Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T17:04:04.650Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Limitations of hypocrisy as a strategy of critique in international politics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 October 2024

Katharine M. Millar*
Affiliation:
International Relations, London School of Economics and Political Science, London, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Hypocrisy, when addressed at all, is typically considered a functional, even valuable, aspect of international political practice within international relations theory. It is alternatively seen as necessary to the exercise of sovereignty and a rhetorical device used to seek pragmatic political change. Utilising insights from feminist, queer, and postcolonial theory, this article challenges this understanding of hypocrisy. The article demonstrates that hypocrisy is animated and elided by an investment in a particularly liberal vision of politics and international order (and concomitant obfuscation of the racialised, sexual, gendered, and colonial underpinnings of those same assumptions). The notion of hypocrisy relies upon a unitary and stable subject whose moral consistency is to be expected across time and space – a luxury less afforded to those disadvantaged within intersectional international hierarchies. Consequently, although the charge of hypocrisy appears to be about holding power to account, the article finds that it serves less to uphold normative principles than to re-centre the privileged and powerful subject – typically, the sovereign state of liberal international order – and its consistency with itself, as the unit and basis of moral concern. The article concludes by outlining the limitations of hypocrisy as a strategy of critique.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

Both practices of hypocrisy, as well as criticisms of hypocritical practices, are commonplace within international politics. States accuse other states of hypocrisyFootnote 1 as a tactic of statecraftFootnote 2; non-governmental organisations accuse states of hypocrisy in an attempt to promote change and hold them to previously expressed commitmentsFootnote 3; and corporations are accused of hypocritically leveraging rights commitments to protect market advantages.Footnote 4 International actors consistently engage in practices that may be read as hypocritical,Footnote 5 such as Global North states' attempts to reach agreements curbing fossil-fuel emissions in the Global South without addressing their own historical – and contemporary – disproportionate contributions to the emissions driving climate change.Footnote 6 Scholars have also expressed qualms about hypocrisy in academic practice, ranging from feminist concerns around co-optationFootnote 7 to resistance to parachute/helicopter research.Footnote 8

With a few key exceptions,Footnote 9 however, hypocrisy per se is rarely examined in international relations (IR).Footnote 10 The meaning of hypocrisy is interrogated even less often. Typically, rationalist approaches to IR regard hypocrisy as a functional practice sufficiently necessary to the conduct of international politics that it is normatively neutral or even positive.Footnote 11 Constructivist and liberal IR theory posits charges of hypocrisy (i.e. anti-hypocrisy) as a rhetorical strategy for promoting positive moral change within the international system.Footnote 12 Critical approaches to IR, in contrast, are more sceptical about the potential normativity of hypocrisy. Drawing upon the insights of feminist, queer, and postcolonial critique, this article demonstrates that existing theorisations (or lack thereof) of hypocrisy in IR are limited in several ways.

Mainstream IR treatments of hypocrisy are constrained by an implicit assumption that hypocrisy, as a practice or a rhetorical device, works the same for all actors and in all circumstances. Formally, practices of hypocrisy and corresponding critiques may arise within any given community or social context. The degree to which it is logical to tolerate hypocritical behaviour, or pursue a rhetorical stance of anti-hypocrisy, depends upon how a given actor is positioned in relation to both power and the status quo of the given community. This logic pertains in the international and in the theorisation of hypocrisy within mainstream IR theory.

Further, the article will demonstrate that mainstream IR's conceptualisation of hypocrisy reflects a specifically liberal political inheritance. As a practical matter, the status quo in which mainstream IR and the practices of international politics its account of hypocrisy is used to parse are embedded is the existing liberal international order. Both functional and normative accounts of hypocrisy in international politics tend to normatively or analytically presume it operates within a political system meaningfully analogous to (an idealised) liberal domestic polity. These accounts likewise assume that normative values are largely shared and more instrumental practices of, or tolerance for, hypocrisy maintains something worthwhile. Critical IR theory's sceptical treatment of hypocrisy, in contrast, reflects the approach's critique of the inconsistencies and exclusions of liberalism itself.Footnote 13

The naturalisation of liberalism within mainstream IR has two implications for the way hypocrisy is presumed to operate within the international system. First, it projects a set of assumptions that presume – not unlike much of the constructivist norms literatureFootnote 14 – that international stability is itself a normative good and, correspondingly, that the existing order is at least minimally desirable. Second, conventional IR's treatment of hypocrisy as an effective strategy of critique relies on a liberal understanding of the self as a universalised, intentional, and autonomous political actor, consistent across time and space.

The aim of the article was not to diagnose this account of hypocrisy as good or bad per se. This is a contextual question relating to how those tolerating or critiquing hypocrisy relate to power and the status quo – in this instance, the liberal international order. Exposing instances of hypocrisy can be an important ‘weapon of the weak’.Footnote 15 Charges of hypocrisy, notably the ‘naming and shaming’ of human rights violations, may, under certain conditions, produce ameliorative changes in state behaviour.Footnote 16 Instead, this article seeks to complement this literature by examining the under-theorised consequences of the investment in liberal, universalist accounts of hypocrisy and its relationship to liberal international order.

First, as argued by Martha Finnemore,Footnote 17 it is difficult to levy charges of hypocrisy against another actor without implicitly reifying the principle at hand as valuable. The less-examined corollary of this point is that charges of hypocrisy make sense only to the extent that the actor levying the charge agrees with both the principle at hand and the system within which it is embedded. Anti-hypocrisy as a strategy of political critique works in the tenor of reform, rather than transformation. It is better suited to some political claims/projects (and thus positions of some actors within the existing international order) than others.

Second, although charges of hypocrisy legitimate the principle at hand, they do so by centring the moral consistency of the purported hypocrite as the primary locus of normative concern. The central question in instances of hypocrisy is less the merit of the relevant principle than the actor's consistency with itself, across time and space. This reifies a particular understanding of the actor – in this instance, a universalised, liberal self constituted via modern/colonial epistemes – and one that is less available/applicable to all political subjects. As a result, although the charge of hypocrisy is meant to hold power to account, those on the sharp end of the gendered, sexualised, racialised, and colonial hierarchies of the existing liberal international order are more vulnerable to being constituted as hypocritical (and ‘bad’ normative actors).Footnote 18

The article proceeds with an overview of existing conceptualisations – functional and normative – of ‘hypocrisy’ that characterise mainstream IR theory. It then demonstrates, drawing upon critical and postcolonial critiques, how these uses of hypocrisy reflect a continuation of the liberal ‘domestic analogy’ to the international, with important implications for the presumed desirability of existing international order. The article then illustrates the implications of naturalised normative and analytical liberalism within the theorisation of hypocrisy: the normative reification of the political status quo and a re-centring of the universalised, autonomous liberal self as the point of moral concern. The article concludes with an explication of the conditions under which hypocrisy may – or may not – function as a useful practice, or form of critique, in the international. This question hinges on whether the political project in question is oriented towards reform of the status or revolution.

Hypocrisy in IR

Hypocrisy, as observed by George Lawson and Ayşe Zarakol, Footnote 19 although frequently mentioned within disciplinary IR, remains under-theorised.Footnote 20 This section outlines the two broad uses of ‘hypocrisy’ – functional and normative – that, though they align with existing schools of IR theory, as noted below, crosscut the discipline. I use the functional/normative heuristic distinction to track how hypocrisy ‘works’ within mainstream IR broadly, as a precursor for demonstrating the two uses' mutual production within an assumption of liberal politics.

In typical usage, hypocrisy is understood as arising from a difference between a proclaimed standard – either for oneself or for others – and what one actually does.Footnote 21 As Martha Finnemore argues in her account of legitimacy, practice of hypocrisy does not pertain to just any form of speech, but rather ‘involves deeds that are inconsistent with particular kinds of words – proclamations of moral value and virtue’.Footnote 22 As a result, saying one thing and doing another – agreeing to a Tuesday deadline and completing the work for a Friday, fortunately for many academics – does not rise to the level of ‘hypocrisy’. Such actions are (usually) insufficiently linked to values, beliefs, and normative commitments to trigger the ‘moral opprobrium’ necessary to hypocrisy.Footnote 23 As further argued by Finnemore, hypocrisy pertains to ‘character and identity…we despise and condemn hypocrites because they try to deceive us: they pretend they are better than they are’.Footnote 24 Hypocrisy is also perceived to be dangerous to social order, as widespread practices of hypocrisy risk ‘destroy[ing] the very moral principles’ the hypocrites ostensibly uphold.Footnote 25

In IR, however, functional accounts of hypocrisy as a practice found within rationalist (i.e. neorealist and institutionalist) theories frame it as normatively neutral, even positive. Steven Krasner famously defines hypocrisy in international politics as the result of a clash between the logic of appropriateness and logic of consequences, wherein state leaders say one thing and, as a result of overriding interests, do another.Footnote 26 Sovereignty, for Krasner, is the paradigmatic instance of this form of pragmatic political hypocrisy. The modern state system requires the principle of juridical, territorial sovereignty to function – and yet it is constantly violated in practice.Footnote 27 As observed by Michael Lipson, this account of hypocrisy is a realist–rationalist version of sociologist Nils Brunsson's organisational theory extrapolated to the international.Footnote 28

According to Brunsson, political organisations frequently pursue values, priorities, and interests, that appear at odds with each other: they engage in hypocrisy.Footnote 29 Rather than positing this hypocrisy as a threat to political legitimacy, however, Brunsson sees the organisation of hypocrisy as a key benefit, and function, of institutions, which enable societies to balance diverse (and contending) political concerns without lapsing into conflict.Footnote 30 This argument, that ‘organized hypocrisy can hold important functional value’,Footnote 31 even survival value, has traction in IR. ‘Organised hypocrisy’ has been used to understand peacekeeping and the United Nations (UN),Footnote 32 statebuilding,Footnote 33 regional organisations,Footnote 34 the World Bank,Footnote 35 judicial reform in fragile states,Footnote 36 and multilateralismFootnote 37 amongst others. In this approach, the ‘problem’ to be managed is not hypocrisy, but rather failures in expectation-setting and communication that threaten actors' credibility.Footnote 38 The continued existence of the responsibility to protect as an ostensibly live international commitment despite its failure to be invoked in the face of many instances of mass atrocity violence since its inception is a good example of this practice.Footnote 39 Hypocrisy is instrumentally useful and implicitly normatively valuable to the extent that it preserves order and stability.Footnote 40

