Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T07:43:23.320Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The costs of recognition: global politics, religion, and the colonial history of South Asia

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 June 2023

Maria Birnbaum*
Affiliation:
Universität Bern, Bern, Switzerland
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In this article I consider religion in international political scholarship and suggest a study of its epistemological politics and conceptual history. I argue that scholarship which strives to ‘engage’ or ‘recognize’ religion in global politics remain ignorant of the costs involved. Building on this argument, I ask if the troubles with recognizing religion reflect more basic qualities of recognition scholarship. Following the work by Jacques Rancière, Patchen Markell, Elizabeth Povinelli, and Jens Bartelson I argue that recognition has two faces and that along with its frequently acknowledged empowering aspect, it also comes with costs. In order to assess the costs of recognition I propose a study of its conditions of possibility, that is, a study of the ways in which the subjects of recognition become recognizable as such. In the final section of the paper, I apply this to the example of religion in global politics and the formation of the Muslim subject in the lead-up to the partition of British India and the founding of Pakistan.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

Throughout the last three decades religion has increasingly become part of a public vocabulary to make sense of international conflict dynamics while also describing the contours of cultural, epistemic, and ontological diversity.Footnote 1 Governments, international organizations, and universities have invested vast resources in assessing ‘religious conflicts’ and in engaging with ‘religious’ institutions and actors, their ideas, claims and visions of the world. While the place and role of religion in global politics continue to be disputed, international policymakers and scholars alike agree that one can no longer address world affairs without it: religion demands recognition.Footnote 2 However, as decades of scholarship in religious studies has shown, religion – just like sovereignty, democracy, or freedom – is an unstable concept encompassing a shifting order, range and scope of social relations, actors, institutions, ideas, and practices. If the object to be engaged with – religion – is continuously shifting, then what exactly should scholars engage with, recognize, or include in our studies, policies, and predictions?

In this paper I argue that there are costs involved in recognizing religion in global politics that are neither sufficiently understood nor appropriately evaluated. These stem, among other things, from the fact that recognition processes presuppose the prior identification of entities and subjects ready to be recognized.Footnote 3 Acts of recognition build upon an assumed ‘fact’ of recognizability and so, in order to become recognized, a subject must be or become recognizable to a regime of knowledge. Arguments that we should recognize religion in global politics ignore, therefore, the conceptual, epistemological, and historiographical politics of recognition, instead conceiving of religion as intelligible prior to recognition as something that can be included or excluded, governed, managed, and engaged with.Footnote 4

Building on this argument, I ask if the troubles with recognizing religion in the study of International Relations (IR) reflect more basic qualities of recognition. After an introduction to the arguments for the recognition of religion in global politics, I study recent critical debates about recognition in relation to individuals and groups, minorities, nations, empires, and states. Building on the work of Jens Bartelson, Patchen Markell, Elizabeth Povinelli, James Tully, and Jacques Rancière, I argue that recognition has two faces and that along with the frequently acknowledged empowering and emancipatory aspect of recognition, the conditions for its possibility are also bound up with costs. One of these conditions is that arguments for recognition both presuppose and reproduce a differentiated social logic; that is to say, a logic which assumes an identifiable and differentiated subject. This subject acts as a benchmark for understanding whether or not a process of recognition has been successful. It depends on a prior establishment of the criteria of recognizability that one can either successfully meet or fail to meet. By studying the processes by which a subject becomes recognizable we can start understanding the costs that accompany recognition.

I end the paper by giving an indication of what such a study might look like. I examine the government of British India and the subsequent establishment of the Islamic Republic of Pakistan. I show how the quest for statehood, the role of minorities, political representation, and international border-making both shaped, and were shaped by the concepts, agents and identities associated with ‘religion’ that broke through the threshold of political recognition to establish themselves as taken-for-granted political entities on the global stage. I illustrate how claims for the recognition of religion are intimately connected to the colonial epistemological politics through which such processes played out and which costs they carried.

Religion in global politics: narratives of exclusion and arguments for recognition

In this section I look at arguments for the recognition of religion in global politics as illustrated through narratives of its exclusion and arguments for its rehabilitation. I point out that these arguments for recognition have costs as they both depend on and reproduce an intelligible subject of religion as already available for recognition. This is significant because scholars and policy makers alike use the conceptual apparatus of religion to make sense of the dynamics of global political order, including violent conflicts and peace building, state building processes, minority protection claims and violations, and the development of democratic institutions and aid programs. I end the section by suggesting that this is not exclusively a problem of religion in IR but is inherent in the grammar of recognition in a broader sense.

During the early 2000s interest in religion and politics grew exponentially in academia, as well as in policy circles and public discourse. With it a debate moved center stage regarding the secular foundations of the liberal political (international) order.Footnote 5 The debate outlined and critiqued various secularist assumptions about political order and legitimate authority which explicitly saw religion on the outside, often as defining the limits of the political and the public.Footnote 6 According to those critiques, religion was not as easily separated from politics as had been assumed and liberal secularity, as we know it today, was argued to be the result of a particular settlement in a particular historical period.Footnote 7 The settlement was, in this sense, neither universal nor neutral, and the fact that its idea had been near to universalized via the institution of the liberal state did not make it a necessary condition of liberal democracy. According to this position, the secularism(s) underlying the Western liberal political order had a history, a genealogy, and was to be studied in detail rather than used as a measurement for democratic development.Footnote 8

This secularism debate continued into the following decade and cleared space for a new form of engagement with religion, both in scholarship and in policy circles.Footnote 9 I focus here on the former. In an attempt to re-read international political history and theory after the critique of secularism, Daniel Philpott saw religion as constitutive of the current Westphalian international order of sovereign states, since this order would never have emerged, were it not for the way in which the Reformation and Protestant ideas of political authority shaped the states' interests in sovereign statehood.Footnote 10 ‘No Reformation, no Westphalia’ is the short version of the argument.Footnote 11 Scott Thomas continued to argue that assumptions about a secular Westphalian international system that had relegated religious conflict to the inner life of states skewed the understanding of the ‘resurgence of religion’ in the Global South, regions where religion had never lost its political and social salience.Footnote 12 In this sense when scholars retained Westphalia as a symbol for secularized IR the global resurgence of religion came to look like an internationalization of a private matter, threatening the international order.Footnote 13 Following Thomas in an effort to de-securitize religion, William Cavanaugh argued against what he called the ‘secular myth of religious violence’.Footnote 14 He pointed to the ways in which the emerging early modern state established a discourse of religious violence and the perceived necessity to remove religion from the public in order to shift loyalties from the religiously constructed identity of a community to the new territorial claim to power and authority of the state. Elizabeth Shakman Hurd argued in Politics of Secularism in International Relations that secularism cannot be written off as a fixed and final achievement of European modernity, showing rather that secularism needs to be considered a socially constructed and historically contingent form of religious governance which has consequences for domestic and global politics. Once secularism is seen as a mode of political governance rather than a stable and neutral solution to the problem of religion in public, it is possible to start looking at the evolution of different forms of secularism and their multi-faceted trajectories, histories, and political consequences.Footnote 15

Following the deconstruction of the secular ontology of IR, other scholars from a variety of disciplinary backgrounds saw religion as potentially embodying the move to a cultural and epistemic diversification in the field. In undoing the knowledge-power regime of secularism IR scholars expected to broaden the range of actors, arguments, ideas, institutions, and forms of knowledge, opening up to ‘otherwise neglected forms of being, becoming and knowing’.Footnote 16 Expanding the ‘hermeneutic register’ to reach localized cultural markers or vernacularsFootnote 17 or establish an ‘open hermeneutic margin’ for non-Western actors to widen the resources of negotiation,Footnote 18 to pursue an ‘ethos of engagement’ with a plurality of previously untapped moral resources,Footnote 19 or alternative ontologiesFootnote 20 was considered a value in and of itself. The value of diversity and plurality was particularly emphasized in relation to the decolonization or provincialization of an otherwise Eurocentric framework of global politics. ‘Taking views of other worlds seriously’, Erin Wilson writes, ‘requires that we do not attempt to relate different ontologies to one another through language and concepts that belong to only one of them’.Footnote 21 Following the postsecular account of Jürgen Habermas, Mariano Barbato argued, that the semantic figures of religious communities might offer ‘resources for fueling deliberation processes with notions of arguing beyond narrow concepts of self-interest’ broadening the range of ethical possibilities that the instrumental reason of a secular system of thought would be unable to respond to.Footnote 22

This movement toward exploring previously excluded aspects of international life, however, not only identified new perspectives, and increased the range of relevant actors, institutions, or epistemologies but was also productive in defining who and what would count as belonging to the category of religion and thereby as worthy of recognition. In various ways but in a similar manner both the narratives of exclusion tracing what had been lost due to the ‘secularist’ marginalization of religion as well as restorative arguments and policies regarding what needed to be ‘brought back in’ relied on particular notions of what counts as ‘religious’ and what does not.Footnote 23 In these cases ‘religion’ referred to difference – cultural, ontological, or epistemic – which may not be fixed in substance but known when seen.Footnote 24 Even scholarship that pursued a more relational approach tended to treat religious identities, ideas, norms, and practices as independently constituted, putting pre-given actors, structures, and interest at the center of their analyses focusing instead on what Jonathan Agensky has called their ‘interdependence and strategic accommodation’.Footnote 25

