Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-94fs2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-13T07:22:29.934Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Institutions, rule-following and conditional reasoning

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 March 2018

CYRIL HÉDOIN*
Affiliation:
Economics and Management Research Center REGARDS, University of Reims Champagne-Ardenne, Reims, France

Abstract

This paper is a contribution to the advancement of a naturalistic social ontology. Individuals participate in an institutionalized practice by following rules. In this perspective, I show that the nature, the stability, and the dynamics of any institution depend on how people reason about states of affairs that do not occur. That means that counterfactual reasoning is essential in the working of institutions. I present arguments for the importance of counterfactuals as well as a game-theoretic framework to account for them. Since the role of counterfactuals does not directly transpire in people's behavior, the whole discussion can be seen as a broad argument against behaviorism in philosophy and the social sciences.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Millennium Economics Ltd 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aumann, R. (1987), ‘Correlated Equilibrium as an Expression of Bayesian Rationality’, Econometrica, 55 (1): 118.Google Scholar
Aumann, R. and Dreze, J. (2008), ‘Rational Expectations in Games’, American Economic Review, 98 (1): 7286.Google Scholar
Bacharach, M. (1993), ‘When Do We Have Information Partition?’ in Bacharach, M., Dempster, M. A. H., and Enos, J. (eds), Mathematical Models in Economics, Oxford: University of Oxford, pp. 123.Google Scholar
Bennett, J. (2003), A Philosophical Guide to Conditionals, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Binmore, K. (2009), Rational Decisions, NY: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Board, O. (2006), ‘The Equivalence of Bayes and Causal Rationality in Games’, Theory and Decision, 61 (1): 119.Google Scholar
Bradley, R. (2016), Decision Theory with a Human Face, Mimeo, London School of Economics.Google Scholar
Brandenburger, A. (2014), The Language of Game Theory: Putting Epistemics into the Mathematics of Games, London: World Scientific.Google Scholar
Dietrich, F. and List, C. (2016), ‘Mentalism versus Behaviourism in Economics: A Philosophy-of-Science Perspective’, Economics and Philosophy, 32 (2): 249–81.Google Scholar
Elster, J. (2007), Explaining Social Behavior: More Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fudenberg, D. and Levine, D. (1993), ‘Self-Confirming Equilibrium’, Econometrica, 61 (3): 523–45.Google Scholar
Fudenberg, D. and Levine, D. (1998), The Theory of Learning in Games, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gintis, H. (2009), The Bounds of Reason: Game Theory and the Unification of the Behavioral Sciences, New York: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (2008), Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading, Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Greif, A. (2006), Institutions and the Path to the Modern Economy: Lessons from Medieval Trade, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Guala, F. (2007), ‘The Philosophy of Social Science: Metaphysical and Empirical’, Philosophy Compass, 2 (6): 954–80.Google Scholar
Guala, F. (2016), Understanding Institutions: The Science and Philosophy of Living Together, New York: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Guala, F. and Hindriks, F. (2015), ‘A Unified Social Ontology’, Philosophical Quarterly, 65 (259): 177201.Google Scholar
Gul, F. B. and Pesendorfer, W. (2008), ‘The Case for Mindless Economics’, in Caplin, A. and Schotter, A. (eds), The Foundations of Positive and Normative Economics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 339.Google Scholar
Hands, D. W. (2013), ‘Foundations of Contemporary Revealed Preference Theory’, Erkenntnis, 78 (5): 1081–108.Google Scholar
Hédoin, C. (2017), ‘Institutions, Rule-Following and Game Theory’, Economics and Philosophy, 33 (1): 4372.Google Scholar
Hindriks, F. and Guala, F. (2015), ‘Institutions, Rules, and Equilibria: A Unified Theory’, Journal of Institutional Economics, 11 (3): 459–80.Google Scholar
Jackson, M. (2012), ‘Machiavellian Intelligence Hypothesis’, in Seel, N. M. (eds), Encyclopedia of the Sciences of Learning, Boston, MA: Springer.Google Scholar
Levi, I. (1997), The Covenant of Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1969), Convention: A Philosophical Study, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1973), Counterfactuals, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
List, C. and, Spiekermann, K. (2013), ‘Methodological Individualism and Holism in Political Science: A Reconciliation’, American Political Science Review, 107 (4): 629–43.Google Scholar
Morton, A. (2003), The Importance of Being Understood: Folk Psychology as Ethics, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Perea, A. (2012), Epistemic Game Theory: Reasoning and Choice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ross, D. (2014), Philosophy of Economics, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Schelling, T. (1960), The Strategy of Conflict, Harvard: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sillari, G. (2013), ‘Rule-Following as Coordination: A Game-Theoretic Approach’, Synthese, 190 (5): 871–90.Google Scholar
Smit, J. P., Buekens, F. and du Plessis, S. (2011), ‘What Is Money? An Alternative to Searle's Institutional Facts’, Economics and Philosophy, 27 (1): 122.Google Scholar
Smit, J. P., Buekens, F. and du Plessis, S. (2014), ‘Developing the Incentivized Action View of Institutional Reality’, Synthese, 191 (8): 1813–30.Google Scholar
Smit, J. P., Buekens, F. and du Plessis, S. (2016), ‘Cigarettes, Dollars and Bitcoins – An Essay on the Ontology of Money’, Journal of Institutional Economics, 12 (2): 327–47.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1968), ‘A Theory of Conditionals’, in Harper, W. L., Stalnaker, R. and Pearce, G. (eds), IFS, University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science 15, Springer Netherlands, pp. 4155.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1996), ‘Knowledge, Belief and Counterfactual Reasoning in Games’, Economics and Philosophy, 12 (2): 133–63.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1998), ‘Belief Revision in Games: Forward and Backward Induction’, Mathematical Social Sciences, 36 (1): 3156.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1999), ‘Extensive and Strategic Forms: Games and Models for Games’, Research in Economics, 53 (3): 293319.Google Scholar
Tomasello, M. (2014), A Natural History of Human Thinking, Harvard: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (2010), Philosophical Investigations, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar