Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dk4vv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T07:59:55.641Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Imwinkelried's Argument for Normative Ethical Testimony

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

Professor Imwinkelried has boldly attempted to justify the admissibility of normative ethical expertise in the face of a legal evidentiary rule requiring a scientific basis for expert testimony. Because ethical testimony is inherently unscientific, Professor Imwinkelried prudently focuses his analysis on circumstances where evidentiary requirements are less strict; those involving the legislative rather than adjudicative function of courts and those in which substantive law overrides normally rigorous evidentiary requirements. While both proposals may have merit and are thoughtful and creative, Professor Imwinkelried ultimately fails to provide sufficient doctrinal support or persuasive rationale for his arguments.

Professor Imwinkelrieds argument for the admissibility of “expert” normative ethical testimony has two parts. The major proposition is that, when courts are engaged in legislative functions, they should be permitted to consider all sources of information. The assumption that apparently underlies this proposition is that nothing limits courts’ exercise of legislative powers.

Type
Symposium
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

509 U.S. 579 (1993).Google Scholar
526 U.S. 137 (1999).Google Scholar
Imwinkelried, E. J., “Expert Testimony by Ethicists: What Should be the Norm?” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 33, no. 2 (2005): 198221, at 198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
509 U.S. at 520.Google Scholar
Imwinkelried, , supra note 3, at text accompanying note 212.Google Scholar
Pierce, R. J. Jr., Administrative Law Treatise, 4th ed. (New York: Aspen Publishers, 2002), cited in Imwinkelried, , supra note 3, at note 213.Google Scholar
Fed. R. Evid., 28 U.S.C.A.Google Scholar
Adv. Comm. Notes, Fed. R. Evid., 28 U.S.C.A.Google Scholar
Davis, K., “A System of Judicial Notice Based on Fairness and Convenience,” in Perspectives on Law: Essays for Austin Wakeman Scott, Pound, R Griswold, E. N., and Sutherland, A. E., ed. (Boston: Little, Brown, 1964): 6995 (quoted in Adv. Comm. Note To Subdivision (a), Fed. R. Evid. 201).Google Scholar
Morgan, E. M., “Judicial Notice,” Harvard Law Review 57(1944): 269294, at 269, 270–71 (quoted in Adv. Comm. Note To Subdivision (a), Fed. R. Evid. 201).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adv. Comm. Note g, Fed. R. Evid. 201.Google Scholar
Davis, , supra note 9, at 82 (quoted in Adv. Comm. Note To Subdivision (a), Fed. R. Evid. 201).Google Scholar
358 U.S. 74 (1958).Google Scholar
Davis, , supra note 9, at 83 (emphasis added; quoted in Adv. Comm. Note To Subdivision (a), Fed. R. Evid. 201).Google Scholar
The test from Daubert instructs trial judges to be gatekeepers, excluding unreliable testimony by flexibly considering the following four factors (among others), at least where they reasonably shed light on the reliability of the proffered evidence: whether a theory or technique…can be (and has been) tested; whether it has been subjected to peer review and publication; whether, in respect to a particular technique, there is a high known or potential rate of error and whether there are standards controlling the technique's operation; and whether the theory or technique enjoys “general acceptance” within a relevant scientific community. Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc., 509 U.S. 579, 592–94 (1993), as summarized in Kumho Tire Co. v. Carmichael, 526 U.S. 137, 149–50 (1999).Google Scholar
Adv. Comm. Note to Subdivision (b), Fed. R. Evid. 201.Google Scholar
Imwinkelried, , supra note 3, at text accompanying note 123.Google Scholar
Id. at text in sentence following note 241.Google Scholar
Id. at text two sentences before note 242.Google Scholar
Id. at text accompanying note 242.Google Scholar
Id. at text in third sentence after note 242.Google Scholar
Id. at text accompanying note 41.Google Scholar
Id. at text accompanying notes 59–60.Google Scholar
Id. at text accompanying note 246.Google Scholar
Id. at text accompanying note 247.Google Scholar
Id. at text accompanying note 251.Google Scholar
Id. at text accompanying notes 254–55.Google Scholar
Id. at text accompanying notes 212–14.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Bobbitt, P., Constitutional Interpretation (Cambridge, MA.: Blackwell Publishing, 199l)(identifying historical, structural, doctrinal, and prudential modalities of constitutional interpretation in addition to ethical). Unlike the ethical arguments to which Professor Imwinkelried refers, these ethical arguments are “an appeal to those elements of the American constitutional ethos that are reflected in the Constitution,” and more normative than ethical in character. Id. at 20.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Hoffstadt, B. M., “Common-Law Writs and Federal Common Lawmaking on Collateral Review,” Northwestern University Law Review 96 (2002): 14131495, at 1413, 1432 (reviewing limits on judicial lawmaking power in the federal common law context). Scalia, Compare A., “The Rule of Law As a Law of Rules,” University of Chicago Law Review 56 (1989): 1175–1188, at 1175, 1182–83 (arguing that courts’ role should be limited to interpretation of statutes and passages in the Constitution) and Tribe, L. H., American Constitutional Law (St. Paul, MN.: West Publishing, 1978): 52 (arguing that it is the outcome of judicial analysis rather than the method of interpretation that results in laws that reflect social values). See also, Starr, K. W., First Among Equals: The Supreme Court in American Life (New York: Warner Books, 2002)(describing the different predelictions among current Supreme Court justices to create new law).Google Scholar
Webster's New Collegiate Dictionary (Springfield, MA.: Merriam Webster, 1973): 976.Google Scholar
Black's Law Dictionary, 8th ed. (St. Paul, MN: West Publishing, 2004).Google Scholar
Imwinkelried, , supra note 3, at text accompanying note 284 (stating “natural law theorists believe that there are universal moral standards, accessible to the human mind.”)Google Scholar
Id. at text accompanying note 273.Google Scholar
Keeton, W. P. et al., Prosser and Keeton on Torts 5th ed. (St. Paul, MN.: West Publishing, 1984): 21.Google Scholar
Id. at 23.Google Scholar
Id. at 20–26. See also, Kelso, J. C., “Sixty Years of Torts: Lessons for the Future,” Torts & Insurance Law Journal 29 (1993): 113, at 1 (arguing that courts and scholars have turned to asking instrumentalist questions such as whether the goals of tort law are well served by imposing liability in a particular case and that compensation and deterrence are the pillars of tort law) and Smith, S. D., “The Critics and the ‘Crisis,’ A Reassessment of Current Conceptions of Tort Law,” Cornell Law Review 72 (1987): 765–798, at 765 (arguing that resolving disputes is the primary focus of tort law). The goals tort law pursues certainly reflect social norms, but are not for that reason based on morals, as that term is typically used.Google Scholar
Imwinkelried, , supra note 3, at text accompanying notes 277–78.Google Scholar
Id. at text in the beginning of the section following note 286.Google Scholar
Id. (Emphasis added.)Google Scholar
Id. at text accompanying note 314.Google Scholar
Id. at text in paragraph containing notes 289–95.Google Scholar
Id. at note 287.Google Scholar
Id. at text following note 294.Google Scholar
Dobbs, D. B., Law of Remedies, 2d Ed. (St. Paul, MN.: West Publishing, 1993): 311.Google Scholar
Professor Imwinkelried alludes to a number of cases where the four criteria may be met but does not explore them in enough detail to evaluate them. Imwinkelried, , supra note 3, at note 297. These include family law cases involving the “best interests of the child,” which, he states, might permit consideration of moral factors; cases involving “inappropriateness of physician's sexual contact with a patient” given ethical standards of the profession; obscenity trials considering the “redeeming value” of allegedly obscene work, tort cases where an evaluative moral judgment of defendant's behavior for punitive damages is made instead of applying extant moral standards; and criminal cases involving an objective test of “spontaneous moral revulsion.” On their face, these examples seem no more likely than the punitive damages example to meet his criteria, though raising them as possibilities is provocative.Google Scholar
Barnes, D. W., “Too Many Probabilities: Statistical Evidence of Tort Causation,” Law and Contemporary Problems 64 (2001): 191212, at 192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
In jurisdictions where a plaintiff may recover for a future harm which has a less than 50% chance of occurring, damages are often calculated by multiply the probability of future occurrence (the fact probability) by the damages that would be appropriate if it did occur. When the defendant has created an increased risk of harm, i.e., when the fact of damage has been established, the question turns to the extent of that damage: “The probability percentage for the occurrence of a particular harm, the risk of which has been created by the tortfeasor, can be applied to the damages that would be justified if that harm should be realized.” Petriello v. Kaiman, 576 A.2d 474, 484 (Conn. 1990).Google Scholar
Imwinkelried, , supra note 3, at text accompanying note 314.Google Scholar
Id. at note 314.Google Scholar
Id. at text following note 314.Google Scholar