The productive power of exclusion narratives and recognition arguments

If global politics are to be governed through the category of religion – aiming to solve ‘religious’ conflicts, engage with ‘religious’ actors, and protect ‘religious’ freedom – this will incentivize association accordingly.Footnote 26 As Hurd puts it in relation to the politics of religious freedom, ‘(g)overning religion as a right funnels individuals into discrete faith communities, empowers those communities and their spokepersons, and marginalizes other modes of solidarity’.Footnote 27 The risk of emphasizing the ‘role of religion’, then, is that boundaries between groups are made more salient and that this creates new forms of social friction defined by religious difference.Footnote 28 Responding to and governing of religious difference further ‘puts pressure on nonestablished, unorthodox, [or] nonconforming’ forms of religious life to yield to the recognizable versions thereof or risk being rendered invisible.Footnote 29 The burden of normalization is thereby thrown onto those who find themselves outside the realms of the intelligible, compelled to shape themselves in a manner that does not render them imperceptible to the various available forms of recognition and empowerment. Anthropologist Elizabeth Povinelli writes in this vein regarding the recognition of the indigenous Australian population, noting that they are ‘called on to perform an authentic difference’ and to ‘transport [their] ancient prenational meanings and practices to the present in whatever language and moral framework prevails at the time of enunciation’.Footnote 30 In order to be recognized, in other words, one has to be recognizable and if this is not the case, one needs to become so. To accept a process of recognition, as political theorist Sara Ahmed puts it, is to ‘value those who can “be heard and act” under its name’.Footnote 31 Subjects in global politics, therefore, do not only exist by virtue of being recognized, but do so in a prior sense, by having become recognizable.Footnote 32 International organizations, governmental foreign policies, local administration, and international law have shaped a new global politics of religion that defines the criteria of what it means to be recognizably religious and have, as Hurd shows, created new categories of actors in world politics.Footnote 33 Recognition as an actor, then, depends on a prior establishment of the criteria of recognizability that one can either successfully meet or fail to attain.Footnote 34 In this way both the new and never-conceived become ‘tied to that which is already cognized’.Footnote 35

In a paper published at the height of international scholarship's engagement with religion, Robert M. Bosco described this move to ‘capture the “global resurgence” of religion’ as a persistent Orientalist discourse inhabiting the ability to ‘seamlessly appropriate new phenomena into received representations’ while continuously overlooking the politics of the definition of religion.Footnote 36 The assumption that it is possible to engage with ‘religions’ in a neutral manner, however, masks the epistemic politics interwoven into the concept and its history.Footnote 37 While agreeing with Bosco that the integration of ‘religion’ into IR scholarship has been defined by the appropriation of pre-determined conceptions of what ‘religion’ is supposed to be and do, I argue that the engagement with ‘religion’ did not simply reproduce the existing conceptions of the term and the political orders and hierarchies it served but reflects a more basic problem with recognition. The point that I want to make is that these are not random examples of the productive and reifying power entailed in engaging religion in global politics and beyond. Rather, I see the problems of recognizing religion as reflecting a more general issue with the grammar of recognition, namely that recognition presupposes the prior identification of entities and subjects ready to be recognized.Footnote 38 The act of recognition, then, depends on an established ‘fact’ of recognizability. It assumes a subject that can be known and differentiated from that which it is not prior to the moment of recognition. In order to understand how religion became available as an object of knowledge that was possible to recognize and the marker of differentiation of subjects claiming recognition, we must know more about how it became recognizable in different circumstances as distinct and identifiable, and somehow different from politics, law, or culture. Once we have a better grasp on how religion became recognizable, we will be able to assess what costs accompanied those processes and how these were distributed. As I will show in detail below, the costs of recognizing religion in IR are on the one hand side epistemic in the assumption that there is an identifiable and differentiable subject that can be extended recognition to, that is, religious minority, religious argument, institution, or organization, a religious doctrine, idea, norms, or identity. Thereby, those outside this legibility scheme are either forced to claw their way back into intelligibility by the means at their disposal or risk remain unrecognizable. The costs are also context dependent and particular to each case, referring, for example to the marginalization of unrecognizable groups, the reification of social and legal structures and institutions, the heightening of conflict fault lines, and so on. I will return to the question of the costs of recognition in the next section and continue to illustrate examples of specific costs in the last section examining state-building efforts in South Asia.

Two faces of recognition

In his book Bound by Recognition, Patchen Markell illustrates the double nature of recognition by drawing on an analysis of the emancipation of European Jews in the late 18th and early 19th centuries. The emancipation had aspired for inclusion into the ‘civic’ nation, which meant access to citizenship rights, education, and the removal of discriminatory laws. However, the assimilation of Jews into the broader structures of European political communities did not simply imply that Jewishness was deemed irrelevant to political membership. Emancipation was, instead, both an effort to remove restrictions on ‘Jewish life’ but also, ‘an active effort to reshape Jewish … identity’.Footnote 39 While emancipation had provided recognition and empowerment to the Jewish population, it had also conditioned that empowerment by means of integration into a certain form of structure that encompassed political institutions, an educational system, and legal norms. In Enlightenment in the Colony Aamir Mufti continues that, as a recognized minority European Jews became vulnerable in novel ways. They became identifiable, quantifiable and, in a word, governable, as the contours of their communities were made more easily known and detectable.Footnote 40

As Markell puts it, by making the ‘distribution of resources and the institutionalization of rights dependent upon one's recognizability as the bearer of an identity’, the politics of recognition ‘risks subjecting the very people whose agency it strived to enhance to powerful forces of normalization’.Footnote 41 Processes of recognition may give shape to the existing political order but they are also making it governable, helping to ‘create the world that [they] purport … to oversee’.Footnote 42 The conditions of empowerment are thereby also the conditions of control.

Another example is the case of British Indian Muslims, to whom I will return below. They gained political influence as colonial subjects of the British Empire to the degree to which they were accountable and enumerable through, among other instruments, the colonial census and the governmental logics that structured it. Recognizing religious difference and the subjectivities tied to it empowered those who were identifiable within the logics of the census. The recognition of religious and cultural difference was, in this way, productive of the subjects that it named while also binding them to existing systems and structures of power – extending rights, legitimacy, and authority at the same time as implicating those subjects in its hierarchical structure.Footnote 43 A deeper understanding of these two sides of recognition – empowering and subjecting – allows us to account for the costs that accompany it. Focusing on recognition or misrecognition as a ‘fact of rightly or wrongly cognizing and respecting an already-existing identity’ distracts from the fact that this form of acknowledgment partakes in the constitution and government of the subjects in place.Footnote 44

In the next section I look at recognition theories in IR, arguing that several approaches incorporate and reflect this problematic assumption regarding the nature of the subject of recognition. I contrast the accounts of recognition with an alternative which echoes the shift from a struggle for recognition to a struggle over recognition gestured to by James Tully in his later work. This means that instead of arguing for the recognition of certain subjects – individuals, communities, or states – my focus is on the struggle over recognition's conditions of possibility. I then proceed to illustrate what that looks like in practice linking it back to the question of religion and the claims for recognition in the cases of British India and Pakistan.

Actualizing the potential: the productive and performative power of international recognition

During the 1990s, questions of recognition increasingly came into focus in political and international political discourse in the wake of a flourishing discussion of multiculturalism and identity politics at international and domestic levels.Footnote 45 In international political scholarship, this took the form of analyses of identity-based conflicts, used to explain why actors sometimes seemed to act against their material interests in pursuit of an identity-based goal.Footnote 46 In contrast to prevailing realist and liberalist approaches in IR, the focus on recognition emphasized the importance of identities and subjectivities alongside the more traditional quest for power or wealth and modes of coordination and cooperation beyond the state.Footnote 47 Recognition was considered, however, as not simply one goal among others, but a basic need.Footnote 48 Unlike other basic needs, such as shelter or food, that must be met to ensure the survival of the individual or collective subjects, the need for recognition was considered different – its very fulfillment served to constitute the individual or collective as a particular kind of actor. Recognition mattered in IR, because it described the process through which actors came to exist as actors within the international system and to take on a particular role and place within that system.Footnote 49 This constitutive theory added the productive, relational, and social power of recognition to declaratory or cognitive theories which relied much more heavily on an objective set of criteria necessary to obtain the sought for recognition. In this sense, recognition was not only cognitive of existing actors, but elevated into actorhood for those international entities that were recognized by others.Footnote 50

Recognition was considered in these accounts not only as part of the process constituting the (collective) identities of international actors but also as an intrinsic part of the dynamics of international politics and conflicts, and as a motor of change.Footnote 51 By struggling for recognition, actors were understood as challenging prevailing political structures to establish a new order that better met their needs. This changing order would be continuously challenged by others to include an ever-growing community of recognized actors, perpetually developing toward ever-increasing inclusion. One example is IR scholar Christian Reus-Smit's book Individual Rights and the Making of the International System, in which he draws on Axel Honneth's Hegelian study of struggles for recognition and argues that the relational striving for, and realization of, individual rights has repeatedly driven large-scale change in the international system.Footnote 52 Reus-Smit's argument is one example of a longer tradition in IR of tracing international dynamics back to the realization of a potential, imagined reality, or an as yet unrealized subjectivity that is made realizable through struggles for recognition.Footnote 53 Shannon Brincat also draws on Honneth's story of the subject's journey toward a progressively successful ‘self-actualization’, reshaping it as a quest for the cultivation of cosmopolitan social relations and an ethical life which ‘increases possibilities for social freedom’.Footnote 54 A decade earlier Alexander Wendt had told a similar, teleological story about self-realization and the historical evolution of the international state system from one of differentiated entities into a single overarching Self in the form of the World State.Footnote 55 Transcending the particular and developing into a universal entity, as Wendt envisioned, however, assumes a starting point of clearly distinguishable, bounded subjects – states in this case – that insist on being recognized in their particularity or difference. In other words, his teleology depends upon a preexisting logic of differentiation. The central point here is that for these authors there is, and needs to be, a difference that can be recognized and, subsequently, overcome for the process to move forward. There needs to be a recognizable difference between ‘Self’ and ‘Other’ before one can insist on the recognition thereof as a step toward reconciliation as a higher level ‘We’. Without such difference there would be no intersubjectivity but rather a form of radical fusion.Footnote 56

While the teleological aspect of the approach adopted by Wendt and others can be viewed as problematic in its own right, that is not my focus here. The important point for my argument, rather, is that such approaches require and presuppose a preexisting, latent subject, without which the struggle for recognition would not be possible. They require a differentiated logic, a differentiated social ontology, in order for the mechanisms of recognition to gain a foothold. With respect to scholarship positing recognition as a source of change and a means through which to actualize a potential self, the question remains: from where does the potential subject emerge on behalf of which recognition can be claimed (or denied)? How does that which is potential differentiate itself from that which it is not? How does one traverse the threshold of recognition? There is a crucial step missing in the recognition-based arguments considered above – namely an explanation for how the subject on behalf of which recognition is claimed, granted, or denied can be assumed.

As we saw above, in much of the scholarship on recognition in international politics, the game of recognition – demanding, extending, or receiving it – is conceived of as part of the constant political activity through which agency is acquired and identities formed. However, this is achieved via a vision of ‘identity as the always already settled criterion of proper intersubjective relations’.Footnote 57 An identity is asserted and assumed that grounds and guides its carrier's actions and, here I agree with Jens Bartelson, such theories of recognition ‘assume that the entities to be … recognized already are given, be they national communities or cultures’.Footnote 58 That is, in order to extend recognition to the multiple varieties of different states, communities, or cultures that demand and deserve it, they need to be distinguishable and ready to be recognized. To put it succinctly, they need to be recognizable. As Bartelson warns us, it is tempting, therefore, to argue that such subjects need to have been politically recognized – making them legible and intelligible – before they can be morally recognized as part of a larger diverse order. In Bartelson's words, it is ‘tempting to argue that moral recognition actually depends on prior political recognition of these entities, constituting them as bounded containers of distinct cultures’.Footnote 59

While theories of international political recognition view acts of mutual political recognition as constitutive – of, for example, the status of statehood, as we saw above in Honneth's reference to the ‘potential’ becoming ‘actual’ – they nonetheless also assume an actor that can enter into these games of recognition. That is, political recognition presumes the ‘existence of pre-constituted actors as a baseline for [its] explanatory endeavour’.Footnote 60 Or, as Oliver Kessler and Benjamin Herboth put it, to ‘frame politics in terms of recognition is to presuppose a world a priori divided into a multiplicity of distinct and separated collectivities’.Footnote 61

The benchmark of misrecognition and the assumption of the subject

Recognition also can fail, according to the scholars that follow its dynamics in the global realm.Footnote 62 The need for recognition is universal and so are the consequences of it failing.Footnote 63 However, despite their attempt to avoid essentializing the identities that were recognized, these scholars remained dependent on identity as a benchmark by which to judge the various available recognitive structures.Footnote 64 It is on the basis of identity that the failure of recognition is measured; misrecognition is only intelligible if recognition itself is a matter of the cognition of an identity that is in some sense independent of the uncertainties of human interaction. Because, if identities were not independent in this way ‘they could not serve as reliable benchmarks by which to judge the adequacy of particular recognitive act of structures’.Footnote 65 For Taylor, Honneth, Brincat, Reus-Smit, Wendt, and the large majority of political and international political scholarship, misrecognition can be read as the failure of recognition.Footnote 66 The conventional idea of misrecognition as a failure to adequately recognize others is further reflected in Axel Honneth's argument, considered above, about how recognition indicates the transition from a ‘potential’ to an ‘actual’ identity.Footnote 67 The pre-existence of a ‘potential’ identity in this case is necessary as a criterion for judging the adequacy of the act of recognition, which would, in turn, lead into an ‘actualized’ identity.Footnote 68 That is, in the interdependency of the development of a ‘Self’ vis-á-vis an ‘Other’, this constructive theory of recognition still depends on the existence of a ‘potential’ entity, identity, or subjectivity. Absent the potential subject, there are no grounds on which to know if recognition has succeeded or failed. Misrecognition assumes an existing identity as a benchmark for failed recognition. When Honneth argues that the ‘path for civilizing international relations primarily lies in sustained efforts at conveying respect and esteem for the collective identities of other countries’,Footnote 69 he is referring to the actualization of the potential collective identities of these other countries. Or, as he argued, against Patchen Markell, a few years earlier, ‘the struggle for recognition represents a struggle for the social articulation of pre-existent knowledge’.Footnote 70 The ‘pre-existing knowledge’ of a ‘potential’ subject carries the assumption of a pre-differentiated entity awaiting recognition, a subject that is harmed should recognition fail.

I have argued that attempts to analyze international dynamics through the lens of recognition assume a differentiated and recognizable subject. However, one might suggest that IR's constructive arguments of recognition – building on Hegel and Honneth's reading of him – do not assume a sovereign subject at all, to the contrary. However, as I will show below, my point is not to say that IR-scholars assume a sovereign subject but that they assume that sovereignty in knowledge about the subject is possible and necessary in order to assess whether or not recognition had succeeded or failed. They must assume a recognizable subject in order to proceed the analysis of the dynamics of recognition struggles. That does not mean that the grammar of recognition is stuck with fixed or reified subjectivities, but rather that it is dependent on an assumption that sovereignty in knowledge is possible. If this were not to be the case, again, there would be no way of knowing whether the suggested recognition of a known subject – substantive or enacted – would have been successful or not.

Patchen Markell and James Tully: non-sovereign knowledge and non-essential recognition

The pursuit of recognition in IR scholarship functions in a framework where knowable and differentiable subjects are the conditions of possibility for intersubjective relations. But through its aspiration and desire for epistemological sovereignty the politics of recognition misses the constitutive vulnerability of subjectivity.Footnote 71 Hegelian-inspired scholarship on recognition in IR often assumes the possibility of knowing who we and others are; it assumes sovereignty in knowledge of identity, and the recognition of this knowledge by others.Footnote 72 It assumes that this identity will guide and ground our actions and, moreover, that knowing the identity brings knowledge of the actions. Thus, if we were to know who an actor is, it would be possible to know what the actor would do. What this perspective elides is that identity does not simply ground action but is constituted by it, including the performative claims to recognition themselves. Further, since human action can never rid itself of its non-sovereign character, neither can the identity and agency that is formed by such action ever be fully sovereign. There is a limit to what we can expect our knowledge of ourselves and of others to do for us.

IR scholarship on recognition often remains blind to the possibility of the ‘non-sovereign’ character of human action and knowledge.Footnote 73 Since action will always be partly unpredictable the knowledge and subjectivities that emerge from it will remain non-sovereign. In this sense, the subject is not lacking sovereignty due to its dependency on an ‘Other’ but because it is performatively enacted and action will inevitably remain partly unpredictable.Footnote 74 Acknowledging the contingency and chance of human action means acknowledging the vulnerability and practical limits ‘imposed upon us by the openness and unpredictability of the future’.Footnote 75 Politics, Markell writes, ‘is in part a response to the experience of vulnerability’ to the fact that our identities are shaped in part through the unpredictable responses of other people. This is ‘what makes being recognized by others seem so acutely important in the first place’.Footnote 76 It is in reaction to the troubling unpredictability of the responses of others that the politics of recognition demands ‘that others recognize us as who we already really are’ be it an individual, a community, or a state.Footnote 77 It is because subjectivities are vulnerable and instable that the recognition of them appears critical. Recognition depends upon the impossible assumption of sovereignty in knowledge over that which already is.Footnote 78 The desire for sovereignty performs the function of making the ever-ongoing project of identity seem to be a stable and a steady ground for action.

I began this article by claiming that recognizing religion in global politics has costs. This follows from the fact that recognition has costs, both ontological – in the misrepresentation of the non-sovereign nature of human knowledge and subjectivity – and epistemological – by obscuring those subjects and forms of knowledge that fall outside of the currently recognizable, a point I will return to below. One might contend that international political scholars arguing for the importance of recognition do not assume this kind of sovereignty in a subject at all. In fact, a point might be made saying that the very grounds for political claims for recognition is that a subject is not (yet) recognized; if there were a recognized subject, there would be nothing to struggle for. As we saw above, recognition, in such arguments, is the force of change both for agents and epistemic systems.Footnote 79 My argument is, however, not about whether a new political order is realized as a result of subjects' struggles for recognition. My argument is that even absent its recognition, the subject is assumed to be there – the process of recognition assumes a subject that can be known and differentiated from that which it is not prior to the process of recognition. Such an approach begs the question: if claims or struggles for recognition are fueled by the fact that the subject is as yet unrealized, on behalf of what or whom are these claims made? How did they become recognizable in the first place?

To return to the empirical example introduced above of Jews in 18th and 19th century Europe; if recognition realized and constituted a European Jewish political subject – through the emancipation of Jewish minorities into citizens – how could a political subject be successfully recognized which did not yet exist in this manner?Footnote 80 The obvious answer to that question seems to be the performative enactment of Jewish subjectivities by individuals and groups claiming rights in the name of a Jewish community, the Honnethian ‘potential’ subject. Similarly, British Indian Muslims were vibrant communities prior to the allocation of rights and forms of representation by the British colonial regime. Does the argument of the costs of recognition break down once the subjectivities are not assumed as reified identities, but rather conceptualized as contingent and changing? In other words, what about non-essentialist recognition? In proceeding to the second part of my argument which leads us to the building blocks for thinking differently about recognition in international scholarship, I turn to Canadian political theorist James Tully. By identifying a shift in his work from what I conceptualize as an analysis of struggles for recognition to struggles over recognition I show how I see the conversation on recognition in IR moving forward.

From a struggle for recognition to a struggle over recognition

James Tully has increasingly featured in IR scholarship throughout the last decade, mainly in reference to his agonistic approach to social and political theory but also, prior to that, as a proponent for a ‘post-imperial cultural diversity’ defined by mutual recognition.Footnote 81 I will not be able to treat Tully's work with the detail it deserves.Footnote 82 What I will do, however, is to use a shift in Tully's scholarship to show how an approach to recognition which does not depend on reified identities but instead emphasizes non-essential subjectivities remain subject to the costs of recognition I outlined above. What Tully helps me to do, then, is to move from a framework focusing on the struggles for recognition – where non-essentialist recognition still assumes a differentiable subject tied to the existing categories of legibility where costs are entailed – to a framework focusing on the struggles over recognition, that is, the struggles in defining the conditions of possibility for recognition and its epistemic frameworks of legibility. First, two words on Tully's initial position.

Published in 1995 back-to-back with Charles Taylor's work on The Politics of Recognition, James Tully's book Strange Multiplicity takes a different approach than its fellow Canadian counterpart. Here, the politics of recognition is described as an ongoing process which values not the end-state of recognized subjects, but the shared political activity of subjects that are both the authors of and constituted by the engagement.Footnote 83 However, when reframing the question of recognition as dealing with performatively enacted subjects, as Tully does in his examples from North American indigenous peoples, he is still aiming at a more than just a form of successful recognition of subjectivities as they are.Footnote 84 While Tully remains sensitive to the risks of domination and effects of various power hierarchies on the course of negotiations, he also slips back into a cognitive understanding of recognition, that is, a position where the construction of the subject is performative but where that performativity is still limited to the available categories of intelligibility.Footnote 85 Non-essentialist recognition is not by definition free from costs, and Tully's earlier account echoes the dependency on an intelligible subject – even if it is ‘multiple, overlapping and contested’Footnote 86 – and the reproductive power entailed therein. If recognition is tied to the currently recognizable – reproducing the epistemic structures that enable it – what are the prospects for change?

In later work Tully enacts a useful shift in perspective from struggles for recognition, as in the case of peoples or nations, to the struggle over recognition. This implies a new focus on challenges to the norms underpinning recognition practices as well as the pathways to arriving at a place of legibility, of becoming recognizable. In his two-volume Public Philosophy in a New Key he picks up where he left off in Strange Multiplicity but highlights the contingent nature of the norms underpinning the processes, practices, and claims for recognition within and between nations and states. This contingency and the struggle to define the norms, subjectivities, and epistemic frameworks is, however, not a problem. Rather, the struggles over intersubjective norms of mutual recognition are necessary not only for the development of just social and political relations but also for the prevailing legitimacy of social and political order at large.Footnote 87 It is, for Tully, therefore not enough for an existing legislation, set of minority rights, or international covenants to recognize minorities or nations. Instead, he points out, these social, political, and legal institutions need to contain the conditions of possibility for change in the norms underpinning that legislation, the minority rights, or covenants.Footnote 88 If we take this agonistic idea of the centrality of the struggle over recognition with us, emphasizing the importance of the possibility for change – both in the norms, the subjectivities, and in the epistemic framework that holds them – how is that different from the approach to recognition in IR outlined above? For this, I turn to Jacques Rancière and Axel Honneth.

Axel Honneth, Jacques Rancière, and the possibility of epistemic change

Throughout the paper I have argued that the costs of recognition can be found, among other things, in the ontological misrepresentation of the non-sovereign nature of human knowledge and subjectivity. I have also gestured toward a second argument to which I will now turn. Here, I show that while recognition depends on a recognizable subject the framework of knowledge within which the subject has become recognizable is also due to be reproduced through the recognition of that recognizable subject. In other words, I am suggesting the contrary to IR scholars who see recognition as a motor of change and emancipation; that recognition has a reifying and potentially repressive element.Footnote 89

In order to forward this argument, I turn to a notable debate between Axel Honneth, whose reading of Hegel informs a large part, if not most, work on recognition in IR, and the French philosopher Jacques Rancière. The book Recognition or Disagreement was published in 2016 and captured a conversation between Honneth and Rancière at the Institute for Social Research in Frankfurt am Main a few years earlier. In Honneth's description of the struggle for recognition, he presents previously excluded subjects as challenging the prevailing social and political order, including the knowledge system that underpins it. Such challenges undermine and change the epistemic range of whom can be included in a particular social and political order, broaden its range of intelligibility – that is, they extend the range of that or who is available for recognition.Footnote 90 The inclusion of a new type of nation, for example, changes the meaning of nationhood itself. Rancière's critique holds that the inclusion of new subjects will not change the range of the intelligible in any way, since it is only possible to include into the new order those who are recognizable as subjects to begin with.Footnote 91 The established framework of knowledge, what Rancière calls the ‘common sense’, will not change through the inclusion of that or those who were previously excluded from it. A change in the framework of knowledge, Rancière argues, does not come through the acknowledgment of the previously excluded but, rather, through the enactment of a different reality altogether.Footnote 92

Epistemological change – what Rancière calls a change in the ‘distribution of the sensible’ – stands in stark contrast to theories of the transformative power of recognition, which take place within a certain normative and cognitive framework. It is epistemological change that holds the possibility for transforming the workings of such normative and cognitive frameworks,Footnote 93 going ‘beyond given systems’ and proposing a ‘new system of norms’.Footnote 94 A change to the distribution of the sensible is not a broadening to include that or those who were previously excluded, nor is it the self-realization of a group becoming ‘aware’ of itself, finding its voice or imposing its weight on society.Footnote 95 It is not the acknowledgment of the grievances or suffering of those on the wrong side of a hierarchical order that will change the range of the recognizable; the wrong by which politics occurs is not ‘some flaw calling for reparation’.Footnote 96 A change in the foundations of knowledge comes, rather, through the interruption of the common sense by those and that which were invisible to it. This is what Rancière calls the introduction of an ‘incommensurable at the heart of the distribution of speaking bodies’.Footnote 97

The range of what or who can count as a subject does not change through the inclusion of those who are considered rightly worthy of a place, but through the enactment of a different reality all together – acting as if one were a subject.Footnote 98 Such an action is an intervention into the conditions of knowledge of what a subject is and who is eligible to become one. A redistribution of the sensible means a change in the framework of the intelligible – it makes ‘what was unseen visible’.Footnote 99 For Rancière, the struggle for recognition in Honneth's terms aims to change the range of the recognizable by convincing or pressuring the arbiters of the boundaries of that knowledge to expand them. By contrast, a change in recognizability, in Rancière's understanding, is about claimed space regardless of the arbiters or boundaries – it is the change of terms altogether.Footnote 100

As political theorist Hanna Pitkin noted in her analysis of Niccolò Machiavelli, in order to communicate an alternative, one ‘wants not to convey new information to (one's audience), but rather to change the terms, the conceptual framework through which they presently organize their information’.Footnote 101 Referring this back to the discussion of recognition the question is not ‘how does a subject become recognized?’, but ‘how does it become recognizable?’. In the previous case of the Jewish or Muslim subjects referenced below, how did those subjects become intelligible as distinct from their surroundings, as something available for recognition? How was this subjectivity stabilized and made coherent? What were the consequences as to what or who could be included in the categories of ‘Muslim’ or ‘Jewish’ as those categories became linked to the minority, the nation, and the state?

Through Rancière's critique we see that Honneth's struggle for and achievement of recognition is trapped within its own referential bubble. Requiring the assumption of a subject or, in Hegelian terms, a consciousness for the relational process of recognition between a Self and an Other, Honneth is unable to account for forms of subjectivity other than those that are expected, those that are intelligible as subjects from the start. Recognition might change the number of players in the recognition game, but it will not be able to change the game itself. Rather, recognition will reproduce the common sense, the established social and political order.

Turning back to the question of religion and the recognition of religious difference, a process that follow's Honneth's logic will extend acknowledgment and empowerment to that or those who are already recognizable as religious, thereby confirming powerful actors' claims to represent religion, religious groups, and religious truths. Such a process marginalizes those who are outside of the spectrum of the recognizably religious, writing out of the picture an entire range of possibilities while those who remain unrecognized struggle to achieve a place on the public register of recognition. The requirement of an already-recognizable subject strengthens the voices of conventional and established religion, and further hardens the boundary between those included in that category and those who are not.Footnote 102 It is, therefore, not merely that the recognitive structures of social and political orders assume and reproduce a knowable and differentiated subject, they are also risk reifying the structures and hierarchies of a given prevailing order.

If it is true then, as Axel Honneth put it, that ‘the struggle for recognition represents a struggle for the social articulation of pre-existent knowledge’ – that is, an articulation of that which is, already, known – the question emerges as to how that knowledge comes about? Returning to the example of the Jewish and Muslim subjects, how does one know what or who is Jewish or Muslim, and who is not? What are the processes that make the contours of a subject identifiable and how is it differentiated from other subjects? How does it change regarding that which is possible to recognize, and what are the social and historical forces affecting that change? What are the consequences? And who pays – who carries the costs? By examining in detail the conditions of possibility of recognition we gain a better grasp of the costs that come with it. In the next section I illuminate the conditions of possibility for the recognition of ‘religion’, and the recognition of ‘Muslim’ during the establishment of the independent state of Pakistan. The line between religion and politics is, as Hussein Agrama points out, ‘historically connected with modern state sovereignty and its constitutive indeterminacies’.Footnote 103 Studying the birth of a state claimed and recognized, in part, along the lines of ‘religious difference’ provides us with important resources for understanding the conditions and the costs of that constitutive relationship between religion, state sovereignty, and the system in which they are embedded.

Recognizing religion and postcolonial independence: India and Pakistan

In this final section I illustrate how ‘religion’ and a ‘Muslim’ nation came to form part of a transnational vocabulary describing minorities, borders, and conflicts see also: Devji Reference Devji2013; Dubnov Reference Dubnov, Dubnov and Robson2019; Kattan Reference Kattan2008. As I have shown elsewhere, the British, Indian, and Pakistani state-building projects were grounded in a shared assumption that a political and epistemic mastery of ‘religion’ was essential to the working of political and legal governance.Footnote 104 My approach to religion here builds on and develops recent scholarship in political theory, anthropology, and sociology.Footnote 105 Religion is considered a ‘moving target’ shaped by, while simultaneously informing, broader social formations, nationalist agendas, and political structures.Footnote 106 Here, I study the road to recognizability of a Muslim subject and ask: how did the conceptual apparatus of religion develop to describe minorities, borders, and conflicts? And how was that apparatus put to use in negotiating claims for independence and various visions of statehood? How did it structure the analysis of conflicts and expectations about how those conflicts would develop? And how did it feature in struggles about authority, legitimacy, and political order? What were the consequences and costs of employing the vocabulary of religion and how were they distributed?

In August of 1947, India and Pakistan became sovereign states, independent from both the British Empire and from each other. The partition of South Asia served as a resource for Middle Eastern state builders not only with respect to seeing partition as a solution to the problems of increasingly intense conflicts, the administration of refugees and absentee property, but also in terms of the terminology used to make sense of it.Footnote 107 An example is ‘religion’ and a ‘Muslim subject’. The partition of Bengal in 1905 set the precedent. In that case, the colonial government had aimed to splinter and weaken political resistance to British power by dividing the province into an eastern part, where Muslims formed a majority, and a western part, where non-Bengali Hindus dominated numerically. As Penny Sinanoglou has argued, from the vantage point of later events in Palestine, the ‘partition of Bengal is significant because it manifested the concept of dividing territory and political representation along religious lines’.Footnote 108

Although the partition of Bengal was reversed in 1911 in response to large-scale protests, the principle of representation by religion had become an integral part of Indian politics and law. The efforts to govern Bengal also further laid the groundwork for the British understanding of Muslim governance and the ‘manner in which Islam might be handled by the British Empire’ elsewhere.Footnote 109 The party of the All-India Muslim League was founded a year after the Bengali partition, while in 1909 the Indian Councils Act (also known as the Morley–Minto reforms) created exclusively Muslim electorates in provincial and central legislative councils. The provisions, defined as protections for religious minorities, were developed and embedded in the Indian political system through both the Montagu–Chelmsford reforms of 1919 and the new constitutional framework developed in the 1935 Government of India Act.Footnote 110 The rationale behind these ‘marked’ electorates was to increase Muslim representation in the system of elective local government.Footnote 111 At the same time, however, they also established a link between religion and political representation, power, and patronage.

Connecting political power to one's recognizability as a religious minority cuts both ways; as Iza Hussin notes, ‘[a]t the level of legal and political discourse, the ability to make claims on behalf of a Muslim interest required an acceptance of the space within which Islam had been assigned, thereby often undermining the logic and power of the claim itself’.Footnote 112 In The Politics of Islamic Law, Hussin shows how the realm of Islamic law became intelligible as a separate category of law in Muslim societies under British imperial rule. Colonial encounters both subjugated Islamic law – detaching it from public politics and restricting it to the private realm of family law – but also, through its reification, codification, and textualization, gave Muslims (in courts and in larger society) concrete and legible references for litigation, appeal, and reform. This made Islamic law a powerful tool in articulating alternatives to and challenges to the authority of the colonial state.Footnote 113 By compartmentalizing religion into various domains, and ceding those domains to the local elite, ‘(t)he colonial state in fact helped constitute the private domain that Indian nationalists later cherished as free from colonial interference’.Footnote 114

The processes of minoritization such as giving a ‘Muslim minority’ exclusive electorates brought both access to power and subjugation to it. It granted access to power by making the members of a population recognizable as political actors. Yet, the condition of that access to power was subjugation or subjection to the particular form of knowledge that grants access – in this example becoming legible to the apparatus of the state. Returning to the terminology of the discussion above, recognition, in this sense, had a double face, making the conditions of empowerment simultaneously the conditions of control.

My point in drawing a parallel between the recognition of Islamic law and minority recognition is to draw attention to the two faces of recognition. Recognition brings with it access to power but also brings costs. The British colonial state separated Islamic law, and the Muslim subjectivities connected to it, from public political power. At the same time, the unification, codification, and reification of Islamic law opened up space for anti-colonial actors to draw on those highly specified codes and rules in order to articulate an alternative to British rule. Similarly, the recognition of British Indian Muslims as a minority created a unified actor with political access. At the same time, it limited that access to those who were recognizably Muslim in the eyes of the colonial state and the technologies of categorization it used to visualize its subjects (such as the census or the law).Footnote 115 The form of power expressed through the regimes of recognition thus both established the subject and governed it at the same time.Footnote 116

The same is true of the conditions of resistance to colonial rule. In order to be recognizable to the state as opposing a certain policy on Islamic law or identity, it was necessary to identify as an ‘Indian Muslim’ – an act which ‘brought [the category] into being as a political and public reality’.Footnote 117 That being the case, alternatives to the colonial state still depended on them remaining legible to it; those who resisted the state still had to align themselves along the unified categories of race and religion in order to be recognizable to and recognized by the state. Even the act of resistance against local and colonial elites helped, therefore, to reinforce the idea of a unified ‘Muslim’ subject.Footnote 118 At the same time, however, the second role played by the bounded category of religion was the creation of this unified Muslim subject, whose codification in law and representation in politics would become a node in the anti-colonial resistance and claims to independence that would follow. The imperial recognition of the Indian Muslim was, then, Janus-faced, working both as a condition for government and power and as a resource for challenging and opposing them.

Conclusion

The last decade has seen critical accounts add to the debate about recognition in global politics.Footnote 119 Jens Bartelson has argued that ‘international relations are mute when it comes to the conditions of epistemic recognition, implying that the classificatory grounds for recognizing an entity as an actor of a certain kind already are given or at least sufficiently unproblematic’.Footnote 120 Janis Grzybowski has added that recognition is reproductive of the ontology of the state and the state system, and ignores ‘the prior question of what states actually are and how they can be identified as such’.Footnote 121 Ayse Zarakol, meanwhile, has joined Charlotte Epstein, Ole Jacob Sending, and Thomas Lindemann in reversing the recognition ontology to one of misrecognition, where global political subjects strive for, but can never achieve, sovereign agency.Footnote 122 Such perspectives hint at the futility of the strive and struggle for recognition in global politics, suggesting that its effect is perpetuating order and hierarchies, rather than challenging them.

In this paper, I have gone beyond the critique of recognition to argue for a study of its costs. These are not the result of ‘recognition gone wrong’, or its ‘instrumentalization’ in more intricate power games but can only be understood through an examination of recognition's conditions of possibility. I have argued that recognition depends on and reproduces a knowable and differentiable subject, without which it would be impossible to evaluate the success or failure of recognition in the first place. By understanding how this subject became recognizable, it becomes possible to examine the costs bound up with it. That means studying the vulnerability and governability bound up with recognition – making visible the forgetting of certain histories, the abandonment of certain practices, the silencing of certain voices, and the privileging of certain forms or regimes of difference over others. Regarding the question of religion, it is by studying the path to recognizability, that is, the global epistemological politics of religion that we can begin to understand the costs of its recognition.

Over the last 20 years an impressive body scholarship has taken shape in the fields of anthropology, history, sociology, law, and political theory, tracking these productive processes and their implications in detail. Winnifred Sullivan, Nadia Marzouki, Iza Hussin, Benjamin Schonthal, Noah Salomon, Saba Mahmood, Elizabeth Shakman Hurd, Ben Crosson, Amélie Barras, Joseph Blankholm, Justin Richland, Meadhbh McIvor, Brannon Ingram, Teren Sevea, and many others have analyzed the dynamics of the co-constitutive relationship between modern national and international politics and religion illustrating in detail the ways in which the productive and epistemic power of political and legal orders shape modern political, religious, and legal subjects.Footnote 123 This scholarship on religion and politics shares the critical theoretical, conceptual, and methodological groundwork of scholarship in International Political Sociology, Historical IR, Postcolonial Global History and Decolonial Theory, and any variety of Feminist approaches which have remained reluctant to engage with scholarship on religion in IR since, as we saw above, a majority of this scholarship remains locked into the epistemological trap of rehabilitating religion and its accompanying hierarchies. IR does not need to recognize religion. Rather, international scholarship needs to engage with the costs of recognition by studying the histories and global epistemological politics of religion that produces recognizable religious and political subjects.

Acknowledgments

The author would like to thank Elizabeth Shakman Hurd, Iza Hussin, Nadia Marzouki, Christian Reus-Smit, Jens Bartelson, Andrew Phillips, Patrick Herron, Olivier Roy, Janis Grzybowski, Jaakko Heiskanen, Stefano Guzzini, Ayse Zarakol, Minda Holm, Ole Jacob Sending, Benjamin de Carvalho, Amélie Barras, Mariano Barbato, Elif Kalaycioglu, Erik Ringmar, Arie Dubnov, Faisal Devji, Daniel Levine, Martino Mona, Inanna Hamati-Ataya, and two anonymous reviewers. The author would also like to acknowledge the Centre for Research in the Arts, Social Sciences and Humanities (CRASSH) and the Department of Politics and International Studies (POLIS) at Cambridge University for fellowships enabling her to finalize the article.

Conflict of interest

The author declares none.

Footnotes

3 Grzybowski Reference Grzybowski2019, 253.

9 Religion in international security (Fox and Sandler Reference Fox and Sandler2005; Mavelli Reference Mavelli2012, Reference Mavelli2013; Sandal and James Reference Sandal and James2011; Sheikh Reference Sheikh2012; Hassner Reference Hassner2016, Reference Hassner2003); politics of religious freedom (Hurd Reference Hurd2015; Sullivan et al. Reference Sullivan, Hurd, Mahmood and Danchin2015; Philpott Reference Philpott2019) in IR theory and history (Thomas Reference Thomas2005; Snyder Reference Snyder2011; Shani and Behera Reference Shani and Behera2022); international ethics (Lynch Reference Lynch2020); in international organizations (Haynes Reference Haynes2014; Årsheim Reference Årsheim2018) religion and the nation state (Cesari Reference Cesari2021); postsecular global politics (Barbato Reference Barbato2010; Mavelli and Petito Reference Mavelli and Petito2012; Wilson Reference Wilson2014).

11 Philpott Reference Philpott2000, 206.

12 Thomas Reference Thomas2010, 507.

16 Mavelli and Petito Reference Mavelli2012, 942; Pasha Reference Pasha2012.

21 Wilson Reference Wilson2017, 1088.

22 Barbato Reference Barbato2010: 552; see also Lynch Reference Lynch2020.

23 For Philpott this was religious institutions and ideas, ‘feverish belief’, ‘ultimate concern’, or primordial loyalties, for Thomas liberal mythologies of religion are replaced with communitarian ones, and religion is conceived as ‘a type of social tradition’ as ‘religious traditions shape identity, thought, and experience’. This way religious traditions are reified as culturally a priori makers of ‘situated selves’, for Lynch religious ethics.

26 See debate between Hurd and Philpott on religious freedom. While Philpott contends the importance of protecting religious freedom globally, Hurd argues that the politics of religious freedom is accompanied with the risk of reifying religious subjectivities, religious differences, and conflicts that accompany them (Hurd Reference Hurd2015; Philpott Reference Philpott2019).

27 Hurd Reference Hurd2015, 48.

28 See also Connolly Reference Connolly2005; Hurd Reference Hurd2015, 41.

29 Hurd Reference Hurd2015, 112.

30 Povinelli Reference Povinelli2002, 6, my italics.

31 Ahmed Reference Ahmed2012, 29.

32 Butler Reference Butler2021 (1997), 5.

33 See here Sending Reference Sending2017 and Bourdieu's conception of authority as the ability to set the evaluative criteria structuring the granting or withholding of recognition.

34 Hurd Reference Hurd2015, 113.

36 Bosco Reference Bosco2009, 99–100.

37 Hurd Reference Hurd2015, 81.

38 Grzybowski Reference Grzybowski2019, 253.

39 Markell Reference Markell2003, 131. Recognition, here, refers to epistemic recognition. That means that recognition is not only claimed or extended to minorities or states but also concerns the concepts that define them. Recognition, in the sense that I use it is about the possibility and ability to recognize, not just the extension of rights to a minority.

41 Markell Reference Markell2003, 175.

42 Hurd Reference Hurd2015, 111.

43 See also Bartelson Reference Bartelson2013, Reference Bartelson2016, as well as Grzybowski Reference Grzybowski2019.

44 Markell Reference Markell2003, 59–60. For a critique of recognition in relation to indigenous rights in Canada and beyond, see Coulthard Reference Coulthard2014.

48 Taylor Reference Taylor1994; Honneth Reference Honneth2008. See Erman Reference Erman2013 for the difference between declaratory and constitutive recognition; Wendt Reference Wendt2003 and further Strömbom (Reference Strömbom2014) for the difference between ‘thick’ and ‘thin’ recognition; Geis et al. for gradual and fluid, formalized and informal forms of recognition; Bartelson Reference Bartelson2013 for the differentiation between moral, political, and legal recognition; Ricoeur for three forms: identifying an object; self-recognition; of others, sociability a predisposition of the human; Hayden and Schick Reference Hayden and Schick2016 for the difference between existential, Marxist, critical theoretical, feminist, poststructural, postcolonial, agonistic, and psychoanalytic; Ikäheimo and Laitinen Reference Ikäheimo and Laitinen2011.

49 Greenhill Reference Greenhill2008, 344. For a discussion about the possibilities and limits of scaling up from the individual to the collective, see Honneth Reference Honneth, Lindemann and Ringmar2012, 28; Geis et al. Reference Geis, Fehl, Daase and Kolliarakis2015, 14; Brincat Reference Brincat2017; Zarakol, Reference Zarakol2018, 851; Lindemann and Ringmar Reference Lindemann and Ringmar2012, 7; for a historical account of the extension from domestic recognition within the state to the international level during the 19th century see Zarakol Reference Zarakol2018.

50 Bartelson Reference Bartelson2013. For a critique of lack of acknowledgment of material inequality, the emphasis of identitarian criteria and the risk of reification of identities, see Fraser Reference Fraser1995; Fraser and Honneth Reference Fraser and Honneth2003.

54 Brincat Reference Brincat2017, 13.

55 Wendt Reference Wendt2003. While Wendt's teleological vision of the international future is quite specific to his work, the understanding of recognition as positive empowerment by which the international system expanded and evolved, possibly to a more peaceful state, runs through international scholarship on recognition more broadly (Ringmar Reference Ringmar1996, 188; Lindemann 2014; Honneth Reference Honneth, Lindemann and Ringmar2012; Onuf Reference Onuf2013, for other examples of teleology, see Fukuyama Reference Fukuyama1992).

56 For a critique on Honneth's reading of Hegel and the bifurcation between recognition and reification see Butler Reference Honneth2008, 106.

57 Markell Reference Markell2003, 59f.

58 Bartelson Reference Bartelson2013, 119, my italics.

59 Footnote Ibid., my italics.

60 Bartelson Reference Bartelson2013, 113, 114; Grzybowski Reference Grzybowski2019.

61 Kessler and Herborth Reference Kessler and Herborth2013, 157.

63 In global politics, failed recognition or non-recognition has further been considered a root cause of violent conflict as actors struggle to claim what they consider rightfully theirs, be it positions of status, membership, or name (Ringmar Reference Ringmar1996; Ringmar and Lindemann Reference Lindemann and Ringmar2012; Wolf Reference Wolf2014; Adler-Nissen and Zarakol 2020).

64 Lindeman and Ringmar 2012; Wolf Reference Wolf2014; Geis et al. Reference Geis, Fehl, Daase and Kolliarakis2015.

65 Markell Reference Markell2003, 59.

71 Markell Reference Markell2003, 5.

74 Markell Reference Markell2003, 4–10. In searching for ways to understand the ‘non-sovereign’ character of human action, knowledge, and life, Markell builds on the work by Hannah Arendt to give us a different reading of Hegel's Phenomenology of the Spirit. Against the interpretation that Hegel assumes recognition to be a precondition of genuine agency and the action following from this agency as authentic, Markell argues action outruns recognition, leaving it inevitably lagging (Markell, 94). Rather than simply originating from identity, action and practices are constitutive thereof. Due to the inevitably unpredictable nature of action, these performatively enacted forms of subjectivity as well as the knowledge that constitute them must remain non-sovereign (Markell, 13).

75 Markell Reference Markell2003, 4f, 63, 89ff.

76 Markell Reference Markell2003, 14; see also Tully Reference Tully2008, 168.

77 Footnote Ibid., 14. Italics in original.

78 See Epstein et al. Reference Epstein, Lindemann and Sending2018 and the special issue on Misrecognition in World Politics for an account of the futility of the desire for recognition and sovereign agency in IR.

80 See Lapidot Reference Lapidot2020 for an argument against the claim that anti-Semitism created a unified Jewish subject.

84 Tully Reference Tully1995, 24.

85 Recognition is ‘a performative whose conditions of felicity include that it seems only to be a constative’ (Markell Reference Markell2000, 503).

86 Tully Reference Tully2008, 181.

87 Tully Reference Tully2008, Chs. 7–9.

88 Tully Reference Tully2008, Chs. 4–6 and Reference Tully2008, Chs. 1, 4, 5.

90 Honneth 1995.

91 Honneth and Rancière Reference Honneth and Rancière2016.

94 Honneth Reference Honneth2014, 104, 112.

95 Footnote Ibid., 40. Rancière makes a clear distinction between a struggle for the recognition of a sociologically or culturally defined identity and a demand to be recognized in one's capacity of ‘equal intelligence’, meaning one's equal ability to speak, recognized as a being with a logos. See Honneth and Rancière Reference Honneth and Rancière2016, 38f.

96 Grievances, as Frantz Fanon pointed out, do not need to accompany a hierarchical system of power – such as colonialism or slavery – since the particular forms of recognition working within them will become internalized by the subordinated and not necessarily questioned. Change within a system thus does not need come through recognizing the rights of the suffering, since neither suffering nor rights are necessarily available options in an oppressive political system (Fanon Reference Fanon2008 (1952)).

97 Rancière Reference Rancière1999, 19.

98 Footnote Ibid., Ch. 2.

99 Footnote Ibid., 37–38, 55.

100 Rancière Reference Rancière1999, 16.

101 Pitkin, Reference Pitkin1984, 291.

103 Agrama Reference Agrama2010, 503.

104 See also Birnbaum Reference Birnbaum2022; Cohn Reference Cohn1996; Salomon Reference Salomon2016, 62. For Cohn colonialism was an ontological and epistemological project, its ways of knowing were its ways of governing.

106 Hurd Reference Hurd2015; on Hurd's analysis of religion as a ‘moving target’, see Birnbaum Reference Birnbaum2017.

109 Hussin Reference Hussin2016, 47, 199.

110 Sinanoglou Reference Sinanoglou2019, 159.

112 Hussin Reference Hussin2016, 210.

113 Footnote Ibid., 33, 147.

114 Footnote Ibid., 137. See also: Birnbaum Reference Birnbaum2022.

115 Footnote Ibid., 66.

117 Hussin Reference Hussin2016, 221; for a similar study of the role of jurisdiction and religion in Palestine and Israel, see Shindler Reference Shindler2008, 78ff.

118 Hussin Reference Hussin2016, 30f.

120 Bartelson Reference Bartelson2013, 109.

121 Grzybowski Reference Grzybowski2019, 245.

References

Abeysekara, Ananda. 2002. Colors of the Robe: Religion, Identity, and Difference. Studies in Comparative Religion. Columbia, S.C: University of South Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Adcock, C. S. 2010. “Sacred Cows and Secular History: Cow Protection Debates in Colonial North India.Comparative Studies of South Asia, Africa and the Middle East 30 (2): 297311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adler-Nissen, Rebecca, and Zarakol, Ayşe. 2021. “Struggles for Recognition: The Liberal International Order and the Merger of Its Discontents.” International Organization 75 (2): 611–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Agensky, Jonathan C. 2017. “Recognizing Religion: Politics, History, and the ‘Long 19th Century.’” European Journal of International Relations 23 (4): 729–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Agné, Hans, Bartelson, Jens, Erman, Eva, Lindemann, Thomas, Herborth, Benjamin, Kessler, Oliver, Chwaszcza, Christine, Fabry, Mikulas, and Krasner, Stephen D.. 2013. “Symposium_‘The Politics of International Recognition.’International Theory 5 (1): 94107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Agrama, Hussein Ali. 2010. “Secularism, Sovereignty, Indeterminacy: Is Egypt a Secular or a Religious State?Comparative Studies in Society and History 52 (3): 495523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ahmed, Ishtiaq. 1999. “The 1947 Partition of Punjab_Arguments Put Forth before the Punjab Boundary Commission by the Parties Involved.” In Region and Partition: Bengal, Punjab and the Partition of the Subcontinent, edited by Talbot, Ian and Singh, Gurharpal, 116–67. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ahmed, Sara. 2012. On Being Included: Racism and Diversity in Institutional Life. Durham, London: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Årsheim, Helge. 2018. Making Religion and Human Rights at the United Nations. Religion and Society. Boston: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Asad, Talal. 1993. Genealogies of Religion: Discipline and Reasons of Power in Christianity and Islam. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asad, Talal. 2003. Formations of the Secular: Christianity, Islam, Modernity. Cultural Memory in the Present. Stanford, Calif: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Aydin, Cemil. 2017. The Idea of the Muslim World: A Global Intellectual History. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bailes, Alyson J. K. 2015. “Legal Precision or Fuzzy Feelings? A Diplomatic Comment on Recognition Studies.” In Recognition in International Relations, edited by Daase, Christopher, Fehl, Caroline, Geis, Anna and Kolliarakis, Georgios, 251–64. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barbato, Mariano. 2010. “Conceptions of the Self for Post-Secular Emancipation: Towards a Pilgrim's Guide to Global Justice.Millennium: Journal of International Studies 39 (2): 547–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barras, Amélie, Selby, Jennifer A., and Adrian, Melanie, eds. 2021. Producing Islam(s) in Canada: On Knowledge, Positionality, and Politics. Toronto; Buffalo; London: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartelson, Jens. 2013. “Three Concepts of Recognition.” International Theory 5 (1): 107–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartelson, Jens. 2016. “Recognition: A Short History.” Ethics & International Affairs 30 (3): 303–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Batnitzky, Leora. 2011. How Judaism Became a Religion: An Introduction to Modern Jewish Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bender, Courtney, and Klassen, Pamela E., eds. 2010. After Pluralism: Reimagining Religious Engagement. Parts. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Bettiza, Gregorio. 2019. Finding Faith in Foreign Policy: Religion and American Diplomacy in a Postsecular World. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Birnbaum, Maria. 2015. “Exclusive Pluralism: The Problems of Habermas’ Postsecular Argument and the ‘Making of’ Religion.” In Religion as a Category of Governance and Sovereignty, edited by Stack, Trevor, Goldenberg, Naomi and Fitzgerald, Timothy, 182–96. Leiden and Boston: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Birnbaum, Maria. 2017. “Arbiters of Orthodoxy: Contentious Politics and Epistemological Change.Politics, Religion & Ideology 18 (1): 109–12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Birnbaum, Maria. 2020. “Recognizing Diversity: Establishing Religious Difference in Pakistan and Israel.” In Culture and Order in World Politics, edited by Phillips, Andrew and Reus-Smit, Christian, 250–70. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Birnbaum, Maria. 2022. “Entangled Empire: Religion and the Transnational History of Pakistan and Israel.” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 50 (2): 561–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bosco, Robert M. 2009. “Persistent Orientalisms: The Concept of Religion in International Relations.Journal of International Relations and Development 12 (1): 90111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blankholm, Joseph. 2022. The Secular Paradox: On the Religiosity of the Not Religious. Secular Studies. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Braidotti, Rosi. 2008. “In Spite of the Times The Postsecular Turn in Feminism.Theory Culture & Society 25 (6): 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brincat, Shannon. 2017. “Cosmopolitan Recognition: Three Vignettes.” International Theory 9 (1): 132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Butler, Judith 2008. “Taking Another's View: Ambivalent Implications.” In Reification: A New Look at an Old Idea, edited by Honneth, Axel, 97119. The Berkeley Tanner Lectures. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Butler, Judith. 2021. Excitable Speech: A Politics of the Performative. London, New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calhoun, Craig J., Juergensmeyer, Mark, and VanAntwerpen, Jonathan, eds. 2011. Rethinking Secularism. Oxford, N.Y: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cavanaugh, William T. 2009. The Myth of Religious Violence: Secular Ideology and the Roots of Modern Conflict. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cesari, Jocelyne. 2021. We God's People: Christianity, Islam and Hinduism in the World of Nations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohn, Bernard S. 1996. Colonialism and Its Forms of Knowledge: The British in India. Princeton Studies in Culture/Power/History. Princeton, N.J: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Connolly, William E. 1999. Why I Am Not a Secularist. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Connolly, William E. 2005. Pluralism. Durham: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Coulthard, Glen Sean. 2014. Red Skin, White Masks: Rejecting the Colonial Politics of Recognition. Indigenous Americas. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crosson, J. Brent. 2020. Experiments with Power: Obeah and the Remaking of Religion in Trinidad. Class 200, New Studies in Religion. Chicago, London: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devji, Faisal. 2007. “Minority as a Political Form.” In From the Colonial to the Postcolonial: India and Pakistan in Transition, edited by Chakrabarty, Dipesh, Majumdar, Rochana and Sartori, Andrew, 8596. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Devji, Faisal. 2013. Muslim Zion: Pakistan as a Political Idea, First Harvard University Press edition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dressler, Markus, and Mandair, Arvind-pal Singh, eds. 2011. Secularism and Religion-Making. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, Hubert L., Rabinow, Paul, and Foucault, Michel. 1983. Michel Foucault, beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dubnov, Arie M. 2019. “The Architect of Two Partitions or a Federalist Daydreamer? The Curiouscase of Reginald Coupland.” In Partitions. A Transnational History of the 20th Century Territorial Separatism, edited by Dubnov, Arie M. and Robson, Laura, 5684. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dubnov, Arie, and Robson, Laura, eds. 2019. Partitions: A Transnational History of Twentieth-Century Territorial Separatism. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, Charlotte. 2018. “The Productive Force of the Negative and the Desire for Recognition: Lessons from Hegel and Lacan.” Review of International Studies 44 (5): 805–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, Charlotte, Lindemann, Thomas, and Sending, Ole Jacob. 2018. “Frustrated Sovereigns: The Agency that Makes the World Go Around.” Review of International Studies 44 (5): 787804.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erman, Eva. 2013. “The Recognitive Practices of Declaring and Constituting Statehood.” International Theory 5 (1): 129–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fadil, Nadia. 2011. “Not-/Unveiling as An Ethical Practice.Feminist Review 98 (1): 83109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fanon, Frantz. 2008. Black Skin, White Masks. New York: Grove Press.Google Scholar
Fox, Jonathan, and Sandler, Shmuel. 2005. “The Question of Religion and World Politics.” Terrorism and Political Violence 17 (3): 293303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fraser, Nancy. 1995. “Recognition or Redistribution? A Critical Reading of Iris Young's Justice and the Politics of Difference.” Journal of Political Philosophy 3 (2): 166–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fraser, Nancy, and Honneth, Axel. 2003. Redistribution or Recognition? A Political–Philosophical Exchange. London, New York: Verso.Google Scholar
Fukuyama, Francis. 1992. The End of History and the Last Man. New York, Toronto, New York: Free Press; Maxwell Macmillan.Google Scholar
Geis, Anna. 2018. “The Ethics of Recognition in International Political Theory.” In The Oxford Handbook of International Political Theory, edited by Brown, Chris and Eckersley, Robyn, 611–25. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Geis, Anna, Fehl, Caroline, Daase, Christopher, and Kolliarakis, Georgios, eds. 2015. Recognition in International Relations: Rethinking a Political Concept in a Global Context. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Gorski, Philip S. 2011. The Protestant Ethic Revisited. Politics, History, and Social Change. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Greenhill, Brian. 2008. “Recognition and Collective Identity Formation in International Politics.” European Journal of International Relations 14 (2): 343–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grosz, Elizabeth A. 2001. Architecture from the Outside: Essays on Virtual and Real Space. Writing Architecture Series. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Grzybowski, Janis. 2019. “The Paradox of State Identification: De Facto States, Recognition, and the (Re-)Production of the International.” International Theory 11 (3): 241–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hallward, Maia Carter. 2008. “Situating the ‘Secular’: Negotiating the Boundary between Religion and Politics.International Political Sociology 2 (1): 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartikainen, Elina Inkeri. 2019. “Candomblé and the Academic's Tools: Religious Expertise and the Binds of Recognition in Brazil.” American Anthropologist 121 (4): 815–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hassner, Ron E. 2003. “‘To Halve and to Hold’: Conflicts Over Sacred Space and the Problem of Indivisibility.” Security Studies 12 (4): 133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hassner, Ron E. 2016. Religion on the Battlefield. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayden, Patrick, and Schick, Kate, eds. 2016. Recognition and Global Politics: Critical Encounters between State and World. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Haynes, Jeffrey. 2014. Faith-Based Organizations at the United Nations. Palgrave Studies in Religion, Politics, and Policy. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1986. The Philosophical Propaedeutic, edited by George, Michael and Vincent, Andrew. Oxford, UK; New York, NY: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1991. Elements of the Philosophy of Right, edited by Wood, Allen W. and Nisbet, H. B.. Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heins, Volker M. 2015. “Recognition Going Awry: NGOs and the Global Rise of the Unelected.” In Recognition in International Relations, edited by Daase, Christopher, Fehl, Caroline, Geis, Anna, and Kolliarakis, Georgios, 199219. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 2002. “Grounding Recognition: A Rejoinder to Critical Questions.” Inquiry: A Journal of Medical Care Organization, Provision and Financing 45 (4): 499519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Honneth, Axel 2005. The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts. Translated by Joel Anderson. Reprinted. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 2008. Reification: A New Look at an Old Idea. The Berkeley Tanner Lectures. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 2010. “Rejoinder.” In Recognition and Power: Axel Honneth and the Tradition of Critical Social Theory, edited by van den Brink, Bert and Owen, David, 328–70. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 2012. “Recognition Between States: On the Moral Substrate of International Relations.” In The International Politics of Recognition, edited by Lindemann, Thomas and Ringmar, Erik, 2539. Boulder, CO: Paradigm Publishers.Google Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 2014. Freedom's Right: The Social Foundations of Democratic Life. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Honneth, Axel, and Rancière, Jacques. 2016. Recognition or Disagreement: A Critical Encounter on the Politics of Freedom, Equality, and Identity. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurd, Elizabeth Shakman. 2008. The Politics of Secularism in International Relations. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hurd, Elizabeth Shakman. 2012. “International Politics After Secularism.” Review of International Studies 38 (5): 943–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurd, Elizabeth Shakman. 2015. Beyond Religious Freedom: The New Global Politics of Religion. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hussin, Iza 2016. The Politics of Islamic Law: Local Elites, Colonial Authority, and the Making of the Muslim State. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hussin, Iza. 2018. “‘The New Global Politics of Religion’: Religious Harmony, Public Order, and Securitisation in the Post-Colony.” Journal of Religious and Political Practice 4 (1): 93106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ikäheimo, Heikki, and Laitinen, Arto, eds. 2011. Recognition and Social Ontology. Social and Critical Theory. Leiden; Boston: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ingram, Brannon D. 2018. Revival from Below: The Deoband Movement and Global Islam. Oakland, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Iser, Mattias. 2015. “Recognition between States? Moving Beyond Identity Politics.” In Recognition in International Relations, edited by Daase, Christopher, Fehl, Caroline, Geis, Anna, and Kolliarakis, Georgios, 2745. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jansen, Yolande. 2011. “Postsecularism, Piety and Fanaticism: Reflections on Jürgen Habermas’ and Saba Mahmood's Critiques of Secularism.Philosophy & Social Criticism 37 (9): 977–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kattan, Victor. 2018. “The Empire Departs: The Partitions of British India, Mandate Palestine, and the Dawn of Self-Determination in the Third World.” Asian Journal of Middle Eastern and Islamic Studies 12 (3): 304–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kessler, Oliver, and Herborth, Benjamin. 2013. “Recognition and the Constitution of Social Order.” International Theory 5 (1): 155–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lapidot, Elad. 2020. Jews out of the Question: A Critique of Anti-Anti-Semitism. Suny Series, Philosophy and Race. Albany: State University of New York.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindemann. 2014. “Interest, Passion, (Non)Recognition, and Wars: A Conceptual Essay.Global Discourse 4 (4): 483–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindemann, Thomas, and Ringmar, Erik, eds. 2012. The International Politics of Recognition. Boulder, CO: Paradigm Publishers.Google Scholar
Livingston, Alexander. 2022. James Tully: To Think and Act Differently. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luoma-Aho, Mika. 2009. “Political Theology, Anthropomorphism, and Person-Hood of the State: The Religion of IR.International Political Sociology 3 (3): 293309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lynch, Cecelia. 2020. Wrestling with God: Ethical Precarity in Christianity and International Relations. Cambridge Studies in International Relations 152. Cambridge ; New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mahmood, Saba. 2006. “Secularism, Hermeneutics, and Empire: The Politics of Islamic Reformation.” Public Culture 18 (2): 323–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mahmood, Saba. 2012. “Religious Freedom, the Minority Question, and Geopolitics in the Middle East.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 54 (2): 418–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mahmood, Saba. 2016. Religious Difference in a Secular Age: A Minority Report. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mahmood, Saba. 2017. “Secularism, Sovereignty, and Religious Difference: A Global Genealogy?Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 35 (2): 197209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markell, Patchen. 2000. “The Recognition of Politics: A Comment on Emcke and Tully.” Constellations 7 (4): 496506.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Markell, Patchen. 2003. Bound by Recognition. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Marzouki, Nadia. 2017. Islam: An American Religion. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mavelli, Luca. 2012. “Security and Secularization in International Relations.European Journal of International Relations 18 (1): 177–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mavelli, Luca. 2013. “Between Normalisation and Exception: The Securitisation of Islam and the Construction of the Secular Subject.Millennium-Journal of International Studies 41 (2): 159–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mavelli, Luca, and Petito, Fabio. 2012. “The Postsecular in International Relations: An Overview.Review of International Studies 38 (5): 931–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McIvor, Méadhbh. 2020. Representing God: Christian Legal Activism in Contemporary England. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Menon, V. P. 1997. The Transfer of Power in India. Reprinted. Hyderabad: Orient Longman.Google Scholar
Mufti, Aamir. 2007. Enlightenment in the Colony: The Jewish Question and the Crisis of Postcolonial Culture. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Onuf, Nicholas. 2013. “Recognition and the Constitution of Epochal Change.” International Relations 27 (2): 121–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owen, David. 2012. “Tully, Foucault and Agnostic Struggles Over Recognition.” In Recognition Theory and Contemporary French Moral and Political Philosophy: Reopening the Dialogue, edited by Bankovsky, Miriam and Le Goff, Alice. Reappraising the Political. Manchester, New York: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Pasha, Mustapha Kamal. 2012. “Islam and the Postsecular.Review of International Studies 38 (5): 1041–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pasha, Mustapha Kamal. 2017. “Religion and the Fabrication of Race.Millennium-Journal of International Studies 45 (3): 312–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pasha, Mustapha. 2018. “Beyond the ‘Religious Turn’ International Relations as Political Theology.” In The Sage Handbook of the History, Philosophy and Sociology of International Relations, edited by Gofas, Andreas, Hamati-Ataya, Inanna, and Greenwood Onuf, Nicholas, 106–21. Los Angeles: Sage Reference.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, Andrew, and Reus-Smit, Christian, eds. 2020. Culture and Order in World Politics: Diversity and Its Discontents. LSE International Studies. Cambridge, UK; New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Philpott, Daniel. 2019. Religious Freedom in Islam: The Fate of a Universal Human Right in the Muslim World Today. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Philpott, D. 2000. “The Religious Roots of Modern International Relations.World Politics 52 (2): 206–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Philpott, D. 2002. “The Challenge of September 11 to Secularism in International Relations.World Politics 55 (1): 66-+.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Philpott, Daniel. 2001. Revolutions in Sovereignty: How Ideas Shaped Modern International Relations. Princeton Studies in International History and Politics. Princeton N.J: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Pitkin, Hanna Fenichel. 1984. Fortune Is a Woman: Gender and Politics in the Thought of Niccolò Machiavelli. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Povinelli, Elizabeth A. 2002. The Cunning of Recognition: Indigenous Alterities and the Making of Australian Multiculturalism. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Rancière, Jacques. 1999. Disagreement: Politics and Philosophy. Translated by Julie Rose. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Reus-Smit, Christian. 2011. “Struggles for Individual Rights and the Expansion of the International System.” International Organization 65 (2): 207–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reus-Smit, Christian. 2013. Individual Rights and the Making of the International System. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richland, Justin B. 2021. Cooperation without Submission: Indigenous Jurisdictions in Native Nation-US Engagements. Chicago Series in Law and Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ringmar, Erik. 1996. Identity, Interest and Action: A Cultural Explanation of Sweden's Intervention in the Thirty Years War. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ringmar, Erik. 2015. “Recognition in International Relations: Rethinking an Ambivalent Concept in a Global Context.” In Recognition in International Relations: Rethinking a Political Concept in a Global Context, edited by Daase, Christopher, Fehl, Caroline, Geis, Anna, and Kolliarakis, Georgios. Palgrave Studies in International Relations. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire; New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Ringmar, Erik. 2016. “How the World Stage Makes Its Subjects: An Embodied Critique of Constructivist IR Theory.” Journal of International Relations and Development 19 (1): 101–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roy, Olivier. 2004. Globalized Islam: The Search for a New Ummah. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Salomon, Noah. 2016. For Love of the Prophet: An Ethnography of Sudan's Islamic State. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandal, Nukhet A., and James, Patrick. 2011. “Religion and International Relations Theory: Towards a Mutual Understanding.” European Journal of International Relations 17 (1): 325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandal, Nukhet Ahu. 2012. “The Clash of Public Theologies? Rethinking the Concept of Religion in Global Politics.Alternatives 37 (1): 6683.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schonthal, Benjamin. 2016. Buddhism, Politics and the Limits of Law: The Pyrrhic Constitutionalism of Sri Lanka. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sending, Ole Jacob. 2017. “Recognition and Liquid Authority.” International Theory 9 (2): 311–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sevea, Teren. 2020. Miracles and Material Life: Rice, Ore, Traps and Guns in Islamic Malaya. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shani, Giorgio, and Behera, Navnita Chadha. 2022. “Provincialising International Relations Through a Reading of Dharma.” Review of International Studies 48 (5): 837–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sheikh, Mona Kanwal. 2012. “How Does Religion Matter? Pathways to Religion in International Relations.Review of International Studies 38 (2): 365–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shindler, Colin. 2008. A History of Modern Israel. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sinanoglou, Penny. 2019. Partitioning Palestine: British Policymaking at the End of Empire. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snyder, Jack L., ed. 2011. Religion and International Relations Theory. Religion, Culture, and Public Life. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Strömbom, Lisa. 2014. “Thick Recognition: Advancing Theory on Identity Change in Intractable Conflicts.” European Journal of International Relations 20 (1): 168–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan, Winnifred Fallers. 2018. The Impossibility of Religious Freedom. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sullivan, Winnifred Fallers, Hurd, Elizabeth Shakman, Mahmood, Saba, and Danchin, Peter G., eds. 2015. Politics of Religious Freedom. Chicago, London: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Charles. 1994. Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Scott. 2005. The Global Resurgence of Religion and the Transformation of International Relations: The Struggle for the Soul of the Twenty-First Century. 1st ed. Culture and Religion in International Relations. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Scott M. 2010. “Living Critically and ‘Living Faithfully’ in a Global Age: Justice, Emancipation and the Political Theology of International Relations.Millennium: Journal of International Studies 39 (2): 505–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Troy, Jodok. 2020. “Legitimacy in the ‘Secular Church’ of the United Nations.” International Relations 34 (4): 565–82.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tully, James. 1995. Strange Multiplicity Constitutionalism Age Diversity – History of Ideas and Intellectual History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tully, James. 2000. “Struggles Over Recognition and Distribution.” Constellations 7 (4): 469–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tully, James. 2008. Public Philosophy in a New Key. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wendt, Alexander. 2003. “Why a World State is Inevitable.” European Journal of International Relations 9 (4): 491542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiener, Antje. 2018. Contestation and Constitution of Norms in Global International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Erin K. 2014. “Theorizing Religion as Politics in Postsecular International Relations.” Politics, Religion & Ideology 15 (3): 347–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Erin K. 2017. “‘Power Differences’ and ‘the Power of Difference’: The Dominance of Secularism as Ontological Injustice.” Globalizations 14 (7): 1076–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolf, Reinhard. 2014. “Treating Asian Nations with Respect: Promises and Pitfalls of Status Recognition.” Global Discourse 4 (4): 462–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe. 2018. “Sovereign Equality as Misrecognition.” Review of International Studies 44 (5): 848–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar