legal reasoning in which Gentili was also engaged. In much the same way that this foundation led Connan and Doneau to attribute to a particular concept of the state a pre-eminent standing in the ius gentium, so, too, did it lead Gentili. I will then say a few words in conclusion about the appearance of this broader legal theory in early modern works primarily focused on domestic politics.

I

Both Connan and Doneau discuss the origin of law in general, and of the ius gentium in particular, in their commentaries on the first chapter of the Digest, entitled ‘Concerning justice and law’. The ius gentium, these jurists argued, is the second of a tri-partite division of law, alongside the universal natural law and the particular civil law. This division is rather conventional; but, as we will see, their approach to it is highly distinctive in one, especially significant respect. Whereas many of their jurist predecessors and contemporaries conceived of the ius gentium as a form of positive law shared among all peoples that is distinct from, and sometimes at odds with, natural law, Connan and Doneau thought of the two laws as compatible.Footnote 20 While natural law, strictly speaking, is contained in the initial dictates of natural reason within a state of nature, ius gentium is the form natural law assumes as that same natural reason is applied within a progressively advancing society. As a result, the institutions of the ius gentium developed historically, and, as we will see, this is a crucial factor in how institutions we could describe as independent states came to acquire a unique and prominent place within it.

It is when making this argument that they introduce their social ontology. Connan claims that the origin of ius gentium can be traced to the inability of the natural law as instinctively understood to govern more than merely a very simple way of life. ‘The first men, simple and rustic’, he says, ‘lacking desire and competition, and not seeking for themselves the protection of relatives or neighbours, but dispersed in mountains and forests, seem to have used natural law.’Footnote 21 Natural law is, then, the law of men who do not live in society, belonging ‘to solitary man, living life in the field with a wife and children’.Footnote 22

This ‘natural’ state of affairs could not last long, however. Joined to the possession of natural reason are other dispositions that push human beings beyond ‘life in the field’, and therefore into circumstances beyond the scope of the natural law. ‘But since [a man] is led by nature to associations (societates) and unions (coetus) of men’, Connan says, referencing a famous passage from Cicero’s De officiis, ‘he gradually moved outwards, first to an association (societas) with kin, then to one with extended family, then to friends, later to neighbours, and finally, through commerce, to an association (societas) that encompasses the whole of humanity.’Footnote 23 The cause of this outward movement is an aspiration to improve their condition, and it is on account of this motivation that these relationships assume a particular form: seeking utility, he says, ‘led them to live a more commodious life’, doing so ‘through the exchange of duties and commercial matters’.Footnote 24

Over time, then, a world characterized by scattered family groups eventually transformed into a world filled with a number of larger groups, with each group resembling a ‘neighbourhood’.Footnote 25 Initially, these groups were concentrated along family bloodlines and, for this reason, they acquired the name gentes, in the sense of having the same genus.Footnote 26 But, Connan is keen to stress, this is just a name that reflects the group’s beginnings. As he then proceeds to argue, gens quickly assumes another meaning over time: ‘a multitude of men using the same manners (mores)’.Footnote 27 Connan traces the appearance of these manners to the exigencies of living in the group. Living and trading in these groups, he claims, put their members in situations that the natural law was not equipped to handle. Reasoning that ‘it became necessary that they secure justice’, ‘that faith in contracts be observed’, and ‘that nobody betray what has been agreed’, they consequently began to formulate a set of rules, basing them on the spirit of the natural law.Footnote 28 Indeed, the aim of these rules is to make all group members ‘act with the same probity with foreigners and those unknown to them as they are accustomed to with their wife and children’, the primary relationship covered by natural law.Footnote 29 Following their natural reason, which ‘prescribed what is to be done or not done’, the participants in each group thus eventually developed a shared understanding of how to act in order to preserve them.Footnote 30 These laws, as they overlapped across these gentes, came to constitute the ius gentium, deriving its name from the fact that ‘human beings use it not so much in their capacity as…living beings who are participants in reason, but as peoples (gentes)’, engaged in social life.Footnote 31

Connan’s description of a gens as a group of individuals bound by the same laws rooted in natural reason situates this idea within a particularly Ciceronian tradition of thinking about the origin of society. In the opening chapters of his youthful rhetorical treatise, De inventione, Cicero claims that there was a time when human beings wandered the world in the manner of beasts, lacking the guidance of reason, religion, and law, and relying solely on physical strength for survival. Eventually, a man emerged who became aware of what Cicero describes as the potential latent in the rational minds of men, a potential that can only be harnessed through instruction. To capitalize on this potential, this man gathered the dispersed individuals into one place, where, through a combination of eloquence and reason, he convinced them that it was both reasonable and advantageous to abandon their brute and unorganized way of life, and to live together and obey the principles of justice, which are accessible to them through the natural reason they all share. After having been introduced to justice and convinced to follow it, the originally dispersed human beings from that moment on began to live ‘voluntarily’ according to its principles, becoming ‘kind and gentle’, and enabling them to reap the many advantages of their new co-operative life.Footnote 32

Cicero’s argument linking the establishment of society with knowledge of justice would be cited frequently by medieval and Renaissance authors, including jurists.Footnote 33 For example, Alciato, who was Connan’s teacher at Bourges, made Cicero’s fable central to an oration he gave ‘in praise of the civil law’. Alciato says here that it was through an orator’s introduction of laws rooted in natural reason that previously ‘unsociable’ (insociabile) men came to live a ‘civil’ life.Footnote 34 Connan himself would also cite the work as he elaborates upon his account of the origin of the ius gentium. An original lawgiver, he says, ‘brought together men dispersed in fields and joined them’, transforming ‘initially wild and unruly men into men peaceful and tame, with the result that they administer all things more through the judgement of the mind than through physical strength’.Footnote 35 This enables them, in turn, to create a society in which ‘they give and receive benefits from one to the other, taking nothing from another’s due, only each person thinking one and the same thing, namely, the utility of the whole’.Footnote 36

The significance of Connan’s participation in this Ciceronian tradition lies in what unites De inventione’s fable with Cicero’s more mature political thought. For, in a section of his De re publica transmitted to the medieval and early modern world through Augustine’s De civitate Dei, Cicero portrays these kinds of societies devoted to common utility and made possible by an agreement on justice as the foundation of one form of society in particular: the res publica. The res publica, he says, is the res populi, or thing of the populus. This populus, he continues, ‘is not every group of men assembled in any way, but an assemblage of some size associated (sociata) with one another through an agreement on law (iuris consensus) and a community of interest (utilitatis communio)’.Footnote 37 Connan’s claim that the ius gentium is the law that unites individuals into gentes very much suggests that the natural proliferation of these groups is the foundation of a world of res publicae. The gens, after all, is an ‘associated people (sociatus populus)’.Footnote 38

Doneau likewise understands a gens as a populus on Ciceronian terms. In his commentary on the same section of the Digest, he also collapses ius gentium into natural law.Footnote 39 Additionally, he endorses the conjoined claim that the ius gentium developed over time, as the human population grew and applied natural reason to a changing set of circumstances. Looking for the origins of the ius gentium thus requires going back to the ‘beginnings of this world’.Footnote 40 At that time, the existence of a small population slowly growing out from ‘the first two men’, and living within an environment of relative abundance, meant that individuals could take whatever they needed without ‘injuring’ or offending another.Footnote 41 Over time, however, the population began to increase, and the situation changed dramatically. ‘Led by the use of right reason (recta ratio), and confirmed by experience’, people reasoned that ‘either the human race can no longer be’, or ‘that those things, which a man cultivates, should be declared his own’, and that ‘it should not be allowed for others to take it without the will of its owner’.Footnote 42 For, they believed, without such a principle, this ‘scarcity of the things necessary for life’ would produce a number of disastrous consequences, ranging from natural material remaining uncultivated, to the existence of people living off the labours of others, to those who possess the most oppressing those who possess the least.Footnote 43 As a result, again applying ‘right reason’ (recta ratio), they imposed the ‘first law (lex) among human beings’, which declared – in a manner strikingly similar to a claim that would most famously be made by John Locke – that anything that anyone ‘cultivated or procured by their labour’ belonged to them alone and thus should be protected from others.Footnote 44

The institution of a right to private property then contributed to the separation of human beings into distinct groups. With the ‘distinct dominions’ among individuals resulting from the institution of the property law, Doneau says, it soon followed under this arrangement that, to avoid ‘indigence’, people needed to enter into trading relationships (commutationes), which ‘we call exchanges (commercia) and contracts (contractus)’.Footnote 45 Now concentrated into distinct networks of exchange, these groups soon established an assortment of commercial institutions, alongside a set of related ‘obligations’, including ‘buying, selling, tenancy, hiring, partnership, commission, trust, loans, and others of that sort’: all standard institutions of the ius gentium.Footnote 46 What we once again see, then, is that, after the institution of private property, the unfolding of natural reason led people to separate into distinct groups defined by their members’ subjection to the same set of laws, transforming what may previously have been a world of unorganized crowds, into a world of associations of individuals bound by shared laws: a world of populi.

II

Consisting at this point of a number of rules governing a limited set of commercial transactions, we are only halfway through the development of the ius gentium. Yet, even at this early moment, it is already apparent that Connan and Doneau are putting forward a significantly revised account of the law of nations. By claiming that the first ius gentium institutions to emerge are, for Connan, those falling under the umbrella of ‘obligations’, and, for Doneau, property followed by obligations, the two jurists appear deliberately to distance their views from Hermogenianus’s famous definition of the law of nations preserved in Digest 1.1.5. There, the Roman jurist enumerates the different parts of the ius gentium in the following order: ‘As a consequence of this ius gentium, wars were introduced, nations differentiated, kingdoms founded, properties individuated, estate boundaries settled, buildings put up, and commerce established, including contracts of buying and selling and letting and hiring.’Footnote 47 Although Hermogenianus does not explicitly claim that this order reflects the actual chronological sequence through which the ius gentium developed, both Bartolus and Baldus would later replicate this sequence in their commentaries on Digest 1.1.5, with Baldus endorsing it as a chronological account.Footnote 48 Following the sequence, Baldus claims that war, as the product of the ‘diverse minds of men’, is what led to the division of the world into different gentes, thus making possible all other ius gentium institutions.Footnote 49 This is a stark contrast: Connan and Doneau, as we have seen, saw gentes as the product of a natural inclination to co-operate enabled by a shared human reason, not conflict. Conflict and division do enter the picture for Connan and Doneau at a later point, however. But the fact that they do so after co-operation created gentes, and not before, is a key factor which shaped in crucial ways the eventual entrenchment of special rights for gentes themselves within the ius gentium.

Connan draws attention to the importance of this behavioural transformation by leveraging a traditional distinction between two different kinds of ius gentium: the ius gentium primum and the ius gentium secundum. Common in medieval jurisprudence, this distinction took various forms in the work of different authors. What unites the different opinions, though, is the view that they reflect a chronological sequence, with the ius gentium primum coming before, and sometimes being replaced by, the ius gentium secundum.Footnote 50 As the first laws to be promulgated, the obligations which created the gentes are, according to Connan, institutions of the ius gentium primum, and their legislation brought about a ‘golden age’.Footnote 51

But, eventually, moral corruption ushered in an ‘iron’ age, and this is the context for the legislation of the ius gentium secundum. Perhaps on account of the benefits derived from membership in gentes, increasing material wealth led to ‘luxury’, which, in turn, made people ‘endeavour to increase their possessions’ in the hopes that they do not appear ‘equal to someone else’. From this also followed a desire to ‘command’ and ‘to have licence to all things with the utmost impunity’.Footnote 52 These new circumstances dramatically de-stabilized society. Having ‘moved away from the road of nature’, and with many thinking that ‘nothing is worthier of esteem than excelling in wealth and power’, a number of terrible events occurred, such as ‘wars’, ‘seditions’, ‘factions’, and ‘thefts’.Footnote 53 The rule of law had begun to break down, jeopardizing, in turn, the existence of the gentes themselves.

It is important to see what follows within the broader historical trajectory of Connan’s account. Having initially established gentes during a time of virtue – during the ‘golden age’ – the members of each gens apparently remained conscious of the promise of benefits under justice that they offered, despite the difficulties they began to experience within them. They decided, then, to find ways to preserve them, including creating a new institution responsible for maintaining justice in these new circumstances. They reasoned, Connan says in an apparent reference to Cicero’s De officiis, that since the maintenance of the gens demanded ‘that an equality under the law’ be preserved, it became necessary to live under a power capable of enforcing juridical equality in the face of the risks to it generated by material inequality.Footnote 54 ‘Peoples’, he says, therefore ‘created kings’, who ensured that ‘that those among them who are poor would not be oppressed by those who have more’.Footnote 55

Doneau makes a similar argument. Faced with growing injustice, such an authority would ‘guard the public peace, keep citizens in their duties, punish wrong doing, and restore rights to citizens’.Footnote 56 Otherwise, ‘government according to the varied judgements of men’, on account of ‘a natural proclivity towards disagreement’, would ‘forcibly separate’ the group in conflicting directions.Footnote 57 In short, both authors agree that the integrity of the gens as a union of jural equals, to which its members had become attached, necessitated the creation of a set of public institutions tasked with preserving equal rights and formidable enough to do so within a diverse and materially unequal society.

But these authors also stipulate a further reason for the creation of political authority. Not only were they intended to ensure equality under the law internally, they were also established, as Connan says, to ensure that the ‘whole body of their subjects (universi) would not be oppressed by external enemies’.Footnote 58 Or, as Doneau puts it, ‘to protect cities’,Footnote 59 which were built ‘so that they would be stronger against the force and injustice of attacking enemies’.Footnote 60 This collectively authorized power, then, was expected both to enforce justice in the relations among its subjects and ensure that they were treated justly in their relations with foreigners.

With the creation and spread of this institution across the gentes, and thus their inclusion into the ius gentium, the character of these entities had changed. What had begun as a body of law intended to regulate commercial relations between individuals within each gens had now evolved in light of growing corruption to include a set of institutions to enforce them, attributing rights and obligations to these institutions in pursuit of these ends. By this point, then, the gens had become more than just the place in which the ius gentium was legislated; it had also, through its new public institutions, become a subject of the ius gentium itself.

That gentes taken collectively had indeed come to hold these rights and obligations is visible in what Connan and Doneau consider to be the next institution to emerge: the laws of war. Both authors clearly situate the emergence of these laws within the chronological development we have so far traced. ‘After [the elevation of kings]’, Connan states, came ‘the first principles of wars’.Footnote 61 Similarly, Doneau writes that ‘wars were introduced after states (civitatibus) and kingdoms (regnis) were founded’.Footnote 62 The laws of war, then, emerged in response to the circumstances that followed the attribution of rights to the gentes themselves, and it is for this reason that the ius gentium institution of war is restricted to gentes alone. Connan, for example, claims that the laws of war appeared, ‘so that the force of one people may be repelled by the force of another people, and that arms be repelled by arms’.Footnote 63 It is not difficult to see how the situation created by the attribution of rights and obligations to gentes taken collectively could produce this outcome. Matters of internal injustice can be settled straightforwardly, but each gens’s duty to defend the rights of their members could easily generate conflict between these bodies, making these conflicts places to settle disputes that are ultimately about right. Indeed, Doneau writes that wars were instituted ‘so that [states and kingdoms (civitatibus et regnis)] themselves could be maintained’, implying that war aims to preserve these entities as they pursue the things they were instituted to achieve.Footnote 64 An aim that means often ‘repelling enemies’, and ‘justly reclaiming things from them’.Footnote 65 The laws of war thus appear to have come into being between the various gentes for much the same reason that political authority did within each gens: as a set of institutions designed to secure the rights, and to enforce the obligations, of the relevant parties, which in this case are the gentes themselves.

After war, and derivative from its aims, came slavery and manumission, the final institutions of the ius gentium and marking the end of its development.Footnote 66 The overall picture we receive from this account, then, is that the law of nations develops over time as the product of a particular account of social development. First, natural instinct and natural reason among individuals unfolds in such a way that leads to a world of co-operative and harmonious gentes, or populi. Second, in the face of proliferating moral corruption, and to preserve these bodies to which their members had already become attached, each gens comes to acquire in their collective capacity through their common institutions the role of securing equal justice for their members. Finally, this prominent role becomes further entrenched through the legislation of the laws of war, which, limited to gentes exclusively, aims to enable them to pursue their ends. Taken as a whole, the version of the ius gentium offered here embodies a legal system that hinges around the fundamental role of gentes and their collective institutions, without which there can be no justice and, by extension, no society. In a final argument, Connan returns to Digest 1.1.5, where he claims that Hermogenianus (and, by implication, both Bartolus and Baldus) in fact erred by counting ‘wars and kingdoms as among [the ius gentium’s] first institutions’.Footnote 67 He then says, as if to draw attention specifically to the originality of his argument, that wars and kingdoms are the final pieces of a historically constructed system that promotes utility and justice in a world of independent states, that, ‘on our accounting, they should be placed last’.Footnote 68

III

Having reconstructed Connan’s and Doneau’s revised account of the ius gentium, I will now argue that we can observe similar allegiances in the work of Alberico Gentili. First, and more generally, Gentili shares many of the methodological concerns of his humanist predecessors. As Giovanni Minnucci has shown, despite an early methodological work critical of legal humanism – the De iuris interpretibus dialogi sex (1582) – Gentili’s mature jurisprudence reflects a mix of traditional medieval methods, on the one hand, and the new legal humanistic ones, on the other.Footnote 69 In opposition to the strand of legal humanism that had come to regard the Corpus iuris as a relic of a past age, Gentili firmly believed that the Justinianic texts do indeed embody true law.Footnote 70 Yet he also believed that a proper understanding of why the Justinianic texts hold this status requires the serious study of history, philology, philosophy, and theology. Bringing these two aspects together was Gentili’s belief, as Minnucci puts it, that the jurist must ‘research the principles that should supervise human relations’.Footnote 71 The Corpus iuris, in other words, was an expression of true, natural justice, and this claim can and should be supported with reference to history, philosophy, and other parts of the humanist syllabus. As we will now see, Gentili also turns to Cicero to elucidate the foundations of his legal theory, from which it follows, in a similar manner as Connan and Doneau before him, that the ius gentium embodies a legal system that divides the world into independent states.Footnote 72

Gentili’s most significant treatise on the ius gentium is his De iure belli of 1598 (DIB), which concerns the laws of war. The ‘law of nations’, he says, ‘is that which is in use among all human beings, and which is equally observed by all mankind’.Footnote 73 It follows from this, he continues with reference to Cicero’s Tusculanae disputationes, that the ius gentium is natural law: ‘the agreement of all nations about a matter must be regarded as a law of nature’.Footnote 74 ‘Such laws’, he then says with a quote from Cicero’s Pro Milone, ‘are not written, but inborn; we have not learned, received and read them, but we have wrested, drawn, and forced them out of nature herself’.Footnote 75 Gentili’s equation of the law of nations with natural law, and the related claim that the ius gentium is natural reason applied – ‘wrested, drawn, forced’ – as society and politics developed across the world, connects his theory in an important way to that of Connan and Doneau. As we have seen, this is what gives their theory its historical character. Moreover, it is due to this historical character – due to the fact that human beings first applied natural reason to promulgate the laws that created gentes, and then did the same when they tried to secure them – that led the global legal order to develop in such a way that made the gens the cornerstone of the system.

This is an historical account, and a related conclusion, which Gentili endorses. He does so in his De legationibus (1585), in which he argues that the right to send ambassadors is limited to those entities which qualify as states. Embassies originated ‘after the separation of nations (discretis gentibus), the foundation of kingdoms, the partition of dominions, and the establishment of commerce’.Footnote 76 They are, in other words, an institution of the ius gentium that only emerged after individuals had already come to live in gentes, and in response to the circumstances that arose within that specific context. He then proceeds to argue that such a state – in which human beings are dispersed across multiple political bodies which are in turn in relationship with each other – would not have been possible ‘so long as men were in so primitive a state as that depicted by Lucretius’. In this state, ‘they were incapable of respect for the common good, nor did they know enough to adopt customs or laws of a reciprocal nature’. But, ‘later’, ‘those having contiguous territory began to form friendly compacts, and to refrain from doing injury or violence to one another’.Footnote 77 Gentili here seems to be referring to the process that led to the creation of a body of laws specifically between gentes, not to the creation of gentes in the first place, although the ambiguity on this question is suggestive. For it is significant that the margins to this passage include a reference to Book 1 of De inventione. As we have seen, Connan referred to this work to argue that natural reason is the source of the laws that bind individuals into gentes, and, as a result, the ius gentium. In Gentili’s later Regales disputationes tres (1605), he indeed cites De inventione in the same manner. Ius gentium is what holds people together into gentes, he claims, ‘just as reason motivated men then wandering in fields like beasts, living sheltered among the trees, and congregated them into one’.Footnote 78 What Gentili appears to be doing in this De legationibus passage, then, is taking the same framework through which he, and Connan and Doneau before him, understands the creation of gentes and continuing to trace its logic through to the construction of further aspects of the ius gentium that govern the relations specifically between them. Thus, in much the same way that the initial promulgation of laws creating gentes established a shared set of rights and obligations – a consensus iuris – among their respective members, the further unfolding of that process led at a later point to a ‘reciprocity of rights’ (communio iuris) ‘between nations (gentes), commonwealths, and kings’, and thereby entrenching a distinctive and prominent role for them within the greater ius gentium system.Footnote 79

Returning to the DIB, it becomes clear very quickly that war is one of these rights limited to states. It is, he says, a ‘just and public contest of arms’. It is ‘just’ because both its cause and the actions undertaken in it must be ‘just and righteous’. It is ‘public’ (publica) because the rights of war only apply to ‘public’ bodies.Footnote 80 The reason why it is limited to public bodies, he goes on to say, is due to the unique role within the ius gentium system they serve: they are responsible for securing justice for their members. For example, while ‘public’ bodies are not necessarily responsible for the misdeeds of their individual citizens, he claims in Book 1 Chapter 21 of DIB that a situation in which the citizen of one state commits a misdeed against the citizen of another could very well come to implicate both states. The reason for this is that a state is both ‘bound to defend a citizen’ and to ‘hold its citizens to their duty’.Footnote 81 If the state responsible for the offending citizen ‘fails to right the wrong’, then ‘the community binds itself to war’. ‘For since [the state] can hold its citizens to their duty, and indeed is bound to hold them’, he continues, ‘it does wrong if it fails to do so’.Footnote 82

Therefore, a state, which knows because it has been warned, and which ought to prevent the misdeeds of its citizens, and through its jurisdiction can prevent them, will be at fault and guilty of a crime if it does not do so…and we know that war was made upon the Messenians by the Lacedaemonians, for the reason that a murderer of the Lacedaemonians was not surrendered.Footnote 83

The belief that ‘public’ bodies must ensure that their citizens act justly and are treated justly is thus structurally embedded in Gentili’s account of the ius gentium, with the laws of war making it possible for each ‘public’ body to enforce its rights against the other.

With this context in mind, we can now explain a series of perplexing claims Gentili makes about the character of the ius gentium. Near the beginning of DIB, he claims that the ius gentium is ‘based upon [an] association (societas) of humanity’, and that ‘it is precisely for that reason that the law of nations is called by Cicero “civil”’.Footnote 84 This makes the world like ‘one state’, in which ‘all men [are] fellow citizens and fellow townspeople, like a single herd feeding a common pasture’.Footnote 85 In the very same chapter, however, Gentili describes this ‘one state’ with the ius gentium as its law in fundamentally different terms. Whereas he initially spoke of this ‘one state’ as composed of individual human beings, he later claims that the ‘citizens’ of this universal state are not individual human beings, but ‘public’ bodies: ‘the rule which governs a private citizen in his own state ought to govern a public citizen in this public and universal state formed by the world’.Footnote 86 To explain this, one might say that both individuals and ‘public’ citizens are each equal legal subjects of the ius gentium, implying that the laws of the universal state bind both. As we have seen, however, some laws of the ius gentium, above all the law of war, apply only to ‘public citizens’. Perhaps a more plausible explanation for this ambiguity, instead, is that the universal state governed by the ius gentium binds individuals through their membership in particular states, with each individual acquiring their rights and satisfying their obligations under the former through their participation in the latter.

IV

In addition to being the moment when the ius gentium assumed this new form, the end of the sixteenth century is also an important period in the history of Roman law more generally. For it was at this time that a literature emerged, of which Gentili is also a prominent example, that equated the Roman law with natural law itself, in a significant shift from what had been the dominant reading of Roman law in medieval, and even some legal humanist, circles: that the Roman law was the particular law of Rome.Footnote 87 I have already shown how the account of human nature and human sociability which Connan, Doneau, and Gentili had taken from Cicero enabled them to construct a global legal theory based on the texts of Roman law. In conclusion, I would like to gesture towards some evidence that this same social theory served as the basis for more domestically oriented political thought written in a Roman legal idiom.

I would especially like to emphasize one type of argument which we begin to see spreading among jurists at this time: the idea that the state and the family are species of the same genus form of association, alongside other corporate bodies. For example, in the first section of his Politica (1604, 1610, 1614), concerned with the ‘General Elements of Politics’, Johannes Althusius claims that families, corporations, cities, and states (res publicae) are all instances of ‘association’ (consociatio), which is the ‘subject matter of politics’. Althusius’s term consociatio recalls Cicero’s definition of the populus as a societas, and it shares the same fundamental form with a gens-populus: ‘symbiotes pledge themselves each to the other, by explicit or tacit agreement, to mutual communication of whatever is useful and necessary for the harmonious exercise of social life (vitae socialis)’.Footnote 88 Families, corporations, cities, and states are, in other words, groups of individuals involved in the exchange of various goods and services, the terms of which are regulated by a set of principles derived from agreement. This way of life develops naturally with the family, before expanding to the artificial associations of the corporation and state. Althusius’s view is shared by Bodin, who likewise sees families, corporate bodies, and states as species of societas. The family, he says, is a societas naturalis, while corporations and states are societates civiles.Footnote 89

We have seen already that Connan, Doneau, and Gentili saw the creation of autonomous gentes, and eventually the acquisition of rights and obligations for them, to be a direct consequence of the natural unfolding of human sociability, beginning with the individual and moving outwards to families, states, and, eventually, an association of states.Footnote 90 As Connan said with reference to Cicero’s De officiis, the social instinct that led individuals to grow their social network brought them into an expanding network of societates: ‘first to an association (societas) with kin, then to one with extended family, then to friends, later to neighbours, and finally, through commerce, to an association (societas) that encompasses the whole of humanity’.Footnote 91 While the political theory of a Monarchomach such as Althusius has considerably different aims from that of Bodin, the fact that these authors each construct their different arguments from a very similar account of the state and its place among a broader set of natural social forms is highly suggestive. It is a sign that, as Roman law transitioned into being a source of concepts held to be universally applicable, an amenable way of understanding the nature of human sociability came along with it, becoming the foundation upon which both a Romanist account of the global legal order and a Romanist account of the domestic order was built.

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Eero Arum, Signy Gutnick-Allen, Nikolas Hächler, Peter Stacey, Benjamin Straumann, Gio Maria Tessarolo, and Adam Woodhouse, as well as the audiences of two ‘Just City’ workshops in November 2021 and October 2022, for many helpful comments and suggestions. I am especially grateful for the extensive comments offered on earlier versions of this article by Andrew Fitzmaurice, Daniel Lee, Johan Olsthoorn, and the anonymous reviewers.

Funding statement

This work has received funding from the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme (grant agreement No. 864309).

References

1 On this transformation, see Fedele, Dante, ‘Ius Gentium: the metamorphoses of a legal concept’, in Cavanaugh, Edward, ed., Empire and legal thought: ideas and institutions from antiquity to modernity (Leiden, 2020), pp. 213–51CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Starting in the late nineteenth century, historians began to see this moment as the beginning of modern international law. A classic example is Thomas Erskine Holland, An inaugural lecture on Albericus Gentilis, delivered at All Souls College, November 7, 1874 (London, 1874). More recently, however, there has been a movement away from this thesis. See Koskenniemi, Martti, ‘International law and raison d'état: rethinking the prehistory of international law’, in Kingsbury, Benedict and Straumann, Benjamin, eds., The Roman foundations of the law of nations (New York, NY, 2010), pp. 297339CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Vergerio, Claire, War, states, and international order: Alberico Gentili and the foundational myth of the laws of war (Cambridge, 2022)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Recent histories of international law still treat this period as being of significance in the evolution of the global legal order into one defined by statehood, however. See Tuck, Richard, The rights of war and peace: political thought and the international order from Grotius to Kant (Oxford, 1999)Google Scholar; Neff, Stephen C., Justice among nations: a history of international law (Cambridge, MA, 2014)Google Scholar; and Koskenniemi, Martti, To the uttermost parts of the earth: legal imagination and international power, 1300–1870 (Cambridge, 2021)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Domingo, Rafael, The new global law (Cambridge, 2010), pp. 22–4CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Neff, Justice among nations, pp. 139–47; Bhuta, Nehal, ‘State theory, state order, state system – jus gentium and the constitution of public power’, in Stefan Kadelbach, Thomas Kleinlein, and David Roth-Isigkeit, eds., System, order, and international law: the early history of international legal thought from Machiavelli to Hegel (Oxford, 2017), pp. 408–17Google Scholar. On the construction of the idea of the independent sovereign state in the Renaissance and Reformation, see Quentin Skinner, The foundations of modern political thought (2 vols., Cambridge, 1978).

3 Bhuta, ‘State theory, state order, state system’, pp. 413–14. For an example, see Lee, Daniel, The right of sovereignty: Jean Bodin on the sovereign state and the law of nations (Oxford, 2021)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 Major, J. Russell, From Renaissance monarchy to absolute monarch: French kings, nobles and estates (Baltimore, MD, 1994)Google Scholar. The city in question is La Rochelle, which in 1628 negotiated a treaty between itself and England, without at the same time disavowing its allegiance to the French state. On this, see Grewe, Wilhelm G., The epochs of international law, trans. Byers, Michael (New York, NY, 2000), pp. 171–2CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Brett, Annabel, ‘The subject of sovereignty: law, politics and moral reasoning in Hugo Grotius’, Modern Intellectual History, 17 (2019), pp. 619–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Bhuta, Nehal, ‘The state theory of Grotius’, Current Legal Problems, 73 (2020), pp. 127–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For an expression of the same tension in the work of Gentili, see Brett, Annabel, ‘Roman law and Roman ideology in Alberico Gentili’, Huntington Library Quarterly, 83 (2020), pp. 499517CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Daniel Lee has also argued that Jean Bodin, despite recognizing the plurality of political bodies during his lifetime, attributed a pre-eminence to the sovereign state on account of legal reasoning. Lee, The right of sovereignty, pp. 39–40.

6 Stein, Peter, Roman law in European history (Cambridge, 2004), pp. 1213Google Scholar; Fedele, ‘Metamorphoses of a legal concept’, p. 214.

7 Institutions applicable specifically within the context of inter-polity relations, such as the sanctity of ambassadors, began to appear in subsequent centuries. See Digest 50.7.17. Still, most citations to the ius gentium in classical law involve matters of private law, reflecting its continuing character as a body of common institutions, not a legal system that attributes prominence to one type of political institution in particular. See Fedele, ‘Metamorphoses of a legal concept’, pp. 217–19.

8 See Skinner, Foundations of modern political thought, I, pp. 3–22; Black, Antony, Guilds and civil society in European political thought from the twelfth century to the present (Ithaca, NY, 1984), pp. 1921Google Scholar; and Skinner, Quentin, From humanism to Hobbes: studies in rhetoric and politics (Cambridge, 2018), ch. 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar. The work of Joseph Canning has been especially important in this regard. See Canning, Joseph, The political thought of Baldus de Ubaldis (Cambridge, 1987), chs. 1, 3, and 5CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Implications of Canning’s argument have been developed by Lee, Daniel, Popular sovereignty in early modern constitutional thought (Oxford, 2016)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, especially ch. 2; and by Edelstein, Daniel, ‘Rousseau, Bodin, and the medieval corporatist origins of popular sovereignty’, Political Theory, 59 (2022), pp. 142–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 Canning, Political thought of Baldus, pp. 104–6.

10 Lee, Popular sovereignty, p. 217; Edelstein, ‘Rousseau, Bodin, and the medieval corporatist origins’, pp. 151–5.

11 Benjamin Straumann, ‘The Corpus iuris as a source of law between sovereigns in Alberico Gentili’s thought’, in Kingsbury and Straumann, eds., Roman foundations of the law of nations, pp. 103–7; Wagner, Andreas, ‘Francesco de Vitoria and Alberico Gentili on the legal character of the global commonwealth’, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 31 (2011), pp. 565–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Grant, Darragh, ‘Francesco de Vitoria and Alberico Gentili on the juridical status of Native American polities’, Renaissance Quarterly, 72 (2019), pp. 910–52CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Lee, Right of sovereignty, pp. 39–40; Vergerio, War, states, and international order, pp. 49–132.

12 For the weaknesses of the de facto–de iure distinction as a legal doctrine, see Ryan, Magnus, ‘Bartolus of Sassoferrato and free cities. The Alexander Prize lecture’, Transactions of the Royal Historical Society, 10 (2000), pp. 6589CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Canning, Joseph, Ideas of power in the late middle ages, 1296–1417 (Cambridge, 2011), pp. 147–53CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ryan, Magnus, ‘Political thought’, in David Johnston, ed., Cambridge companion to Roman law (Cambridge, 2015), pp. 424–51Google Scholar. For an account of how the issues raised by these overlapping jurisdictions organized Baldus’s writing on the ius gentium, see the major new study Dante Fedele, The medieval foundations of international law: Baldus de Ubaldis (1327–1400), doctrine and practice of the ius gentium (Leiden, 2021).

14 An interesting exception to this is the work of several jurists from Naples and Sicily, beginning in the late thirteenth century. They argued that the emperor had no legitimate claims to sovereignty over the kingdom because the latter was an independent polity whose natural sovereignty under the ius gentium was unlawfully usurped by the Romans. This argument is not elaborated in detail and appears to have been a minority view. More common, instead, was the claim that all jurisdictions, including those which had become self-governing, were ultimately creatures of Rome, and for this reason de iure dependent on it. On the Neapolitan jurists, see Joseph Canning, ‘Law, sovereignty and corporation theory, 1300–1450’, in J. H. Burns, ed., Cambridge history of medieval political thought, c. 350–c. 1450 (Cambridge, 1988), pp. 464–9; and Ryan, ‘Political thought’, pp. 436–7. For the argument that cities and kingdoms are ‘genealogical and derivative’ and ‘splinters of the empire’, see Magnus Ryan, ‘Historicity and universality in Roman law before 1600’, in John Robertson, ed., Time, history, and political thought (Cambridge, 2023), pp. 61–2.

15 For an example of ius gentium arguments shaping English policy on the Dutch revolt, see Gajda, Alexandra, ‘Debating war and peace in late Elizabethan England’, Historical Journal, 52 (2009), pp. 866–8Google Scholar. For its role in the interactions between Europeans and indigenous peoples, see Fitzmaurice, Andrew, Humanism and America: an intellectual history of English colonisation, 1500–1625 (Cambridge, 2003), p. 143CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Fitzmaurice, Andrew, Sovereignty, property, and empire, 1500–2000 (Cambridge, 2014), ch. 2CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Grant, ‘Francesco de Vitoria and Alberico Gentili’.

16 Stein, Roman law in European history, pp. 76–82; Gordley, James, The jurists: a critical history (Oxford, 2013), ch. 4CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Kelley, Donald R., Foundations of modern historical scholarship: language, law, and history in the French Renaissance (New York, NY, 1970)Google Scholar; Stein, Roman law in European history, pp. 76–82; Gordley, The jurists, ch. 4.

18 Stein, Roman law in European history, pp. 79–82; Gordley, The jurists, pp. 118–27.

19 Jean-Louis Thireau in ‘Ciceron et le droit naturel au XVIème siècle’, Revue d’histoire des Facultés de droit et de la science juridique, 4 (1987), pp. 55–85; Gaëlle Demelemestre, ‘La systematization du droit et la théorie du ius gentium comme droit du genre humain chez François Connan’, Revue historique de droit français et étranger, 94 (2016), pp. 413–38.

20 Annabel Brett, Changes of state: nature and the limits of the city in early modern natural law (Princeton, NJ, 2010), ch. 3; Susan Longfield Karr, ‘“The law of nations is common to all mankind”: ius gentium in humanist jurisprudence’, in Anthony Carty and Janne Nijman, eds., Morality and responsibility of rulers: European and Chinese origins of a rule of law as justice for world order (Oxford, 2018), pp. 73–92.

21 ‘Iure naturali videntur usi primi homines rudes illi quidem & agrestes, caeterum expertes cupiditatis & aemulationis, qui nullum adhuc cognatorum aut vicinorum praesidium sibi quaesiverant, sed in montibus & sylvis dissipati’, Franciscus Connanus, Commentaria iuris civilis libri X (Paris, 1553), I, fo. 11r [1.4].

22 ‘Ius itaque naturale proprium est hominis solitarii, vitam agentis in agro cum uxore & liberis’, ibid., I, fo. 13v [1.5].

23 ‘Sed cum ad hominum societates & coetus suapte natura ferretur, paulatim exiit foras, cognationibus primum, tum affinitatibus, deinde amicitiis, postea vicinitatibus, & tandem commerciorum usu totum genus hominum societate complexus est’, ibid., I, fo. 13v [1.5]. See also Cicero, De officiis 1.53.

24 ‘rerum commerciis utilitates sibi quaesiverunt ad vitam commodius degendam’, Connanus, Commentaria iuris civilis, I, fos. 13v–14r [1.5].

25 ‘Ex quibus vicinitatem quandam sibi constituerunt’, ibid., I, fo. 14r [1.5].

26 Ibid., I, fo. 14r [1.5].

27 ‘Est enim gens hominum multitudo iisdem moribus utentium’, ibid., I, fo. 14r [1.5].

28 ‘In quo necesse fuit iustitam colere, fidem servare contractuum, neminem dicto factove laedere’, ibid., I, fo. 14r [1.5].

29 ‘cum extraneis & sibi ignotis hominibus eadem probitate agere, qua soliti erant cum uxore & liberis’, ibid., I, fo. 14r [1.5].

30 ‘ratio praescribit faciendum aut non faciendum’, ibid., I, fo. 14r [1.5].

31 ‘Est ergo ius gentium quo homines utuntur non tanquam homines, id est rationis participes animantes, sed tanquam gentes’, ibid., I, fo. 14r [1.5].

32 Cicero, De inventione 1.1–2.

33 Among medieval authors, see Nederman, Cary J., ‘The union of wisdom and eloquence before the Renaissance: the Ciceronian orator in medieval thought’, Journal of Medieval History, 18 (1992), pp. 7595CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Nederman, Cary J., ‘Nature, sin and the origins of society: the Ciceronian Tradition in medieval political thought’, Journal of the History of Ideas, 49 (1995), pp. 326CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For humanists, see Fitzmaurice, Humanism and America, pp. 102–11.

34 Andrea Alciato, ‘Oratio in laudem iuris civilis principio studii habita cum Avenione profiteretur’, in Opera omnia (Basel, 1582), IV, pp. 1025–6.

35 ‘qui dissipatos in agris homines conciliavit inter se, & coniunxit…Hic homines ex feris & immanibus mites reddidit & mansuetos, ut iam animi iudicio potius quam viribus corporis omnia administrarent’, Connanus, Commentaria iuris civilis, I, fo. 14v [1.5].

36 ‘beneficia ultro citroque darent & acciperent, nihil detraherent de alieno sui emolumenti gratia, sed eandem putarent uniuscuiusque, quae & universorum, utilitatem’, ibid., I, fo. 14v [1.5].

37 Cicero, On the commonwealth and on the laws, trans. James E. G. Zetzel (Cambridge, 2017), p. 18.

38 ‘in populi formam aliquam sociati’, Connanus, Commentaria iuris civilis, I, fo. 14r [1.5].

39 Hugo Donellus, Commentariorum de iure civili (Florence, 1840), I, p. 37 [1.6].

40 ‘in initiis huius mundi tempus’, ibid., I, p. 51 [1.7].

41 ‘Cum enim duo homines primo conditi essent…singuli homines de communi sumere possent, quantum vellent, sine alterius iniuria, aut offensione’, ibid., I, p. 51 [1.7].

42 ‘At postquam terra multitudine hominum frequentari coepit: recta ratio usu et experientia confirmata docuit, aut diu stare non posse genus humanum: aut in iis, quae colerentur, suum cuique constituendum, quod quisque privatim sibi coleret, quoque alii sine voluntate domini pervenire non liceret’, ibid., I, p. 51 [1.7].

43 ‘Illinic enim inopia rerum ad vitam necessariarum: hinc dissidia, et turbae’, ibid., I, p. 52 [1.7].

44 ‘Quapropter post illam hominum frequentiam fuit hoc primum rectae rationis, et iudicii opus, et lex inter homines, ut esset aliquid suum cuiusque, quod (ut dixi) ut suo labore quisque coleret, ac procuraret: ita caveret sibi, ne in id alius quisquam posset invadere sine iniuria’, ibid., I, p. 52 [1.7].

45 ‘Nam cum, dominiis distinctis, coepisset alius habere, quo ego indigerem: eo autem frui, invito domino, non possem…induci eas commutations, quae commercia, et contractus appellamus’, ibid., I, p. 52 [1.7].

46 ‘Hinc ergo contractus recepti, emptio, venditio, locatio, conductio, societas, mandatum, depositum, commodatum, et similes. Ex his obligationes’, ibid., I, p. 52 [1.7].

47 Translation from Alan Watson, The Digest of Justinian (4 vols., Philadelphia, PA, 1985).

48 Bartolus of Sassoferrato on Digest 1.1.5, in Opera quae extant omnia (Venice, 1590), I, fos. 7v–8v; Baldus de Ubaldis on Digest 1.1.5, in In primam digesti veteris partem commentaria (Venice, 1577), I, fos. 11r–12r.

49 ‘sed quia Deus…fecit mentes diversas hominibus, caeperunt homines adversari et bellare invicem…Ex bello aut ventum est ad divisiones gentium’, commentary on Digest 1.1.5, in Baldus, In primam digesti, I, fo. 11r.

50 Fedele, ‘Metamorphoses of a legal concept, pp. 234–5.

51 ‘aureum seculum’, Connanus, Commentaria iuris civilis, I, fo. 14r [1.5].

52 ‘Inde nec ita multo post successit peior aetas, quam vocaverunt ferream…Et ut fit luxu quibus antea satis erat ne qua re egerent, amplificandis rebus suis studverunt, tum ne cui parerent: deinde etiam ut imperarent, & haberent rerum omnium in summa impunitate licentiam’, ibid., I, fo. 15v [1.5].

53 ‘Hinc regnandi libidines, hinc factiones, insidiae, seditiones, rapinae, bella, finis aequi & iusti. Sic tandem deflexit de via naturae, paulatimque eo deducta est humana ambitio, nihil ut haberetur praeclarius, quam divitiis & potentia excellere’, ibid., I, fo. 16r [1.5].

54 ‘aequitatis constitutione summi cum infimis pari iure retinerentur’, ibid., I, fo. 16r [1.5]. In De officiis 2.41, Cicero says ‘qui cum prohiberet iniuria tenuiores, aequitate constituenda summos cum infimis pari iure retinebat’.

55 ‘sunt reges creati a populis…& qui inter ipsos essent inopes, ut ne opprimerentur ab iis, qui maiores opes habebant’, Connanus, Commentaria iuris civilis, I, fo. 16r [1.5].

56 ‘qui pacem publicam tueri, cives in officio continere, maleficia pro imperio coercere, civibus iura reddere, ad munera capessenda cogere invitos possint’, Donellus, Commentariorum de iure civili, I, p. 230 [2.6].

57 ‘in plurium autem administratione propter varia hominum iudicia, et naturalem ad dissentiendum proclivitatem, facile eveniret, ut distraherentur animi in diversas sententias’, ibid., I, p. 53 [1.7].

58 ‘ut ne ab hostibus externis universi’, Connanus, Commentaria iuris civilis, I, fo. 16r [1.5].

59 ‘Ad urbes tuendas regna condita’, Donellus, Commentariorum de iure civili, I, p. 53 [1.7].

60 ‘urbes constitutae…homines et validiores futuri erant ad vim, atque iniuriam hostium propulsandam’, ibid., I, p. 53 [1.7].

61 ‘Bellorum etiam inde initia’, Connanus, Commentaria iuris civilis, I, fo. 16r [1.5].

62 ‘Civitatibus et regnis conditis, bella introducta’, Donellus, Commentariorum de iure civili, I, p. 53 [1.7].

63 ‘ut vis publica vi publica, arma armis repellerentur’, Connanus, Commentaria iuris civilis, I, fo. 16r [1.5].

64 ‘Civitatibus et regnis conditis, bella introducta, nempe ad illa ipsa tuenda’, Donellus, Commentariorum de iure civili, I, p. 53 [1.7].

65 ‘cum bellis utamur aut ad propulsandos hostes aut res ab hostibus juste repetendas’, ibid., I, p. 53 [1.7].

66 Connanus, Commentaria iuris civilis, I, fo. 16rv [1.5]; Donellus, Commentariorum de iure civili, I, pp. 53–4 [1.7].

67 ‘Nam bella & regna in primis annumerat’, Connanus, Commentaria iuris civilis, I, fo. 16v [1.5].

68 ‘tamen ex nostrum opinione debverant esse postrema’, ibid., I, fo. 16v [1.5].

69 These arguments are made in Giovanni Minnucci, Alberico Gentili tra mos italicus e mos gallicus: l’inedito commentario Ad legem Juliam de adulteriis (Bologna, 2002), and Minnucci, Giovanni, Alberico Gentili iuris interpres della prima età moderna (Bologna, 2011)Google Scholar. See also Alain Wijffels, ‘Antiqui et recentiores: Alberico Gentili – beyond Mos italicus and legal humanism’, in Paul J. du Plessis and John W. Cairns, eds., Reassessing legal humanism and its claims: petere fontes? (Edinburgh, 2015), pp. 11–40.

70 Straumann, ‘Law between sovereigns’, offers evidence that Gentili equates Roman law with natural law.

71 ‘di ricercare i principii che devono sovraintendere alla relazioni umana’, Minnucci, Gentili iuris interpres, p. 177.

72 An example of Gentili’s immense debt to Cicero is his De armis Romanis (1599), a dialogue on the model of the Carneadan debate contained in Book 3 of Cicero’s De re publica and preserved for the early modern period in Lactantius’s Institutes. See Benedict Kingsbury and Benjamin Straumann, ‘Introduction: the Roman foundations of the law of nations’, in Kingsbury and Straumann, eds., Roman foundations of the law of nations, pp. 1–21.

73 Gentili, Alberico, De iure belli libri tres, ed. Rolfe, John (Oxford, 1933), p. 8Google Scholar.

74 Ibid., p. 8.

75 Ibid., p. 10.

76 Alberico Gentili, De legationibus, trans. Gordon J. Laing (New York, NY, 1924), p. 51.

77 Ibid., p. 51.

78 ‘Quod vero iuris gentium sit unio, quis non intelligit, qui novit, ut in agris homines passim bestiarum more vagantes, & in tectis silvestribus abditos ratio compulit, & congregavit in unum’, Alberico Gentili, Regales disputationes tres (London, 1605), pp. 42–3. Note here how ‘ratio’ ‘motivated and congregated’ the dispersed men. In Cicero’s original, and in some of its Renaissance iterations, it was a wise man or orator who ‘motivated and congregated’ through an appeal to their reason.

79 Gentili, De legationibus, p. 51.

80 Gentili, De iure belli, p. 12.

81 Ibid., pp. 99–100.

82 Ibid., p. 100.

83 Ibid., pp. 100–1.

84 Ibid., p. 67.

85 Ibid., p. 67.

86 Ibid., p. 68.

87 Straumann, ‘Law between sovereigns’; Straumann, Benjamin, Roman law in the state of nature: the classical foundations of Hugo Grotius’s natural law (Cambridge, 2015)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ryan, ‘Historicity and universality’.

88 Althusius, Johannes, Politica, ed. Carney, Frederick S. (Carmel, CA, 1994), p. 17Google Scholar.

89 Lee, Right of sovereignty, ch. 1; Becker, Anna, Gendering the Renaissance commonwealth (Cambridge, 2019), ch. 3CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

90 For some of the implications following from this connection between the family and the state, see Becker, Gendering the Renaissance commonwealth.

91 See n. 23.