Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-4rdpn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T07:31:13.979Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Justifying Retributivism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 July 2014

Michael S. Moore
Affiliation:
Leon Meltzer Professor of Law and Philosophy, University of Pennsylvania. An earlier version of this paper was given to the Fulbright Colloquium on Penal Theory, held at the Philosophy Department, Stirling University, Stirling, Scotland in September, 1992. My thanks go to the participants at the Colloquium for their helpful comments, and particularly in that regard to my commentator, Dudley Knowles of the Glasgow University Philosophy Department.
Get access

Extract

I shall address two concerns in this paper: first, what retributivism is, and second, how one justifies retributivism as the only proper theory of punishment. Since this paper is necessarily short, treatment of these topics is likewise abbreviated, although hopefully not so abbreviated but that it whets the appetite for those who wish to pursue them in greater depth.

Retributivism is the view that we ought to punish offenders because and only because they deserve to be punished. Punishment is justified, for a retributivist, solely by the fact that those receiving it deserve it. Punishment of deserving offenders may produce beneficial consequences other than giving offenders their just deserts. Punishment may deter future crime, incapacitate dangerous persons, educate citizens in the behavior required for a civilized society, reinforce social cohesion, prevent vigilante behavior, make victims of crime feel better, or satisfy the vengeful desires of citizens who are not themselves crime victims.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press and The Faculty of Law, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 My own views on these topics have been spelled out in greater detail in: “Closet Retributivism” (Spring-Summer 1982) USC Cites 9–16; Law and Psychiatry: Rethinking the Relationship (Cambridge U. P., 1984) 233–243; “The Moral Worth of Retribution”, in Shoeman, F., ed., Character, Responsibility, and the Emotions (Cambridge U. P., 1987) 179219Google Scholar, reprinted in Feinberg, Joel and Gross, Hyman, eds., Philosophy of Law (Wadsworth, 4th ed., 1991) 685707Google Scholar; Placing Blame: A Theory of the Criminal Law (Oxford U. P., forthcoming), chaps. 2 and 3.

2 The late John Mackie called this view “negative retributivism”: Mackie, J. L., “Morality and the Retributive Emotions”, (Winter/Spring, 1982) Criminal Justice Ethics 310CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Mackie, , “Retributivism: A Test Case for Ethical Objectivity”, in Feinberg, Joel and Gross, Hyman, eds., Philosophy of Law (Wadsworth, 4th ed., 1991) 677684.Google Scholar Note that the negative retributivist, if he is truly a retributi vist at all, must also be a positive retributivist. For the negative retributivist asserts that the justification for not punishing those who do not deserve it lies in the fact that there is no morally acceptable reason to punish in the absence of desert; this implicit appeal to the deserving of retributive justice is distinct from justifying the non-punishment of the innocent on grounds of fairness, liberty, or utility. (On the latter point, see Moore, , Act and Crime (Clarendon Law Series, Oxford U. P., 1993) chap. 3.Google Scholar

3 See Moore, “The Moral Worth of Retribution”, supra n. 1, at 182. David Dolinko has come to label this a “bold” retributivism, to be contrasted with a “weak” retributivism according to which it is only permissible to punish those who deserve it. See Dolinko, , “Some Thoughts About Retributivism”, (1991) 101 Ethics 537559, at 542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar The late John Mackie called this pair “positive” versus “permissive” retributivism, respectively: Mackie, “Retributivism: A Test Case for Ethical Objectivity”, supra n. 2, at 678; Mackie, “Morality and the Retributive Emotions”, supra n. 2, at 4.

4 Most notably, Hart, H. L. A., Punishment and Responsibility (Oxford U. P., 1968)Google Scholar, and Rawls, John, “Two Concepts of Rules”, (1966) 64 Philosophical Review 332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5 This Rawls/Hart distinction has been carried into more recent discussions by Raz, Joseph. See his Practical Reason and Norms (Oxford U. P., 1976).Google Scholar I argue against Raz's version of practice rules in Moore, , “Law, Authority, and Razian Reasons”, (1989) 62 S. Cal. L. R. 827896Google Scholar, and Moore, , “Three Concepts of Rules”, (1991) 14 Harv. J. L. and Public Policy 771795.Google Scholar

6 This distinction is explored in much greater detail in Moore, , “Torture and the Balance of Evils”, (1989) 23 Is. L. R. 280344.Google Scholar

7 Kant, , The Metaphysical Elements of Justice (J. Ladd, trans., 1966) 102.Google Scholar

8 See, e.g., Dolinko, , “Three Mistakes of Retributivism”, (1992) 39 UCLA L. R. 1623–57.Google Scholar

9 See Dolinko, ibid.; Schedler, , “Can Retributvists Support Legal Punishment?” (1980) 63 Monist 185198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar Compare Alexander, Larry, “Retributivism and the Inadvertent Punishment of the Innocent” (1983) 2 Law and Philosophy 233246.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

10 I owe this point to Dudley Knowles.

11 The retributiviet might adopt a principle of symmetry here — the guilty going unpunished is exactly the same magnitude of evil as the innocent being punished — and design his institutions accordingly. Or the retributivist might share the common view (that the second is a greater evil than the first) and design punishment institutions so that “ten guilty persons go unpunished in order that one innocent not be punished”. See Reiman, Jeffrey and Haag, Ernest van den, “On the Common Saying that it is Better that Ten Guilty Persons Escape than that One Innocent Suffer: Pro and Con” (1990) 7 Social Philosophy and Policy 226248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12 I explore both the doctrine of double effect, and the analogous doctrine distinguishing knowing visitation of harms on specified people versus risking harm to some unidentified part of a class of persons, in Moore, supra n. 6. As I there show in detail, any deontological view of morality must incorporate some such limits as these in order to specify the domain over which morality's absolute prohibitions range.

13 A “threshold” deontologist refuses to violate a categorical norm of morality until not doing so produces sufficient bad consequences as to pass some threshold — then, he will override such categorical norms. See Moore, supra n. 6.

14 For this older form of argument see, e.g., Quinton, A. M., “On Punishment” (1954) 14 Analysis 1933–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar For a related argument, seeking to tease retributivism out of our concept of law, see Fingarette, Herbert, “Punishment and Suffering” (1977) 50 Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association 499525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

15 Ronald Dworkin regards such claims as interpretive, although I prefer the older if less fashionable label, “functional”. For the difference, see Moore, , “Law as a Functional Kind”, in George, Robert, ed., Natural Law Theories (Oxford U. P., 1992) 201203, 220–221.Google Scholar For the functionalist claim that Anglo-American criminal law is a functional kind whose implicit goal is the seeking of retributive justice, see Moore, , “A Theory of Criminal Law Theories”, (1990) 9 T. A. U. Studies in Law 115185.Google Scholar

16 See Moore, , “Moral Reality”, [1982] Wise. L. K. 10611166Google Scholar; Moore, , “Moral Reality Revisited” (1992) 90 Mich. L. R. 24242533.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

17 Mill, John Stuart, Utilitarianism (Liberal Arte Prees, 1957) 44.Google Scholar

18 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Harvard U. P., 1971).Google Scholar

19 Moore, “The Moral Worth of Retribution”, supra n. 1.

20 For discussion and citations, see Moore, “The Moral Worth of Retribution”, ibid.

21 Hampton, Jean and Murphy, Jeffrie, Forgiveness and Mercy (Cambridge U. P., 1988)Google Scholar; Pillsbury, Samuel, “Emotional Justice: Moralizing the Passiona of Criminal Punishment” (1989) 74 Cornell L. R. 655710.Google Scholar

22 David Dolinko advances this form of the question-begging objection against my coherentist methodology with an example: “Consider, as an analogy, a similar coherence justification for the view, say, that women are inferior to men, offered circa 1800 by one man to another. Someone has raised the question of whether it is really justifiable to treat women as inferior and is met with the response that, ‘Well, of course, we all have the intuition that in this situation we should discriminate against women, and likewise in this and this; now, the best way of accounting for these particular judgments is to suppose women to be morally and intellectually inferior to men’. Wouldn't one feel that the crucial question is being begged?” Dolinko, supra n. 3, at 557–58. Notice that Dolinko trivializes the inference in his analogy in the manner attacked in the text: the particular judgments are not that this person should be treated in some inferior way in this context; rather, the particular judgments already include most of the terms of the principle to be abstracted from them — that the inferior treatment is discrimination; that the only feature to be mentioned is that the persons discriminated against are women.

By his choice of analogy, Dolinko also of course hopes to suggest that a coherence mode of justification is no guarantee against moral error, for we are only cohering our own beliefs and attitudes. One can easily concede this possibility of error without for a moment conceding Dolinko's hoped for conclusion (that this form of argument is question-begging). Our particular judgments of visual perception can of course also be in error on occasion, but that does not eviscerate the power of those judgments to be good (if not conclusive) reasons for believing the principles abstractable from them.

23 For an example of this form of the question-begging worry, see Mackie, “Retributiviem: ATest Case for Ethical Objectivity”, supra n. 2, at 679 (“‘Desert’ is not such a further explanation, but is just the general, as yet unexplained, notion of … retributivism itself”.)

24 These last examples are considered in Moore, Law and Psychiatry, supra n. 1, at chap. 5.

25 On wrongdoing, see Moore, Act and Crime, supra n. 2, chap. 7.

26 In his commentary upon this paper at Stirling my commentator, Dudley Knowles, appeared to take this view before eventually abandoning it See Knowles, “Unjustified Retribution”, in this issue, p. 50.

27 For a more complete taxonomy, see Cottingham, J.G., “Varieties of Retribution” (1979) 29 Philosophical Q. 238–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

28 Dolinko, supra n. 3, at 555.

29 An exception may be Herbert Morris' well-known principle of fairness, which may well survive the by-now voluminous criticisms made of it. See Morris, , “Persons and Punishment” (1968) 52 The Monist 475501.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

30 This is to take up the suggestion I offered in “The Moral Worth of Retribution”, supra n. 1, at 182, 186.

31 I am doubtlessly regimenting the usage of “desert” here a bit so as to give it this descriptive content. Some of the ordinary usages of “desert” are such that it can mean no more than “intrinsically right” or “intrinsically ought to be done”. Such broad, purely evaluative usages of “desert” account for the sense of Mackie and others that “desert” is an empty concept. See n. 23, supra.

32 For an unpacking of the notions of wrongdoing and culpability in the criminal law context, see Moore, “A Theory of Criminal Law Theories”, supra n. 16. For a comparison of some of the conditions of culpability in contract and criminal law, see Hart, H. L. A., “Legal Responsibility and Excuses”, in his Punishment and Responsibility (Oxford, 1968).Google Scholar

33 Dolinko, supra n. 3, at 543–44, 558; Dolinko, supra n. 8, at 1627–30.

34 Dolinko, supra n. 8, at 1629.

36 Ibid., at 1628 (quoting Moore, “The Moral Worth of Retributivism”, supra n. 1, at 180).

37 Ibid., at 1630.

38 Dolinko, supra n. 3, at 544 (quoting Feinberg, Joel, “Justice and Personal Desert”, in Doing and Deserving (Princeton, 1970), at 60Google Scholar).

39 Ibid., at 545.

40 Feinberg, Joel and Grose, Hyman, Phllosophy of Law (Wadsworth, 4th ed., 1991) 630.Google Scholar For similar queries about my thought experiments, see Kadish, Sanford and Schulhofer, Stephen, Cases and Materials on Criminal Law (Little, Brown, 5th ed., 1989) 145.Google Scholar

41 For the classical argument concluding that our moral beliefs cannot be about our own moral beliefs, see Moore, G. E., Ethics (1912)Google Scholar, and for an update, M.S. Moore, “Moral Reality”, supra n. 16, at 1075–1079.

42 This concession is made by the late Mackie, John in his Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (Penguin, 1977), chap. 1.Google Scholar

43 Michael Moore, “Moral Reality Revisited”, supra n. 16, at 2491–2501.

44 Walker, Nigel, Why Punish? (Oxford, 1991), chap. 9.Google Scholar Walker focuses on a fact he believes to be “awkward” for the retributivist, which is “the fact that by no means everyone perceives retribution as a duty” in response to my thought experiments. Walker anticipates that I might explain this fact by reference to a defective upbringing, but urges that I cannot avail myself of this explanation since it suggests that the perception which I posit “is really a learned reaction to offending rather than an inborn intuition”.

To begin with, Walker gets the competing explanations a bit askew: “Inborn intuition” is not the explanation competing with Walker's social upbringing explanation; “causation by the desert of offenders” is the competing explanation of our reactions offered by the retributivist. Secondly and more importantly, Walker is too Manichean in his competition between explanations. Surely part of why we believe anything (e.g., about physics) is due to our educational experiences; yet so long as another part of the overall explanation as to why we believe (e.g., that protons exist) is that our perceptual beliefs about cloud chamber phenomena are caused by protons, then we have good reason to believe such truths of physics.

45 See Mackie, “Retributivism: A Test Case for Ethical Objectivity”, supra n. 2; Mackie, “Morality and the Retributive Emotions”, supra n. 2. It is important to see that in these papers Mackie was not arguing against retributivism in substantive ethics; rather, he was arguing against moral realism in meta-ethics. Since my mode of justifying retributivism presupposes moral realism (in that the objective truth of retributivism causes us to have retributive attitudes), Mackie's attack on moral realism becomes an attack on my way of justifying retributivism.

46 Mackie, “Retributivism: A Test Case for Ethical Objectivity”, supra n. 2, at 683.

49 Mackie, “Morality and the Retributive Emotions”, supra n. 2, at 8–9.

50 Ibid., at 7.

52 Ibid., See also Mackie, supra n. 42, chap. 1.

53 Moore, “Moral Reality”, supra n. 16, at 1086–88, 1117–36; Moore, “Moral Reality Revisited”, supra n. 16 at 2501–2506, 2513–2526.

54 Mackie, “Morality and the Retributive Emotions”, supra n. 2, at 4.

55 See, e.g., Murphy, Jeffrie, Retribution, Justice and Therapy (Reidel, 1979)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sher, George, Desert (Princeton, 1987).Google Scholar

56 For the superiority of moral realist explanations of our moral beliefs generally, see Moore, “Moral Reality Revisited”, supra n. 16, at 2491–2533; Sturgeon, Nicholas, “Moral Explanations”, in Copp, David and Zimmerman, David, eds., Morality, Reason and Truth (Rowman and Allanheld, 1984)Google Scholar; Brink, David, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (Cambridge, 1989), chap. 7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

57 I explored this concern in some detail in “The Moral Worth of Retribution”, supra n. 1.

58 Ibid., at 199–202.

59 This heuristics view of consciousness is defended by me in “Mind, Brain, and the Unconscious”, in Clark, P. and Wright, C., eds., Mind, Psychoanalysis, and Science (Basil Blackwell, 1988).Google Scholar

60 The following is a sampling of the now considerable literature on the rationality of the emotions: Sousa, Ronald de, “The Rationality of the Emotions”, in Rorty, A., ed., Explaining Emotions (U. of Calif. P., 1980)Google Scholar; de Souea, , The Rationality of the Emotions (MIT Press, 1987)Google Scholar; Gordon, R., The Structure of Emotions: Investigations in Cognitive Psychology (Cambridge U. P., 1987)Google Scholar; Lyons, W., Emotion (Cambridge U. P., 1980)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Scruton, “Emotion, Practical Knowledge, and Common Culture”, in A. Rorty, supra; Calhoun, , “Cognitive Emotions?”, in Calhoun, C. and Soloman, R., eds., What Is an Emotion? (Oxford U. P., 1984)Google Scholar; Roberts, , “What an Emotion Is: A Sketch” (1988) 97 Philosophical Review 183209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

61 On the implicit reliance by Freud on these laws of appropriate emotional response, see Sachs, David, “On Freud's Doctrine of the Emotions”, in Wollheim, R., ed., Freud (Anchor, 1975).Google Scholar

62 This situation is nicely described in Morris, Herbert, “Nonmoral Guilt”, in Shoeman, F., Character, Responsibility, and the Emotions (Cambridge U. P., 1987).Google Scholar

63 Joseph Raz, for example, so takes this evidence. See the discussion in Moore, “Law, Authority, and Razian Reasons”, supra n. 6, at 860–61.

64 Joel Feinberg and Hyman Gross, supra n. 2, at 630.

65 Dolinko, supra n. 3, at 555.

66 Ibid., at 557.

67 Smith, M. B. E., “Is There a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law?” (1973) 82 Yale L. J. 950976CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Raz, Joseph, The Authority of Law (Oxford, 1979)Google Scholar; Hurd, Heidi, “Challenging Authority” (1991) 100 Yale L. J. 16111677.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

68 Dolinko, supra n. 3, at 667.

69 E.g., Hart, H. L. A. and Honore, Tony, Causation in the Law (Oxford, 2nd ed., 1985).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

70 Dolinko, supra n. 3, at 557.

71 Moore, “A Theory of Criminal Law Theories”, supra n. 15.

73 See, e.g., Kadish, Sanford, “The Crisis of Overcriminalization” (1967) 374 Annals 157170.Google Scholar

74 See, e.g., Shklar, Judith, Ordinary Vices (Harvard, 1984).Google Scholar

75 On the principle of legality and the values for which it stands proxy, see Moore, , “The Limits of Legislation” [Fall 1984] USC Cites 2332Google Scholar; Moore, Act and Crime, supra n. 2, chap. 9.

76 See Moore, “A Theory of Criminal Law Theories”, supra n. 16, at 181–83; Moore, , “Sandelian Anti-Liberalism” (1989) 77 Calif. L. R. 539661CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Raz, Joseph, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford U. P., 1987)Google Scholar; George, Robert, Making Men Moral: Civil Liberties and Public Morality (Oxford U. P., 1993).Google Scholar