The second understanding of hypocrisy within IR, primarily associated with constructivism and the norms literature, is explicitly normative. Although this conceptualisation also tends to see critiques of hypocrisy, or anti-hypocrisy, as a rhetorical device and a means of preserving order, as potentially positive, it also betrays a concern that excessive exposures of hypocrisy may be destabilising. Finnemore argues that, to the extent that powerful actors have publicly declared support for particular principles (i.e. norms), charges of hypocrisy can be an important ‘weapon of the weak’.Footnote 41 The exposure of failures to adhere to these norms undermines states' credibility and legitimacy and generates social pressure to conform.Footnote 42 This, for example, is how the International Court of Justice and International Criminal Court are meant to work – producing compliance less through material enforcement than broader processes of social deterrence and ‘norming’.Footnote 43

Constructivism argues this dynamic of ‘rhetorical entrapment’, though not always framed explicitly as hypocrisy, contributes to norm compliance.Footnote 44 The exposure of, and presumed aversion to, hypocrisy (typically referred to in terms of ‘shame’) underlies most accounts of normative construction/diffusion/change,Footnote 45 including the boomerangFootnote 46 and spiral models.Footnote 47 The most prominent example of this mechanism is ‘naming and shaming’, wherein advocates expose states' failures to adhere to human rights norms as a means of (hopefully) holding them to account and spurring ameliorative change.Footnote 48 Hypocrisy is framed as negative in substance (i.e. human rights violations) but anti-hypocrisy as a positive rhetorical resource, as it provides ‘discursive openings that can be exploited’ to promote change.Footnote 49 Much of the literature is aimed at uncovering the empirical conditions under which accusations of hypocrisy are most likely to work,Footnote 50 with some scholars advocating for activists to focus advocacy on state hypocrisy rather than the value of human rights per se.Footnote 51

As observed by Lawson and Zarakol, much of this theorising implicitly or explicitly stems from the position of US unipolarity and foreign policy.Footnote 52 There is a racialised, civilisationalFootnote 53 presumption that naming and shaming, as Zarakol has long argued, and concomitant charges of hypocrisy, will be levied at outlying ‘bad actors’ who need to be brought into compliance with human rights norms.Footnote 54 For great powers (i.e. the USA), Finnemore suggests the normativity of hypocrisy is more complex, as ‘while unrestrained hypocrisy by unipoles undermines the legitimacy of their power, judicious use of hypocrisy can, like good manners, provide crucial strategies for melding ideals and interests’.Footnote 55

This position parallels Krasner's tolerance of functional hypocrisy. The difference is that unipole hypocrisy may be framed as an explicit normative good, as it enables some values to be ‘sacrificed in the short term for the sake of other moral values’.Footnote 56 On this basis, normative theorist Richard Price argues that a hypocritical acceptance of a lesser moral evil should be understood as fundamentally distinct from the sacrifice of moral principles in pursuit of material or ‘venal objectives’.Footnote 57 Here, one might think of the European Union's tolerance of members' illiberal practices – such as Hungary and Poland's democratic backsliding and declining human rights records –Footnote 58 in the seeming-service of preserving the liberal Union. Practices of hypocrisy can counter-intuitively bolster not only international stability, but also the legitimacy of the normative order.Footnote 59 The ‘problem’ of hypocrisy, in this account, is less hypocrisy itself than the risk of charges of hypocrisy reaching a level that ‘breeds cynicism and antipathy to politics’.Footnote 60

Overall, disciplinary IR's treatment of hypocrisy has primarily attended to how practices and rhetorical accusations of hypocrisy (anti-hypocrisy) work empirically (or fail to). The literature calls for both the strategic tolerance, or embrace, of hypocrisy as necessary to preserving international order and the practical utility of anti-hypocrisy critiques. It overlooks the meaning of hypocrisy per se and therefore fails to consider the situated theoretico-ideological assumptions upon which this naturalised conceptualisation of hypocrisy is founded.

Hypocrisy and liberalism

This section demonstrates the import of liberal accounts of hypocrisy into mainstream IR. Hypocrisy, and aversion to it, is not limited to liberal polities. The term hypocrisy stems from classical Greek theatre; as explicated by political theorist David Runciman, it originally related to the idea of ‘playing a part’Footnote 61 rather than a moral ill. Later, hypocrisy was associated with false piety: a critique of religious individuals who did not adhere to the tenets of faith they professed.Footnote 62 In so far as hypocrisy involves either a failure to act in accordance with principle or the attempt to hold others to a standard one does not adhere to oneself (i.e. ‘double standards’),Footnote 63 it need not pertain solely to liberal societies. This definition of hypocrisy pertains as much to communist states, anti-colonial independence movements, or religious communities as it does to liberalism.

As the balance of this section will show, however, liberalism has a particular account of hypocrisy, embedded in a series of assumptions about politics and political subjects, that informs IR. I use elements of liberal political theorist Judith Shklar's complex account of hypocrisy – centrally, her analysis of how hypocrisy operates – as a jumping off point from which to illustrate the logic of hypocrisy, both broadly and within liberalism. According to Shklar, as political communities within the West became more secular, the meaning of hypocrisy expanded from private conscience to a broader notion of ‘sincerity’ (in the sense of genuine commitment, combined with some notion of good intentions).Footnote 64 Hypocrisy refers to a discrepancy between publicly declared morals/beliefs and private behaviour. It entails a normative intolerance for a separation in the standards of those spheres. In liberal polities the public/private divide constitutes, and is challenged by, hypocrisy.Footnote 65

This duality between the public and private makes liberalism particularly vulnerable to charges of hypocrisy. As Shklar observes, liberal political systems are premised upon compromise, a stance that resists the acontextual moral consistency suggested by the aversion to hypocrisy.Footnote 66 This vulnerability is compounded by liberalism's ideological commitment to individual autonomy/equality – and implicit promise of meritocracy – and the consistent contradiction of those principles by quotidian inequality in liberal polities.Footnote 67 (Notably, for Shklar, hypocrisy that obscures, or is tantamount to, cruelty cannot be accepted. Hypocrisy that furthers liberal democracy in protecting human diversity (and addressing cruelty) is tolerable.Footnote 68) The pragmatic solution is not to insist on perfect public sincerity (which would require acknowledging lived experiences of inequality) but rather, for the sake of a functioning liberal democracy, to ‘act as if’ all people were formally and morally equal.Footnote 69 Liberalism depends upon a form of hypocrisy that insists upon its universality.

Liberal analogy

Key components of a broadly liberal account of hypocrisy's functions and dysfunctions are apparent in IR. Although many scholars hold that the play between private misdeeds and public commitments is, in theory, inapplicable to the international,Footnote 70 the anti-hypocrisy mechanism of naming and shaming, now inflected by the distinction between domestic and international, follows this logic precisely. As in much of IR theory, the public/private distinction is transposed to the international/domestic distinction,Footnote 71 wherein the ‘bad’ private behaviour aligns with, for instance, domestic human rights violations that contradict the ‘public’ support of human rights made to the international community.

Likewise, critiques of states as enacting ‘double standards’ – such as demanding human rights standards abroad perceived to be greater than what is practiced ‘at home’ – are an affront to the equality and recognition that is meant to characterise relations between political actors within domestic liberal polities and sovereign states abroad.Footnote 72 The presumption that the exposure of hypocrisy will have political effects,Footnote 73 similarly, mirrors the liberal ideological belief that once new facts are produced and publicly known, shared rationality will lead to a common diagnosis and positive change.Footnote 74

The implicit construction of hypocrisy within constructivism is indebted to how hypocrisy is presumed to work within liberal political theory/polities. It reflects the tendency of constructivism – and the norms literature specifically – to focus on liberal politics, practices, and beliefs.Footnote 75 The rationalist approach to IR hypocrisy, however, also demonstrates these liberal underpinnings. Although Brunsson's account of organised hypocrisy, which much of the functional literature draws upon, is explicitly framed as generalisable to a variety of organisations, it was developed with reference to Swedish local government.Footnote 76 The organisation of hypocrisy was paradigmatically illustrated with the imperative to balance competing values and priorities within a democracy.Footnote 77 As a result, although Krasner and other functional hypocrisy theorists seek to clarify the differences between domestic polities and the international, the logic of hypocrisy remains informed by an underlying conceptual, if not substantive, liberalism.

Disciplinary IR's account of hypocrisy thus rests on blurred liberal analytic and normative commitments. The theorisation of both the tolerance of hypocrisy in the international and the utility of rhetorical charges of anti-hypocrisy by mainstream IR scholars – functionalists, normative theorists, and the many empiricists evaluating the bounds and efficacy of charges of hypocrisy – reflects an underlying analytic universalisation of specifically liberal political logics. IR's construction of tolerance of hypocrisy as positive relies on an underlying assumption that hypocrisy works in the service of preserving not any form of international order, but a specifically liberal one.

The underlying liberal international order is necessary for the functional and normative logics of hypocrisy to operate as theorised. It is reproduced by these same assumptions. The normative point is not that tolerating hypocrisy or anti-hypocrisy critique is good, but rather that liberalism is. This is what makes public accusations of hypocrisy – against, particularly, the liberal states and principles presumed to make up the international order – ostensibly more dangerous than hypocrisy itself.

Liberal hypocrisy

Critical IR theory, in contrast, following its scepticism towards liberalism's ideological commitments to equality, individualism, and autonomy, regards the pragmatic value of hypocrisy with scepticism. This scholarship highlights the strategic and ideological value of what Edward Said and Ranajit Guha frame as liberal hypocrisy.Footnote 78 Here, the uneven extension of liberal rights and recognition to all peoples is not a failure, of some ‘actually existing liberalism’,Footnote 79 but rather a reflection of its constitutive inextricability from empire and racialised hierarchy. This is the primary distinction from liberal accounts of hypocrisy: what liberal theorists may read as problems to be addressed by liberalism, postcolonial scholars read as necessary to liberalism.

Postcolonial and decolonial scholars argue that the ‘progressive’ manifestation of liberalism in the European core, as both ideology and system of governance, depends upon the networked, colonial exploitation of others around the globe.Footnote 80 The inside/outside distinction that facilitates the double standards of moral proclamations internationally, and denial of inequality and violence ‘at home’, reflects a broader ‘wilful amnesia’ of the ways in which the (liberal) international order relies upon and reproduces racialised expropriation, genocide, and displacement.Footnote 81 As argued by Anthony Anghie and Laura Benton respectively, sovereignty is less a matter of functional hypocrisy amongst equals than an imperial means of excluding racialised peoples and colonial spaces from ‘the international’ along juridical, liberal lines.Footnote 82

The hypocrisy mainstream IR frame as instrumentally tolerable is made possible by a public/private, domestic/international distinction that is built upon, and yet belies, the legacies of empire and coloniality in ordering the international. This is seen in Beate Jahn's analysis of how the seemingly universal tenets of classical liberal political theory, particularly those derived from the apocryphal ‘state of nature’, rely upon a racialised notion of difference from non-European Others that facilitated mass violence, dispossession, and the differential extension of rights from the inception of European colonialism through the present.Footnote 83 The argument of some critical scholars that international law is inconsistently applied to Palestine (the ‘Palestine exception’) would, here, be read less as a liberal failure than a reflection of its continued entanglement with settler colonialism.Footnote 84 Nivi Manchanda, relatedly, argues that the Trump administration should be viewed not as aberrant to liberalism, but rather a manifestation of its entanglement with colonial racial capitalism.Footnote 85 Liberalism might be the paradigmatic articulation of organised hypocrisy – to such an extent that, as empire and racial hierarchy appear to be constitutive of the system, we might question whether this is meaningfully hypocrisy at all.

Disciplinary IR is increasingly alive to these tensions within liberalism. Lawson and Zarakol, notably, are clear that liberalism's universal ideological commitments are consistently belied by inequities and hierarchies in liberal practice.Footnote 86 Despite an awareness of a disconnect between liberal aspirations and practice, however, the balance of the IR hypocrisy literature maintains a pragmatic commitment to liberal internationalism. Price argues – contra the critical position on liberalism – that the insistent exposure of hypocrisy, unaccompanied by an alternative/better practice,Footnote 87 is dangerous to (liberal) international order and thus itself potentially immoral. Lawson and Zarakol state this explicitly, arguing that charging the liberal international order with hypocrisy ‘not just help[s] to weaken the LIO, but…also play[s] [a] part in the formation of international orders that are likely to be explicitly hierarchical. Here there may be a cautionary case to be made: be careful what you wish for’.Footnote 88 IR broadly argues for the maintenance of international order, despite its flaws, via an implicit agreement to ‘act as if’ the promises of liberal universalism hold.Footnote 89

IR's pragmatic tolerance of the empirical failings of liberal international order, however, is not paired with an interrogation of how liberal theory and analytics themselves reflect liberalism's constitutive flaw: the racialised, colonial, gendered, and sexualised power at work in universalising a particular account of politics, morality, and subjectivity. The balance of the article plays out two related, deeper political perils of invoking the hypocrisy charge that arise as a function of its unexamined production within a liberal political tradition.

First, the article demonstrates that the existing IR account of hypocrisy implicitly supports the tolerance of hypocritical behaviour (particularly by great powers and/or former colonial states) in so far as it upholds the existing, hierarchical liberal international order. Second, the article demonstrates that the existing IR account of hypocrisy rests upon the universalisation of a particular model of agency – as white, masculinised, cis, heterosexual, and, vitally, monolithic – that is less applicable and available to those with less power in the liberal international. Overall, the normativity of hypocrisy – both as a practice to be tolerated and/or as an ameliorative strategy of critique – depends upon how a given actor relates to the status quo (substantively, the liberal international order).

Hypocrisy and reification

The first peril of invoking the hypocrisy charge stems from the fact that the effective political deployment of hypocrisy relies on the validation of the principle that is (not) being followed in the first place. Consider, for instance, a 2022 social media post by an Iranian foreign ministry spokesperson accusing the US of hypocrisy over its stated intention to increase sanctions on Iran following a crackdown on protests in reaction to the police killing of Mahsa Amini: ‘It would have been better for Mr Joe Biden to think a little about the human rights record of his own country before making humanitarian gestures, although hypocrisy does not need to be thought through’.Footnote 90 The claim is that the USA itself does not respect human rights (and thus applies a double standard) and is instead inflicting harm through sanctions (and thus acting hypocritically). This is a classic rhetorical use of hypocrisy in international politics for geopolitical ends, deployed by one state against another in a political conflict, but in the context of a presumptively shared normative standard (here, human rights). It also helps illuminate a logical flaw within the way hypocrisy is frequently used that is unacknowledged within IR theory (and international political practice).

Charges of hypocrisy make the most sense for those sharing the values of the relevant figure. In the classic domestic political example, conservative politicians and public figures may be shamed as hypocrites following their entanglement in sex scandals.Footnote 91 For those sharing an ideological or moral commitment to the violated values, this charge of hypocrisy follows. For those with liberal or progressive political commitments vis-à-vis sexuality, however, accusations of hypocrisy at least implicitly suggest that principles with which they may not agree – in this case, conservative, patriarchal, and/or heteronormative values – are valid and worth upholding.Footnote 92 In the above example, the Iranian state official is in the odd position of reifying liberal human rights principles the Iranian state has, in the past, opposed.

This dynamic is also illustrated by the following excerpt from a 1954 letter to The New York Times, commenting on the ‘Soviet hypocrisy’ of the USSR signing the UN Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide:

There is much tragic irony in the news that the Soviet Union has ratified the United Nations pact outlawing genocide…what else but genocide can we call the dispersion, murder, and imprisonment which have been suffered by innumerable Soviet peoples these past thirty-seven years?.Footnote 93

Here, the author critiques the USSR for perpetrating mass human rights violations and human suffering – a straightforward practice of naming and shaming. The direct object of critique here, however (the object of shame), is not the perpetuation of mass atrocities per se, but rather the USSR signing the Genocide Convention. The charge is hypocrisy, not violence. As a result, the letter is in the odd position of criticising the USSR for doing something the author agrees with and their home state has not done. The USA did not ratify the Convention until 1988.Footnote 94

Substantively, from IR's naturalised position of analytical and normative liberalism, these logical failings in the leveraging of hypocrisy are unobjectionable. Iran is responding to and reifying a form of liberal international hegemony; the USSR (and USA's) hypocrisy is in the service of upholding human rights and criminalising genocide.Footnote 95 The speakers, arguably, have simply made errors in reason in their use of the hypocrisy charge. The analytical point, here, is not that police violence, genocide, or mass human rights violations are in anyway defensible; acceptance of violence is not the opposite of a hypocrisy charge. The aim, instead, is to illuminate what happens when critique, including that of mass harm and suffering, are cast in the idiom of hypocrisy. The examples of Iran and the USA–USSR are analytically useful in demonstrating that: (a) charges of hypocrisy operate differently depending upon one's positioning within the existing system; and (b) that despite their short-term utility, accusations of hypocrisy can also, in reifying the terms of critique, work against the principles (and structural position) of the speaking actor.

Tolerating hierarchies

Although the above argument is made with respect to authoritarian states, the same dynamics pertain to actors without access to state power – including progressive, radical, and/or potentially transformative actors. For those marginalised within the liberal international, it is impossible to levy charges of hypocrisy without reifying the ideological system that makes those charges sensible.

To take another example, the Canadian state's treatment of Indigenous peoples – from police brutality to the failure to investigate missing and murdered Indigenous women and Two-Spirit people to over-incarceration to the abuse of children within violent residential schools, practices together acknowledged as genocideFootnote 96 – has been criticised as hypocritical.Footnote 97 Either the racist, colonial violence experienced by generations of Indigenous peoples at the hands of the Canadian state is a hypocritical contradiction to Canada's identity as a liberal, inclusive, and multicultural state or said identity is itself hypocritical in light of the state's foundational dependence upon genocidal settler colonial violence.Footnote 98 In contrast to the two examples above, Canada epitomises liberal hypocrisy.

Attempts to hold Canada accountable for violence and discrimination against Indigenous peoples through charges of hypocrisy – as violations of ostensible liberal commitments to equality, inclusivity, and so on – also reify that same vision of liberalism as accurate and legitimate.Footnote 99 It suggests a meaningfully universalist, open, and inclusive liberalism either: (a) exists, and is violated by these violences; (b) is possible; or (c) is aspirational. Criticisms of liberalism as hypocritical are unable to get at the foundational constitution/reliance of liberalism upon these violent ‘hypocrisies’.

The implicit tolerance of hypocrisy within IR theory thus does not account for the differential positioning of various peoples within the international system vis-à-vis the reified presumptions of liberal equality and inclusion. In instances of liberal hypocrisy, the hypocrisy people are asked to tolerate (even esteem) for the sake of liberalism, democracy, social order, and so on is not that of discrete individuals, politicians, or the Canadian state. Instead, it is the ideological system and social structure those actors are located within: a system productive of their own expropriation, marginalisation, and discrimination.Footnote 100

Appraisals of the pragmatic value of liberal hypocrisy (or what the mainstream literature might consider functional hypocrisy), despite its violences and inequalities, presume that individuals and peoples are positioned equally in relation to liberalism's aspirations and pitfalls. This assumption fails to engage with the many conceptual and theoretical critiques of even idealised ideological liberalism – let alone its imperfect practice – as foundationally reliant upon exclusion and marginalisation. Charles Mills, although sanguine about the possibility of revivifying Enlightenment ideals to address racial oppression, demonstrates that the social contract upon which most liberal political theory is premised does not exist between acontextual and ahistorical universal subjects, but relies upon and reflects an underlying agreement amongst white, European men to expropriate, displace, exploit, and marginalise Black and Brown peoples through imperialism, settler colonialism, and chattel slavery.Footnote 101 Carole Pateman, likewise, argues that the social contract is dependent upon an underlying sexual contract, wherein men collude to exclude women from the public sphere, preserving patriarchal access to sexual and domestic labour.Footnote 102

Liberalism is predicated upon not only the universalisation of a particular subject – a white, cis, heterosexual, economically productive man – but also his positioning within a particular set of hierarchised gendered, sexualised, racialised, colonial power relations. The presumption that all subjects are positioned equivalently in relation to liberalism's failings is a particular standpoint universalised to the entire system. It is a form of racialised, colonial ignoranceFootnote 103 – facilitated by the articulation of abstracted ideological claims in the grammar of social scientific analysisFootnote 104 – that is related to, but exceeds, the ethnocentrism of social constructivism's presumption of a globally shared worldview.Footnote 105

From the perspective of those constitutively marginalised within liberalism, the call to tolerate liberal hypocrisy is not a call to ‘act as if’ everyone is equal. Instead, it is a call to ‘act as if’ liberalism treats oneself equally and to ignore one's own marginalisation and expropriation. The ‘problem’, here, of charges of liberal hypocrisy is not that they are dangerous to liberal international order. The problem is that they aren't. Critiques of individuals, states, or even liberalism as hypocritical do not (cannot) reflect upon the racialised, colonial, gendered, and sexualised aspects of liberal order itself.

Re-centring the centre

The reification of an idealised and decontextualised liberalism brings us to the second peril of using anti-hypocrisy as political critique. The hypocrisy charge suggests that being morally coherent is more important than the substantive normative content of either the principles or contravening actions themselves. Practices of hypocrisy are not framed as a means of interrogating the normativity, viability, social relations, and power dynamics of a particular set of values and political commitments, but rather the moral identity of the hypocritical actor.

Charges of hypocrisy are an attack on integrity and moral character: ‘to insinuate that someone is hypocritical is to collapse his self-image’.Footnote 106 Actors can be hypocritical in two ways: by condemning others for wrongs one often commits or by failing to align one's own conduct with one's own principles.Footnote 107 In each case, the centrality of the actor's beliefs means the ill of hypocrisy hinges on the actor's intentions and sincerity.Footnote 108 This is why, as Price points out,Footnote 109 the efficacy of a hypocrisy charge relies on the actor critiqued being sufficiently invested in both their own identity and the relevant construction of morality to adjust their actions.Footnote 110 Whether or not an actor is hypocritical hinges on whether or not the actor has violated their own sincere beliefs.

Consequently, charges of hypocrisy revolve around the character of the potential hypocrite – often, as hypocrisy is regarded a ‘weapon of the weak’, the more powerful actor – rather than the substantive harms impelled by their actions. As we saw in the above example of the USSR and the Genocide Convention, the USSR and its disingenuousness, rather than the mass violence in which it was engaged, was centred in the conversation. The USSR was not framed as the complicit or culpable agent, but rather as the object of moral concern. There is a risk, in international politics and liberalism-informed IR theory, of conflating hypocrisy and injustice.

This distinction is evident, for instance, in Runciman's analysis of how hypocrisy operated in political contestations leading up to the American Revolutionary War (1775–83). Runciman observes that in the present, the support of slavery by US founding fathers arguing for individual rights and freedoms, strikes us as the central hypocrisy of the era.Footnote 111 At the time, however, slavery was regarded by US politicians not (solely) as a moral harm,Footnote 112 but one of many dimensions of the British Empire's political hypocrisy.Footnote 113 The Crown criticised US settler colonists for practicing slavery though the Crown had not outlawed the slave trade.Footnote 114 Slavery was seen by US political actors as ‘symptomatic of the ways in which the double standards of empire had made it impossible for the colonists to control their own destiny’.Footnote 115

These charge(s) of hypocrisy do not address the central harm of chattel slavery: the mass enslavement and expropriation of Black people. The contention is not that slavery is wrong, but rather that an expectation of reciprocity amongst white colonial elites and the Crown has been violated. The operation of hypocrisy here reflects the constitutive operation of liberal hypocrisy. Constructing the contestation in terms of the consistency of the UK Crown depoliticised chattel slavery. This facilitated further cooperation by the white settlers amongst whom slavery remained a matter of contention. As the ‘lowest common denominator’ of political critique amongst those who cannot otherwise agree, charges of hypocrisy turn issues of substantive principle into diagnoses of character.

This normative emphasis upon hypocrisy also risks prioritising a coherence of stance and/or principle over the content and implications of those principles. As Lipson states, ‘condemnation of hypocrisy, in the normal sense of the term, assume that the hypocrite is a coherent, unitary actor. The moral stigma attached to hypocrisy flows from this assumption’.Footnote 116 This expectation of coherence and consistency is seen in the social relations of norm adherence, wherein the existence of a normative standard hierarchically differentiates amongst ‘good’ and ‘bad’ actors.Footnote 117 As Towns and Rumelili and Zarakol identify in their challenges to the Eurocentrism of constructivist IR, norm violators are constructed as ‘lesser states than those with better performance’Footnote 118; they are belittled and stigmatised.Footnote 119

The stigmatisation of norm violation means norm adherence is itself constructed as a normative position that requires constant maintenance. Inconsistency itself, Runciman observes, is typically insufficient to generate opprobrium; it is instead the commitment not to be inconsistent (a commitment frequently taken for granted in the liberal constitution of publicly oriented normativity) that is derided as hypocritical.Footnote 120

Consistency and marginalisation

This expectation of moral consistency relies upon and reifies a particular notion of the normative liberal political subject, whose constancy across time and space is lauded as the benchmark for morality. Not all people and communities, however, are included within, or have access to, the normative characteristics of the liberal political subject and presumptive normativity of liberal political orders. Interrogating the politics of hypocrisy also requires unpacking the inadvertent consequences of the naturalisation of this form of subjectivity for those positioned differently within liberalism/the liberal international.

Schematically, to be capable of hypocrisy, the relevant political actor must be conceptualised as intentional, rational, and autonomous: able to control their actions (exercise agency) and thus be held responsible for outcomes. The potentially hypocritical actor is typified by ‘inner consistency, substantiality, genuineness, and worth…usually as having begun in or around birth and liable to extinction with death’.Footnote 121 He is the universalised subject of liberal modernity,Footnote 122 whose integrity is a key determinant of rationality and, through the exercise of reason, morality.

Many, though not all, of the potential limitations of hypocrisy as a strategy of political critique stem from the particularistic characteristics of the normative liberal subject outlined earlier – that is, the implicit construction of the subject as white, cis, heterosexual, masculine, frequently settler/colonial – and their entanglement with the seemingly neutral attributes of liberal modern agency outlined above. The ‘reason’ of the liberal subject, for instance, is constructed in accordance with gendered, masculine tropes of objective, acontextual knowledge and rationality as expressed through instrumental goal-seeking.Footnote 123 Autonomy is likewise premised upon a social reality where the masculinised agent is unencumbered by social obligations or material constraints.Footnote 124

Likewise, the unitary subject presumes the existence of a single set of principles or commitments, internally consistent with each other, to which the subject may be held to account. This construction cannot attend to lived experiences of colonialityFootnote 125 and the differential positioning of peoples within imperial and racialised hierarchies. Coloniality, postcolonial and decolonial scholars argue, does not imply a mimetically transposed unitary, modern, liberal political subject, Instead, coloniality creates a ‘postcolonial subject’,Footnote 126 constituted through multiple locations, workings of power, and social relations simultaneously. Homni Bhabha's concept of hybridity refuses the application of a unitary Western subject to people existing in relations and spaces of coloniality, arguing they are both ‘Western’ and ‘local’.Footnote 127 Within Black US culture, Cornell West similarly argues that ‘there is no subject expressing originary anguish…but a fragmented subject, pulling from past and present, innovatively producing a heterogenous product’.Footnote 128 Decolonial feminist theorising likewise recognises a plurality of selves, informed by race, class, gender, sexuality, nationality, that are fluid and changeable across time and space, responding to material patterns of colonial oppression.Footnote 129

The expectation of a unitary subject, as identified by Rossdale and Zarakol in their critiques of the ontological security literature,Footnote 130 also reflects a preference for epistemological certainty and absolutist moral reasoning. It supposes that we can know hypocrisy and hypocrites when we see them, as the principles at hand are well-defined and contravention is obvious. This is not itself surprising; Western thought is structured and made meaningful via binaries. Most things are represented through an exclusionary logic of either/or.Footnote 131 The expectation of consistency with a unitary, unchanging self upon which hypocrisy relies reflects a broader normative preference for clarity and resolution and an intolerance for uncertainty and ambivalence.

Liberalism's insistence upon the homogenous and stable subject is constituted via hetero- and cis-normative assumptions. It excludes, and exists in opposition to, ‘the queer’, characterised by Sedgwick as that which will not (or cannot be made) to signify monolithically.Footnote 132 Accusations of hypocrisy reproduce a vision of the subject that excludes the plural and the fluid as lived experiences of queer people and as a mode of representation and politics.Footnote 133 The moral opprobrium that accompanies hypocrisy also cannot account for instances in which lived disconnects between the fictive ‘public’ and ‘private’ are a joyful, generative multiplicity of experience.Footnote 134 It is also a matter of survival for queer and trans people whose safety and fidelity to self is jeopardised by externally imposed expectations of ‘coherence’.Footnote 135

Hypocrisy's reliance on an implicit or explicit condemnation of ostensible ‘deception’, in particular, is cis-normative. It normatively prioritises an absolutist correspondence between ‘public’ and ‘private’ identity that reifies a binary, biologically essentialist heteronormative and cissexist gender order. Liberalism also, in its valorisation of ‘transparency’, reinforces a discriminatory expectation regarding the public's entitlement to know about and police such correspondence. The ideological elevation of the unitary self and value/existence of public ‘consistency’ reproduces the same transphobic antipathy for ‘deception’ that places trans people at risk of violence.Footnote 136 Monolithic normativity, both per se and in various substantive guises, within liberalism operates as a subtle form of coercive hegemony.Footnote 137

If we take the plurality of subjectivities seriously, however, the normative pull of hypocrisy loses power. A hybrid, fragmented, and/or plural subject implies multiple, superficially contradictory understandings of normativity.Footnote 138 These arise from the location of the actual people within multiple lived normative systems that include, but are not exhaustively defined by, the modern liberal international.Footnote 139 They also arise from the embedding of people in complex social relations of affect, love, obligation, and reciprocity – such as the way feminised subjects frequently provide/are expected to provide non-instrumentally rational ‘care’Footnote 140 – that inform their normative/political priorities and their ability to act ‘consistently’ across space and time. The hypocrisy charge fails to account for how people's differential experiences of gendered, sexualised, racialised, colonial, and capitalist hierarchies impede their ability (or desire) to be consistent over time.

Limitations of the hypocrisy charge

Hypocrisy, then, may not work as expected in international politics. Practices that may, from a liberal understanding of politics and agency, appear hypocritical, may instead be matters of survival and/or expressions of joy, morality, and connection. Inconsistency is a constitutive condition of multifaceted resistance or transformational politics.

The expectation of consistency with a unitary self, however, remains stigmatising.Footnote 141 Any actor, of course, is subject to censure for hypocrisy. No individual or collective actually is, or can embody, the normative liberal subject; no subject actually exists within its aspirational social relations.Footnote 142 The failure to act consistently with oneself over time, however, is constituted in exclusionary terms that do not attach to all actors equally. Acting ‘irrationally’ or ‘inconsistently’ aligns with gendered stereotypes of feminised subjects as mercurial or volatile, racist colonial tropes of dishonesty, deception or calculation, and hetero- and cis-normative constructions of ambivalence and plurality as dangerous.

Pragmatic strategies of calling out hypocrisy in international advocacy therefore risk reinforcing a model of the unitary, moral subject that furthers racialised, colonial, sexualised, and gendered marginalisation. This has two corollaries worth consideration. First, although hypocrisy is valorised as a rhetorical resource of ‘the weak’, the terms upon which anti-hypocrisy functions also make it an effective weapon against the weak. Second, the differential susceptibility to be read as hypocritical has important implications for various actors' ability to make a hypocrisy charge.

Philosophers Nicolas Cornell and Amy Sepinwall observe that successfully making moral claims relies on having (or being viewed to have) the ‘moral standing’ to do so.Footnote 143 Making charges of hypocrisy depends on not being regarded as a hypocrite oneself (giving yet another normative edge to the differential distribution of access to the unitary modern liberal subject). Accusations of hypocrisy as a political strategy are therefore particularly effective against those who seek transformative political change. Activists seeking radical solutions to climate change, for instance, still use some form of fossil fuels.Footnote 144 Indigenous activists seeking Indigenous sovereignty may also make formal, rights-based claims on the state.Footnote 145 Anti-capitalist advocates still lobby corporations for environmental and/or corporate social responsibility reforms, even as such policies are repackaged as ‘greenwashing’ to promote further consumption.Footnote 146 Here, ameliorative reforms by the relevant corporation follow from the ostensible co-optation, or hypocrisy, of activists.

Absolutist approaches to self-consistency and adherence to moral principle thus help discredit actors seeking transformative political change as hypocritical/unreliable.Footnote 147 Political visions that resist co-optation into liberal frames – such as abolitionism,Footnote 148 pacifism,Footnote 149 or horizontal Indigenous sovereigntyFootnote 150 – are dismissed as unviable/impossible partially on the basis that their advocates, because they remain embedded in the existing liberal order, are unable to demonstrate how these projects would ‘really’ work.Footnote 151 Charges of hypocrisy, then, may fail to address the short-term, substantive problem at hand by re-centring the more powerful actor's moral consistency. They may also strengthen the ideological and epistemological legitimacy of the same systems of racism, sexism, colonialism, homophobia, and transphobia that much activism – including that involved in explicitly liberal naming and shaming – seeks to confront and dismantle.

The implication of this argument is not that tolerating practices of hypocrisy or making anti-hypocrisy charges are necessarily normatively wrong or functionally useless. They are just limited. Everything is always reifying something; it would be analytically hypocritical to suggest an absolutist solution to the workings of power. As many scholars have argued,Footnote 152 rights and recognition are essential to life in the existing liberal international order and state system. The claim here is simpler. Scholars and activists ought to consider whether the social relations, hierarchies, and power dynamics built into the principles they indirectly uphold through the tolerance of hypocrisy and/or invocation of anti-hypocrisy are worthy of valorisation. Does (anti)hypocrisy impede or enhance the realisation of a more just world?

Conclusion

This article has argued that tolerance for hypocrisy follows only in instances where an actor seeks to maintain an existing system. Similarly, the hypocrisy charge as a strategy of critique is only logical if the actor levying the charge agrees with the principle being violated (and thus reified as valuable in the making of the charge). Anti-hypocrisy charges are also unable to get at the exclusionary and hierarchising assumptions and dynamics that constitute both the contemporary liberal international order and implicitly liberal theorisations of hypocrisy. Charges of hypocrisy tend to depoliticise the principle in question in favour of debating the hypocritical actor's moral integrity. The shaming associated with the hypocrisy charge leverages the actor's concern not so much to ‘bring about good or act rightly’, but rather to their desire to ‘avoid personal moral failure’.Footnote 153 The mechanism of anti-hypocrisy as a strategy for political change is self-centrism.

Charges of hypocrisy are thus an effective attack on status – hence their potential utility as a short-term, pragmatic form of critique – but are less effective in terms of broader normative change and contestation. The hypocrisy charge reifies a particular model of agency, subjectivity, and morality that reflects longstanding gendered, sexualised, racialised, and colonial material and epistemic hierarchies. The implicit universalisation of a masculinist, white, cis, heterosexual, and European notion of agency/morality also makes the hypocrisy charge particularly effective against, and less strategically available to, those excluded or marginalised within liberal modernity.

The primary implication of this analysis is that anti-hypocrisy charges are useful to the extent that the actor making the charge (a) agrees with the principle at hand and (b) is invested in the existing liberal international order. Although ‘naming and shaming’ is frequently considered a liberal, pragmatic strategy of the weak, it is more available to those with power. Despite concerns to the contrary, charges of hypocrisy cannot get at, or transform, either liberal hypocrisy or the liberal international order. Charges of hypocrisy work in the register of reform, not revolution. Tolerance of hypocrisy, then, should also be analytically and politically qualified by an assessment of the ends to which that tolerance is directed.

The final implication of this argument is that undue focus on hypocrisy obscures the relationality of the principles, justice claims, and harms that give rise to hypocrisy charges. An analytic and politics that relies on accusations of hypocrisy reflects a position of hierarchically empowered ‘innocence’, in the sense that it ‘den[ies] complicity in the oppression of others’.Footnote 154 This logic suggests that absent hypocrisy or overt and intentional harm, the actor is unimplicated in the fortunes of others, rendering their moral position secure. Morality is constructed as a function of decontextualised individual decisions/actions, rather than a function of pre-existing structures and patterns of hierarchy and inequality. Hypocrisy, in implicitly emphasising the individual actor's relationship to their own principles over time – to themselves – conflates accountability with shaming.

Critiques of hypocrisy are therefore fundamentally unable to get at a notion of ethics or justice based on mutual obligation and solidarity. The inability of charges of hypocrisy to meaningfully challenge or transform liberalism also means they are unable to direct normative questions towards ‘the current and historical connections between people, which are shaped by injustices that structurally disadvantage some and advantage others’.Footnote 155 To avoid prioritising a procedural, liberal notion of perfect ethical correspondence between self-image and action over addressing actual harms, scholars, practitioners, and activists must balance charges of hypocrisy with contesting complicity in injustice.

Acknowledgements

The author thanks Yuna Han, Aiko Holvikivi, Nivi Manchanda, Agnes Yu, the members of the LSE IR Dept Theory/Area/History Research Cluster, and particularly the International Theory peer reviewers for their generous and insightful engagement with this article.

Footnotes

1 Press Association 2014; British Broadcasting Corporation 2016.

3 Fernández Reference Fernández2022; Médecins Sans Frontières 2001.

4 Amnesty International 2022; Privacy International 2021.

7 Eschle and Maiguashca Reference Eschle and Maiguashca2018; de Jong and Kimm Reference De Jong and Kimm2017.

8 Nature Geoscience 2022.

10 Lawson and Zarakol Reference Lawson and Zarakol2023, 209.

12 Keck and Sikkink Reference Keck and Sikkink1998.

15 Brusby and Greenhill Reference Brusby, Greenhill and Friman2015, 114; Cardenas Reference Cardenas2006, 449.

19 Lawson and Zarakol Reference Lawson and Zarakol2023, 209.

20 I borrow the ‘mainstream’ definition of IR in referring to disciplinary international relations theory that explicitly constructs itself as such (i.e. (neo)realism, (neo)liberalism, constructivism, normative IR theory, some historical IR). Works that analyse transnational politics but are not framed as international relations, such as postcolonial thought – which, not coincidentally, treat hypocrisy differently – inform the critique of mainstream IR made here (with their relationship to critical IR theory noted where relevant).

21 See Runciman Reference Runciman2009, 8; Glaser Reference Glaser2006, 252.

22 Finnemore Reference Finnemore2009, 74.

23 Lipson Reference Lipson2007, 6.

24 Finnemore Reference Finnemore2009, 74.

25 Morgenthau Reference Morgenthau1951, 35, cited in Lipson Reference Lipson2007, 23; Price Reference Price2008, 204.

26 Krasner Reference Krasner2001, 174.

28 Lipson Reference Lipson2007, 7–8.

29 Brunsson Reference Brunsson1989; Mörkenstam Reference Mörkenstam2019, 1721.

31 Lipson Reference Lipson2007, 6.

34 Cusumano and Bures Reference Cusumano and Bures2022.

38 Egnell Reference Egnell2010, 490–91.

39 See Zähringer and Brosig Reference Zähringer and Brosig2020.

40 Lawson and Zarakol Reference Lawson and Zarakol2023, 209.

41 Finnemore Reference Finnemore2009, 65.

42 Finnemore Reference Finnemore2009, 61, 66–67; Towns and Rumelili Reference Towns and Rumelili2017, 763.

44 Price Reference Price2008, 204.

45 Towns and Rumelili Reference Towns and Rumelili2017, 757.

46 Keck and Sikkink Reference Keck and Sikkink1999.

49 Bower Reference Bower2015, 363.

50 Brusby and Greenhill Reference Brusby, Greenhill and Friman2015, 114. Although evidence on whether naming and shaming works is mixed (DeMeritt Reference DeMeritt2012; Hafner-Burton Reference Hafner-Burton2008; Krain Reference Krain2012; Squatitro et al., Reference Squatitro, Lundgren and Sommerer2019), the mechanism through which it is theorised to operate – exposing disconnects between normative commitments and actual action – remains hypocrisy.

51 Cardenas Reference Cardenas2006, 449.

52 Lawson and Zarakol Reference Lawson and Zarakol2023, 209.

54 Brusby and Greenhill Reference Brusby, Greenhill and Friman2015, 111.

55 Finnemore Reference Finnemore2009, 61, 81.

56 Price Reference Price2008, 205.

59 Finnemore Reference Finnemore2009, 72; Lantis and Wunderlich Reference Lantis and Wunderlich2018, 18.

60 Finnemore Reference Finnemore2009, 81; Price Reference Price2008, 204.

61 Runciman Reference Runciman2009, 8.

63 Runciman Reference Runciman2009, 8.

64 Shklar Reference Shklar1984, 62–66.

67 Lawson and Zarakol Reference Lawson and Zarakol2023, 210; Shklar Reference Shklar1984, 77. This aligns with social psychology experiments that find the salience of the hypocrisy aversion is greater in contexts that value independence than more highly value interdependence (Effron et al. Reference Effron2018).

68 Shklar Reference Shklar1984, 77; Han and Nantermoz Reference Han and Nantermoz2022.

70 Finnemore Reference Finnemore2009, 72.

71 Sylvester Reference Sylvester1994, 22; Lu Reference Lu2006, 119.

72 Lawson and Zarakol Reference Lawson and Zarakol2023, 205.

73 See Brusby and Greenhill Reference Brusby, Greenhill and Friman2015, 105.

77 Mörkenstam Reference Mörkenstam2019, 1721.

79 Hindess Reference Hindess2008, 349–50.

86 Lawson and Zarakol Reference Brusby, Greenhill and Friman2023, 210.

87 Price Reference Price2008, 210, 217.

88 Lawson and Zarakol Reference Lawson and Zarakol2023, 215.

89 From an intra-liberalism perspective, this may be read as a contestation over the meaning of cruelty, and which hypocrisies can be tolerated in the service of maintain the liberal international order.

90 Jordan Times 2022. On the protests, see Khatam Reference Khatam2023.

91 Gamson and Lowi Reference Gamson and Lowi2023.

92 See McDonough Reference McDonough2009, 287.

93 New York Times 1954.

94 Anton Weiss-Wendt (Reference Weiss-Wendt2017) argues that the USSR used the negotiation of the Genocide Convention to embarrass the USA for its hypocritical historical and contemporary racial violence. The USSR also worked to ensure that political groups were not specified as potential victims of genocide in the Convention. In drafting the Convention, major powers sought to ensure their own practices would not be qualified as genocide – a double standard constituted by internationalisation.

95 As Finnemore, Price, and many international legal scholars would expect.

96 Barber Reference Barber2015; Truth and Reconciliation Commission of Canada 2015.

97 See Ruffo in Robinson et al. Reference Robinson2019, 25–6; Merasty and Carpenter Reference Merasty and Carpenter2022; Cecco Reference Cecco2021; El-Sherif Reference El-Sherif2020; MacDonald Reference MacDonald2021; Samson Reference Samson2020.

98 Lackenbauer and Cooper Reference Lackenbauer and Cooper2007.

100 In a colonial context, it is arguably epistemic violence. See Fanon Reference Fanon1961.

103 Sabaratnam Reference Sabaratnam2020.

105 Zarakol Reference Zarakol2014, 312, 319.

106 Shklar Reference Shklar1984, 64.

107 Cornell and Sepinwall Reference Cornell and Sepinwall2020, 156.

108 Shklar Reference Shklar1984, 80.

109 Price Reference Price2008, 204.

110 The hinging of naming and shaming – hypocrisy – upon critiques of the self, rather than contestation over substantive rights and wrongs, helps explain defensive reactions to shaming the literature has found to undermine the efficacy of human rights norms (see Snyder Reference Snyder2020).

112 Chattel slavery was a matter of contention within the now-USA prior to the Revolutionary War, with some (predominantly free Black people and Black and white abolitionists) arguing against slavery with others, typically slaveholders, in favour. In another layer of hypocrisy, many slaveholders used the language of slavery to argue for independence, as they framed themselves as slaves of the British Crown. Dorsey Reference Dorsey2003; Jones Reference Jones and Holt2021; Shklar Reference Shklar1991.

113 Runciman Reference Runciman2009, 76–77.

114 The slave trade was outlawed in the British Empire in 1807; enslaved people in the colonies were not freed until 1838.

115 Runciman Reference Runciman2009, 76.

116 Lipson Reference Lipson2007, 9.

118 Towns and Rumelili Reference Towns and Rumelili2017, 764.

119 Zarakol Reference Zarakol2014, 314.

120 Runciman Reference Runciman2009, 9.

121 Laing Reference Laing2010, 41–42.

126 Jabri Reference Jabri2014, 380–83.

128 West, cited in Bhabha Reference Bhabha1994.

132 Sedgwick Reference Sedgwick1994, 8.

133 Hypocrisy is often understood in sexualised terms, both in the centrality of sexuality to understandings of ‘private’ morality and the use of heterosexual marriage to analytically illustrate the moral logic and opprobrium of hypocrisy (see Shklar Reference Shklar1984, 63). Hypocrisy literally needs a straight man.

137 Thanks to Nivi Manchanda for sharpening this point. See also Berlant Reference Berlant2020.

138 See Ahmed Reference Ahmed2000, 112.

140 The avoidance of hypocrisy asks one to heroically overcome/ignore the modern public/private divide and gendered expectations that come with it, something that women and feminised subjects are frequently less able to do/be recognised as doing.

141 Zarakol Reference Zarakol2014, 315–16.

142 Butler in Rossdale Reference Rossdale2015, 5.

143 Cornell and Sepinwall Reference Cornell and Sepinwall2020, 156.

145 See Razack's Reference Razack2016 (and special issue) use of both human rights discourses and Indigenous critiques of settler colonialism to confront the Canadian state's neglect of missing and murdered Indigenous women, girls, and Two-Spirit people.

146 E.g. Bloomfield and Manchanda Reference Bloomfield and Manchanda2024.

147 Gunster et al. Reference Gunster2018.

148 E.g. Cady Reference Cady2023.

149 E.g. Davis et al. Reference Davis2022.

150 E.g. Coulthard Reference Coulthard2014.

153 Cornell and Sepinwall Reference Cornell and Sepinwall2020, 155.

154 Razack Reference Razack1998 paraphrased in de Jong Reference Zarakol2017, 2.

155 de Jong Reference Zarakol2017, 59.

References

Abdo, Nahla. 2023. “The Palestine Exception, Racialization and Invisibilization: From Israel (Palestine) to North America (Turtle Island).” Critical Sociology 49 (6): 967–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Acharya, Amitav. 2007. “State Sovereignty after 9/11: Disorganised Hypocrisy.” Political Studies 55 (2): 274–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ahmed, Sara. 2006. “Orientations: Toward a Queer Phenomenology.” GLQ: A Journal of Lesbian and Gay Studies, 12(4): 543–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ahmed, Sara. 2000. “Boundaries and Connections: Introduction.” In Transformations: Thinking Through Feminism edited by Maureen McNeil, 111–18. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Amnesty International UK. 2022. “UK: Government Accused of ‘Hypocrisy’ in Hosting Survivors of Sexual Violence Summit”. 28 November. Available at https://www.amnesty.org.uk/press-releases/uk-government-accused-hypocrisy-hosting-survivors-sexual-violence-summit.Google Scholar
Anghie, Antony. 2007. Imperialism, Sovereignty and the Making of International Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Anzaldúa, Gloria. 1987. Borderlands/La Frontera: The New Mestiza. San Francisco: Aunt Lute Books.Google Scholar
Ashley, Richard K. 1989. “Living on Border Lines: Man, Poststructuralism and War”. In International/Intertextual Relations: Postmodern Readings of World Politics, edited by Der Derian, James and Shapiro, Michael, 259321. New York: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Barber, John. 2015. “Canada's Indigenous Schools Policy was ‘Cultural Genocide’, says report”, The Guardian, 2 June. Available at https://www.theguardian.com/world/2015/jun/02/canada-indigenous-schools-cultural-genocide-report.Google Scholar
Barkin, J. Samuel. 2003. “Realist Constructivism.” International Studies Review 5 (3): 325–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beneria, Lourdes. 1993. “Economic Rationality and Globalization: A Feminist Perspective.” In Feminist Economics Today: Beyond Economic Man, edited by Ferber, Marianne and Nelson, Julie, 115–34. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Benton, Lauren. 2009. A Search for Sovereignty: Law and Geography in European Empires, 1400–1900. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berlant, Lauren. 2020. Cruel Optimism. Durham: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernhard, Michael. 2021. “Democratic Backsliding in Poland and Hungary.” Slavic Review 80 (3): 585607.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bettcher, Talia Mae, 2007. “Evil Deceivers and Make-Believers: On Transphobic Violence and the Politics of Illusion”. Hypatia, 22 (3): 4365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhabha, Homni. 1984. “Of Mimicry and Man: The Ambivalence of Colonial Discourse.” October 28: 125133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhabha, Homni. 1994. The Postcolonial and the Postmodern: The Location of Culture. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bhabha, Homni. 1996. “Culture's In-Between.” In Questions of Cultural Identity, edited by Hall, Stuart and du Gay, Paul, 5360. London: Sage.Google Scholar
Biolsi, Thomas. 2007. “Race Technologies.” In A Companion to the Anthropology of Politics, edited by Nugent, David and Vincent, Joan, 400–40. London: Wiley.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blaney, David L., and Tickner, Arlene B.. 2017. “Worlding, Ontological Politics and the Possibility of a Decolonial IR.” Millennium 45 (3): 293311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bloomfield, Michael John, and Manchanda, Nivi. 2024. “Business, Power, and Private Regulatory Governance: Shaping Subjectivities and Limiting Possibilities in the Gold Supply Chain.” Regulation & Governance 18 (1): 8198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bower, Adam. 2015. “Norms without the Great Powers: International Law, Nested Social Structures, and the Ban on Antipersonnel Mines.” International Studies Review 17 (3): 347–73.Google Scholar
British Broadcasting Corporation. 2016. “Russia Accuses UK of Hypocrisy over Human Rights Record”, 27 April. Available at https://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-36151584.Google Scholar
Brown, Wendy. 2002. “Suffering the Paradoxes of Rights.” In Left Legalism/Left Critique, edited by Brown, Wendy and Halley, Janet, 420–34. Durham: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brunsson, Nils. 1989. The Organisation of Hypocrisy: Talk, Decisions, and Action in Organizations. New York: Wiley and Sons.Google Scholar
Brunsson, Nils. 2002. The Organization of Hypocrisy: Talk, Decisions, and Actions in Organizations. Copenhagen: Copenhagen Business School Press.Google Scholar
Brusby, Joshua W., and Greenhill, Kelly M.. 2015. “Ain't that a Shame? Hypocrisy, Punishment, and Weak Actor Influence in International Politics.” In The Politics of Leverage in International Relations: Name, Shame, and Sanction, edited by Friman, H. Richard, 105–22. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Cady, Duane L. 2023. “A Time – and a Project – for Pacifism and Nonviolence Studies.” Journal of Pacifism and Nonviolence 1 (1): 4151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cardenas, Sonia. 2006. “Violators’ Accounts: Hypocrisy and Human Rights Rhetoric in the Southern Cone.” Journal of Human Rights 5 (4): 439–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cecco, Leyland. 2021. “Canada Turns to Satirical Indigenous Website to Interpret Grim News”, The Guardian, 2 August. Available at https://www.theguardian.com/world/2021/aug/25/indigenous-news-site-walking-eagle-news-satire.Google Scholar
Césaire, Aimé. 1972 [1955]. Discourse on Colonialism. Translated by Joan Pinkham. New York: Monthly Review Press.Google Scholar
Cornell, Nicolas, and Sepinwall, Amy. 2020. “Complicity and Hypocrisy.” Politics, Philosophy & Economics 19 (2): 154–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coulthard, Glen Sean. 2014. Red Skin, White Masks: Rejecting the Colonial Politics of Recognition. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cronin-Furman, Kate. 2022. Hypocrisy and Human Rights: Resisting Accountability for Mass Atrocities. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cusumano, Eugenio, and Bures, Oldrich. 2022. “Varieties of Organised Hypocrisy: Security Privatisation in UN, EU, and NATO Crisis Management Operations.” European Security 31 (2): 159–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, Angela Y., et al. 2022. Abolition. Feminism. Now. London: Haymarket Books.Google Scholar
De Jong, Sara. 2017. Complicit Sisters: Gender and Women's Issues across North-South Divides. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Jong, Sara, and Kimm, Susanne. 2017. “The Co-Optation of Feminisms: A Research Agenda.” International Feminist Journal of Politics 19 (2): 185200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeMeritt, Jacqueline. 2012. “International Organizations and Government Killing: Does Naming and Shaming Save Lives?International Interactions 38 (5): 597621.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorsey, Peter. 2003. “To ‘Corroborate Our Own Claims’: Public Positioning and the Slavery Metaphor in Revolutionary America.” American Quarterly 55 (3): 353–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Effron, Daniel A., et al. (2018). “Hypocrisy and Culture: Failing to Practice What You Preach Receives Harsher Interpersonal Reactions in Independent (vs. Interdependent) Cultures.” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 76: 371–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Egnell, Robert. 2010. “The Organised Hypocrisy of International State-Building.” Conflict, Security & Development 10 (4): 465–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
El-Sherif, Lucy. 2020. “Six Nations Land Defenders in Caledonia Reveal Hypocrisy of Canada's Land Acknowledgements”, The Conversation, 9 September. Available at https://theconversation.com/six-nations-land-defenders-in-caledonia-reveal-hypocrisy-of-canadas-land-acknowledgements-145158.Google Scholar
Erakat, Noura. 2020. Justice for Some: Law and the Question of Palestine. Palo Alto: Stanford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eschle, Catherine, and Maiguashca, Bice. 2018. “Theorising Feminist Organising in and against Neoliberalism: Beyond Co-Optation and Resistance?.” European Journal of Politics and Gender 1 (1–2): 223–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fanon, Frantz. 2001 [1961]. The Wretched of the Earth. London: Penguin Classics.Google Scholar
Fernández, Belén. 2022. “The Massive Hypocrisy of the West's World Cup ‘Concerns’”, Al-Jazeera, 28 November. Available at https://www.aljazeera.com/opinions/2022/11/28/the-massive-hypocrisy-of-the-wests-world-cup-concerns.Google Scholar
Finnemore, Martha. 2009. “Legitimacy, Hypocrisy, and the Social Structure of Unipolarity: Why Being a Unipole Isn't All It's Cracked up to be.” World Politics 61 (1): 5885.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fung, Amy. 2023. “The Melancholy of Extraction: Settler Sentimentality in Canada's Ahistorical Era of Economic Reconciliation.” Global Sentimentality 2: 6588.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gamson, Joshua, and Lowi, Ted. 2003. Public Affairs: Politics in the Age of Sex Scandals. Durham: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Glaser, Daryl. 2006. “Does Hypocrisy Matter? The Case of US Foreign Policy.” Review of International Studies 32 (2): 251–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glasius, Marlies, Schalk, Jelmer, and De Lange, Meta. 2020. “Illiberal Norm Diffusion: How Do Governments Learn to Restrict Nongovernmental Organizations?International Studies Quarterly 64 (2): 453– 68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guha, Ranajit. 1997. “Not at Home in Empire”. Critical Inquiry, 23 (3): 482–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gunster, Shane, et al. 2018. “‘Why Don't You Act Like You Believe It?’: Competing Visions of Climate Hypocrisy.” Frontiers in Communication 3 (49): 114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hafner-Burton, Emilie. 2008. “Sticks and Stones: Naming and Shaming the Human Rights Enforcement Problem.” International Organization 62 (4): 689716.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Han, Yuna, and Nantermoz, Olivia. 2022. “Cruel Intentions: Liberal Logics and Processes of International Criminalization.” Global Studies Quarterly 2 (2): 111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harding, Sandra. 1992. “Rethinking Standpoint Epistemology: What is ‘Strong Objectivity’?”. The Centennial Review 36 (3): 437–70.Google Scholar
Hendrix, Cullen, and Wong, Wendy. 2013. “When is the Pen Truly Mighty? Regime Type and the Efficacy of Naming and Shaming in Curbing Human Rights Abuses.” British Journal of Political Science 43 (3): 651–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, Robert Lamon, and Plitnick, Mitchell. 2022. Except for Palestine: The Limits of Progressive Politics. New York: New Press.Google Scholar
Hinck, Robert. 2023. “US Hypocrisy and the End of American Exceptionalism? Narratives of the January 6th Attack on the US Capitol from Illiberal National Media.” American Behavioural Scientist, 67 (6): 807–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hindess, Barry. 2008. “Political Theory and ‘Actually Existing Liberalism’”. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 11 (3): 347–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hindess, Barry. 2009. “Liberalism and History.” Conference Keynote Address, Foucault: 25 Years On, University of South Australia. Available at https://unisa.edu.au/SysSiteAssets/episerver-6-files/documents/eass/hri/foucault-conference/hindess.pdf.Google Scholar
Jabri, Vivienne. 2012. The Postcolonial Subject: Claiming Politics/Governing Others in Late Modernity. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jabri, Vivienne. 2014. “Disarming Norms: Postcolonial Agency and the Constitution of the International.” International Theory 6 (2): 372–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jahn, Beate. 2016. The Cultural Construction of International Relations: The Invention of the State of Nature. Abingdon: Springer.Google Scholar
Jo, Hyeran, and Simmons, Beth A.. 2016. “Can the International Criminal Court Deter Atrocity?.” International Organization 70 (3): 443–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, Heather. 2012. “Why Comply: An Analysis of Trends in Compliance with Judgments of the International Court of Justice Since Nicaragua.” Chicago Kent Journal of International and Comparative Law 12 (1): 57100.Google Scholar
Jones, Nikole Hannah. 2021. “Our Democracy's Founding Ideals were False when they were Written. Black Americans have Fought to make them True.” In The Best American Magazine Writing, edited by Holt, Sid, 359–82. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Jordan Times. 2022. “Biden Warns Iran to Face ‘Costs’ for Crackdown on Amini Protests.” 4 October. Available at https://jordantimes.com/news/region/biden-warns-iran-face-costs-crackdown-amini-protests.Google Scholar
Keck, Margaret, and Sikkink, Kathryn. 1998. Activists beyond Borders: Advocacy Networks in International Politics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Keck, Margaret, and Sikkink, Kathryn. 1999. “Transnational Advocacy Networks in International and Regional Politics.” International Social Science Journal 51 (159): 89101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Khatam, Azam. 2023. “Mahsa Amini's Killing, State Violence, and Moral Policing in Iran.” Human Geography 16 (3): 299306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krain, Matthew. 2012. “J'accuse! Does Naming and Shaming Perpetrators Reduce the Severity of Genocides or Politicides?.” International Studies Quarterly 56 (3): 574–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krasner, Stephen D. 1999. Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krasner, Stephen D. 2001. “Organized Hypocrisy in Nineteenth-Century East Asia.” International Relations of the Asia-Pacific 1 (2): 173–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krishna, Sankaran, 2001. “Race, Amnesia, and the Education of International Relations.” Alternatives, 26 (4): 401–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackenbauer, P. Whitney, and Cooper, Andrew F.. 2007. “The Achilles Heel of Canadian International Citizenship: Indigenous Diplomacies and State Responses.” Canadian Foreign Policy Journal 13 (3): 99119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laing, Ronald David. 2010. The Divided Self. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Lake, Milli. 2014. “Organizing Hypocrisy: Providing Legal Accountability for Human Rights Violations in Areas of Limited Statehood.” International Studies Quarterly 58 (3): 515–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lantis, Jeffrey S., and Wunderlich, Carmen. 2018. “Resiliency Dynamics of Norm Clusters: Norm Contestation and International Cooperation.” Review of International Studies 44 (3): 570–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lawson, George, and Zarakol, Ayşe. 2023. “Recognizing Injustice: The ‘Hypocrisy Charge’ and the Future of the Liberal International Order.” International Affairs 99 (1): 201–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipson, Michael. 2007. “Peacekeeping: Organized Hypocrisy?.” European Journal of International Relations 13 (1): 534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, Genevieve. 1984. The Man of Reason: “Male” and “Female” in Western Philosophy. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Lowe, Lisa. 2015. The Intimacies of Four Continents. Durham: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Lu, Catherine. 2006. Just and Unjust Interventions in World Politics: Public and Private. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan.Google Scholar
Lugones, María. 2010. “Toward a Decolonial Feminism.” Hypatia 25 (4): 742–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacDonald, David. 2021. “Canada's Hypocrisy: Recognizing Genocide except Its Own against Indigenous Peoples.” The Conversation. 4 June. Available at https://theconversation.com/canadas-hypocrisy-recognizing-genocide-except-its-own-against-indigenous-peoples-162128.Google Scholar
Madhok, Sumi. 2022. On Vernacular Rights Cultures: The Politics of Origins, Human Rights, and Gendered Struggles for Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Manchanda, Nivi. 2023. “Lifting the Veil on Racial Capitalism: American Foreign Policy before and after Trump.” In Chaos Reconsidered: The Liberal Order and the Future of International Politics, edited by Jervis, Robert et al., 318–24. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDonough, Richard. 2009. “The Abuse of the Hypocrisy Charge in Politics.” Public Affairs Quarterly 23 (4): 287307.Google Scholar
McVeigh, Karen. 2022. “West Accused of ‘Climate Hypocrisy’ as Emissions Dwarf those of Poor Countries.” The Guardian. 28 January. Available at https://www.theguardian.com/global-development/2022/jan/28/west-accused-of-climate-hypocrisy-as-emissions-dwarf-those-of-poor-countries.Google Scholar
Medecins san frontieres. 2001. “Voices around the World Condemn Drug Industry Hypocrisy”, 16 April. Available at https://www.doctorswithoutborders.org/latest/voices-around-world-condemn-drug-industry-hypocrisy.Google Scholar
Mehta, Uday Singh. 2018. Liberalism and Empire: A Study in Nineteenth-Century British Liberal Thought. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Merasty, Joseph “Augie”, and Carpenter, David. 2022. “Life inside a Catholic-Run Residential School for Canadian Indigenous Children.” TIME. 15 September. Available at https://time.com/6213238/canada-residential-school-indigenous-children-excerpt/.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. 2014 [1997]. The Racial Contract. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Mondon, Aurelien. 2015. “The French Secular Hypocrisy: The Extreme Right, the Republic and the Battle for Hegemony.” Patterns of Prejudice 49 (4): 392413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgan, Jamelia. 2021. “Responding to Abolition Anxieties: A Roadmap for Legal Analysis.” Michigan Law Review. 120: 11991224.Google Scholar
Mörkenstam, Ulf. 2019. “Organised Hypocrisy? The Implementation of the International Indigenous Rights Regime in Sweden.” The International Journal of Human Rights 23 (10): 1718–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgenthau, Hans. 1951. In Defense of the National Interest New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Muñoz, José. 1999. Disidentifications: Queers of Color and Performance of Politics. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Murray, Dean, and Watson, Sophie. 2022. “‘Hypocritical’ Climate Activists Caught Dumping Plastic Waste.” The Independent. 22 September. Available at https://www.independent.co.uk/climate-change/news/just-stop-oil-flytipping-b2172759.html.Google Scholar
Nature Geoscience. 2022. “Tackling Helicopter Research.” Nature Geoscience 15: 597.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
New York Times. 1954. “Letter: Soviet Hypocrisy.” New York Times. 5 May. p. 30.Google Scholar
Pateman, Carole. 1988. The Sexual Contract. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Press Association 2014. “Russia Accused of Hypocrisy by UK over Ukraine Unrest.” The Guardian. 3 May. Available at https://www.theguardian.com/world/2014/may/03/russia-accused-of-hypocrisy-ukrainian-unrest.Google Scholar
Price, Richard. 2008. “Moral Limit and Possibility in World Politics.” International Organization 62 (2): 191220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Privacy Association. 2021. “On the Hypocrisy of Using Privacy to Justify Unfair Competition.” 21 January. Available at https://privacyinternational.org/news-analysis/4369/hypocrisy-using-privacy-justify-unfair-competition.Google Scholar
Razack, Sherene. 1998. Looking White People in the Eye: Gender, Race, and Culture in Courtrooms and Classrooms. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Razack, Sherene. 2016. “Sexualized Violence and Colonialism: Reflections on the Inquiry into Missing and Murdered Indigenous Women.” Canadian Journal of Women and the Law 28 (2): iiv.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Risse, Thomas, Ropp, Stephen, and Sikkink, Kathryn, eds. 1999. The Power of Human Rights: International Norms and Domestic Change. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, Dylan, et al. 2019. “Rethinking the Practice and Performance of Indigenous Land Acknowledgement.” Canadian Theatre Review 177 (1): 2030.Google Scholar
Rossdale, Chris. 2015. “Enclosing Critique: The Limits of Ontological Security.” International Political Sociology 9 (4): 369–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Runciman, David. 2009. Political Hypocrisy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryan, Cheyney. 2023. “Why Pacifism Now?.” Journal of Pacifism and Nonviolence 1 (1): 6575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sabaratnam, Meera. 2020. “Is IR Theory White? Racialised Subject-Positioning in Three Canonical Texts.” Millennium 49 (1): 331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Said, Edward. 1992. “Nationalism, Human Rights, and Interpretation.” In Freedom and Interpretation, edited by Johnson, Barbara, 175205. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Samson, Colin. 2020. The Colonialism of Human Rights: Ongoing Hypocrisies of Western Liberalism. New York: Polity.Google Scholar
Sedgwick, Eve Kosofsky. 1994. Tendencies. Durham: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sedgwick, Eve Kosofsky. 1997. “Paranoid Reading and Reparative Reading; or, you're So Paranoid, you Probably Think this Introduction is about you.” In Novel Gazing, edited by Sedgwick, Eve Kosofsky, 138. Durham: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shklar, Judith. 1984. Ordinary Vices. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Shklar, Judith. 1991. American Citizenship: The Quest for Inclusion. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Snyder, Jack. 2020. “Backlash against Human Rights Shaming: Emotions in Groups.” International Theory 12 (1): 109–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Squatitro, Theresa, Lundgren, Magnus, and Sommerer, Thomas. 2019. “Shaming by International Organizations: Mapping Condemnatory Speech Acts across 27 International Organizations, 1980–2015.” Cooperation and Conflict 54 (3): 356–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steele, Brent. 2007. “Liberal-idealism: A Constructivist Critique.” International Studies Review 9 (1): 2352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sylvester, Christine. 1992. “Feminists and Realists View Autonomy and Obligation in International Relations.” Gendered States: Feminist (Re)Visions of International Relations Theory, edited by Sylvester, Christine and Peterson, Spike, 155–78. New York: Lynne Reinne Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sylvester, Christine. 1994. Feminist Theory and International Relations in a Postmodern Era. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Todorov, Tzvetan. 1999. The Conquest of America: The Question of the Other. Norman: University of Oklahoma Press.Google Scholar
Towns, Ann. 2010. Women and States: Norms and Hierarchies in International Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Towns, Ann. 2012. “Norms and Social Hierarchies: Understanding International Policy Diffusion ‘From Below’.” International organization 66 (2): 179209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Towns, Ann, and Rumelili, Bahar. 2017. “Taking the Pressure: Unpacking the Relation between Norms, Social Hierarchies, and Social Pressures on States.” European Journal of International Relations 23 (4): 756–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Truth and Reconciliation Commission of Canada. 2015. “Honouring the Truth, Reconciling for the Future: Summary of the Final Report of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission of Canada”. Available at https://ehprnh2mwo3.exactdn.com/wp-content/uploads/2021/01/Executive_Summary_English_Web.pdf.Google Scholar
Weaver, Catherine 2008. Hypocrisy Trap. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, Cynthia. 2014. “From Queer to Queer IR.” International Studies Review 16 (4): 596601.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weiss-Wendt, Anton. 2017. The Soviet Union and the Gutting of the UN Genocide Convention. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
Worland, Justin. 2022. “Why you should Care about Celebrities’ Climate Hypocrisy.” TIME. 30 August. Available at https://time.com/6209448/california-drought-celebrities-climate-hypocrisy/.Google Scholar
Zähringer, Natalie, and Brosig, Malte. 2020. “Organised Hypocrisy in the African Union: The Responsibility to Protect as a Contested Norm.” South African Journal of International Affairs 27 (1): 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe. 2010. “Ontological (In)Security and State Denial of Historical Crimes: Turkey and Japan.” International Relations, 24 (1): 323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe. 2014. “What Made the Modern World Hang Together: Socialisation or Stigmatisation?International Theory 6 (2): 311–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe. 2017. “States and Ontological Security: A Historical Rethinking.” Cooperation and Conflict 52 (1): 4868.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zhou, Yuan, Kiyani, Ghashia, and Crabtree, Charles. 2023. “New Evidence That Naming and Shaming Influences State Human Rights Practices.” Journal of Human Rights 22 (4): 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar