Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T08:36:26.345Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Feminist Perspectives in Health Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Abstract

This essay argues that feminist legal theory offers an important, and underutilized, perspective to examine health law and policy. We use several theoretical frameworks developed by feminist legal theorists including relational autonomy, intersectionality, vulnerability theory, and the feminist critique of the public-private divide to demonstrate the utility of these theories to health law analysis. These frameworks provide insights relevant not only to issues that obviously relate to gender, but also to matters of choice, quality, and access that are less obviously gender-related. We map three key areas of existing scholarship and future inquiry at the intersection of health law and feminist legal theory: (I) patient choice and relational autonomy, (II) patriarchy, power and patient safety, and (III) access to health care and healthy living conditions at the public-private divide. Uniting these areas of inquiry is a nagging question central to the relationship between critical legal scholarship (including feminist scholarship) and pragmatic action to combat injustice: Can we use legal rights to achieve our aims even as we recognize them as tainted tools that have propped up oppressive social structures? A feminist agenda for health law and policy must grapple with this dilemma.

Type
Symposium Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Social epidemiology is “concerned with the way that social structures, institutions, and relationships influence health.” Berkman, L.F. and Kawachi, I., “A Historical Framework for Social Epidemiology: Social Determinants of Population Health,” in Berkman, L.F., Kawachi, I., and Glymour, M.M., eds., Social Epidemiology, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014): 1-16, at 2.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Burris, S., “From Health Care Law to the Social Determinants of Health: A Public Health Law Research Perspective,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 159, no. 6 (2011): 1649-1667, at 1653 (“[C]onsistent correlations across populations between health and various forms of social and economic inequality leave little room for doubt that social arrangements account for an important fraction of population health.”); Rebouche, R. and Burris, S., “The Social Determinants of Health” in Cohen, I.G., Hoffman, A.K., and Sage, W.M., eds., Oxford Handbook of U.S. Health Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017): 1097-1112.Google Scholar
See, e.g., World Health Organization Commission on the Social Determinants of Health, Closing the Gap in a Generation: Health Equity Through Action on the Social Determinants of Health (2008) at 1, available at <http://whqlibdoc.who.int/publications/2008/9789241563703_eng.pdf> (last visisted November 22, 2019) (“[The] unequal distribution of health-damaging experiences is not in any sense a ‘natural’ phenomenon but is the result of a toxic combination of poor social policies and programmes, unfair economic arrangements, and bad politics. Together, the structural determinants and conditions of daily life constitute the social determinants of health and are responsible for a major part of health inequities between and within countries.”)+(last+visisted+November+22,+2019)+(“[The]+unequal+distribution+of+health-damaging+experiences+is+not+in+any+sense+a+‘natural’+phenomenon+but+is+the+result+of+a+toxic+combination+of+poor+social+policies+and+programmes,+unfair+economic+arrangements,+and+bad+politics.+Together,+the+structural+determinants+and+conditions+of+daily+life+constitute+the+social+determinants+of+health+and+are+responsible+for+a+major+part+of+health+inequities+between+and+within+countries.”)>Google Scholar
See Burris, supra note 2, at 1654.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Epstein, R.A., “In Defense of the ‘Old’ Public Health,” Brooklyn Law Review 69, no. 4 (2004): 1421-1470, at 1424 (“[T]he case for government intervention … gets that extra boost of legitimacy” when framed as a public health issue.”); Skrabanek, P., The Death of Humane Medicine and the Rise of Coercive Healthism (Suffolk: St. Edmundsbury Press, 1994): at 11 (“The roads to unfreedom are many. Signposts on one of them bear the inscription HEALTH FOR ALL.”); Wiley, L.F., “Rethinking the New Public Health,” Washington and Lee Law Review 69, no. 1 (2012): 207-272 (describing and refuting libertarian critiques of an expansive scope for public health law).Google Scholar
Hall, M.A., “The Scope and Limits of Public Health Law,” Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 64, no. 3 (2003): S199-S209, at S199 (“explor[ing] the proper scope of public health legal authority in response to compelling scientific evidence about the social determinants of health.”); Id., at S208 (“Beyond the public health arena, there are other good reasons for the government to pursue the more general aims of education, taxation, regulation, and redistribution, but these are broader social and economic policies or they belong to legal realms other than health. Public health advocates can be commended for calling our attention to the health implications of social disparities, but health promotion should not be the primary objective of corrective measures.”); see also Rothstein, M.A., “The Limits of Public Health: A Response,” Public Health Ethics 2, no. 1 (2009): 84-88, at 86 (“concerns about social justice should play a part in priority setting for public health. My point is simply that resolution of underlying socioeconomic and political problems is beyond the domain of public health.”)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCuskey, E., “The Body Politic: Federalism as Feminism in Health Reform,” St. Louis University Journal of Health Law & Policy 11, no. 1 (2018): 303-316, at 310 (“‘(H)ealth law’ has expanded from medical liability and bioethics into a diverse field encompassing regulation of all aspects of human health and the health care system.”)Google Scholar
See, e.g., Williams, R.A. Jr., “Taking Rights Aggressively: The Perils and Promise of Critical Legal Theory for Peoples of Color,” Law & Inequality 5, no. 1 (1987): 103-134 (describing critical legal theory). Although this essay focuses specifically on feminist legal theory (including intersectional and critical race feminism), we note that critical race theory offers another set of perspectives that health law scholars have used to propose solutions to health problems and inequities. For example, Derrick Bell, a pioneer in critical race theory, asserted that “the interest of blacks in achieving racial equality will be accommodated only when it converges with the interests of whites.” See Bell, D.A. Jr., “Brown v. Board of Education and the Interest-Convergence Dilemma,” Harvard Law Review 93, no. 3 (1980): 518-533, at 523. This contention is the basis of interest-convergence theory and has been applied to health law issues. See Matthew, D.B., Just Medicine: A Cure for Racial Inequality in American Health Care (New York: New York University Press, 2015): at 28; see also Crossley, M., “Black Health Matters: Disparities, Community Health, and Interest Convergence,” Michigan Journal of Race and Law 22, no. 1 (2016): 53-100, at 59-60.Google Scholar
There is much complexity in the term woman and how it is used. When we use the term woman throughout the article, this includes transgender men and others who may identify as a woman. See Strangio, C., “Can Reproductive Trans Bodies Exist?” City University of New York Law Review 19, no. 1 (2016): 223-245, at 230-232.Google Scholar
“The woman question asks about the gender implications of a social practice or rule: have women been left out of consideration? If so, in what way; how might that omission be corrected? What difference would it make to do so? In law, asking the woman question means examining how the law fails to consider the experiences and values that seem more typical of women than of men, for whatever reason, or how existing legal standards and concepts might disadvantage women. The question assumes that some features of the law may be not only nonneutral in a general sense, but also ‘male’ in a specific sense. The purpose of the woman question is to expose those features and how they operate, and to suggest how they might be corrected.” Bartlett, K.T., “Feminist Legal Methods,” Harvard Law Review 103, no. 4 (1990): 829-888, at 837.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
West, R., “Introduction to Research Handbook on Feminist Jurisprudence” in West, R. and Bowman, C.G., eds., Research Handbook on Feminist Jurisprudence (Northhampton, MA: Edward Elgar, 2019): at 1.Google Scholar
Fineman, M.A., “Vulnerability and Inevitable Inequality,” Oslo Law Review 4, no. 3 (2017): 133-149, at 148; see also Fineman, M.A., “The Limits of Equality: Vulnerability and Inevitable Inequality,” in West, R. and Bowman, C.G., eds., Research Handbook on Feminist Jurisprudence (Northhampton, MA: Edward Elgar, 2019): 73-90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Little, M.O., “Why a Feminist Approach to Bioethics?” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 6, no. 1 (1996): 1-18, at 3 (“Under androcentrism … we tend to anchor man as the reference point and view woman's nature as a departure from his.”)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nedelsky, J., Law's Relations: A Relational Theory of Self, Autonomy, and Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011): at 5.Google Scholar
Kimberlé Crenshaw first introduced the term intersectionality to describe “how the experiences of women of color are frequently the product of intersecting patterns of racism and sexism, and how these experiences tend not to be represented within the discourses of either feminism or antiracism. Because of their intersectional identity as both women and of color within discourses that are shaped to respond to one or the other, women of color are marginalized within both.” Crenshaw, K., “Mapping the Margins: Intersectionality, Identity Politics, and Violence Against Women of Color,” Stanford Law Review 43, no. 6 (1991): 1241-1299, at 1243-1244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See, e.g., Ross, L., “What Is Reproductive Justice?” in Pro-Choice Public Education Project and Sister Song Women of Color Reproductive Justice Collective, Reproductive Justice Briefing Book: A Primer on Reproductive Justice and Social Change, at 4-5, available at <https://www.protectchoice.org/downloads/Reproductive%20Justice%20Briefing%20Book.pdf> (last visited November 22, 2019).+(last+visited+November+22,+2019).>Google Scholar
See, e.g., Dinner, D., “The Costs of Reproduction, History and the Legal Construction of Sex Equality,” Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review 46 (2011): 415-495, 457 (describing feminist advocates' efforts to “redefine childrearing as a collective, public responsibility rather than a private responsibility of individual women”); Cohen, R., “Feminist Thought and Corporate Law: It's Time to Find Our Way Up from the Bottom (Line),” American University Journal of Gender and the Law 2 (1994): 1-36, at 20-22 (characterizing feminist theory as seeking “elimination of the duality of reason and emotion, public and private, political and personal,” which “have been the justification for the devaluation of the traditional female domain, and the equation of power with the traditional male domain” and arguing that feminist theory “can contribute new perspectives to [debates in corporate law] by “offer[ing] a perspective that approaches the issue of responsibility from a unitary, rather than a fragmented, perspective.”).Google Scholar
See Dinner, D., “Strange Bedfellows at Work: Neomaternalism in the Making of Sex Discrimination Law,” Washington University Law Review 91 (2014): 453-530, 458 (describing Fine-man's vulnerability analysis as “theorizing the privatization of dependency”).Google Scholar
See Fineman, supra note 12.Google Scholar
Kissick, W., Medicine's Dilemmas: Infinite Needs Versus Finite Resources (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994), at 150 (describing the iron triangle of health care: cost, quality, and access); Furrow, B. et al., eds., Health Law: Cases, Materials, and Problems, 8th ed. (Saint Paul: West, 2018), at 495 (“[H] ealth care systems are frequently evaluated on their ability to provide equitable access to quality health care at a reasonable price for the population. In the American health care system, we also highly prioritize the ability to have choice …?Google Scholar
For a similar argument from a British health law scholar, see O'Donovan, K., “Is the Patient Position Inevitably Female?” Foreword to Feminist Perspectives on Health Care Law, in Sheldon, S. and Thomson, M., eds. (London: Cavendish Publishing Ltd., 1998): at vii (arguing that “[f]eminist jurisprudence can “alter[] the way in which [health care law] is researched, taught and understood” in ways that are “not confined to the ‘reproductive ghetto,’ that is to issues of gender and physical differences, of particular female conditions, of uteri and ovaries.”).Google Scholar
Mutcherson, K., “Fetal Rights in the Trump Era,” Texas Law Review 95, no. 6 (2017): 214-220, at 219 (“Abortion foes will continue to use all tools at their disposal to make it ever more difficult — and, in some cases, impossible — for women to safely end their pregnancies, resulting in the births of more children born to reluctant or unwilling mothers or more women injuring themselves through attempts to self-induce abortions.”)Google Scholar
Chemerinsky, E. and Goodwin, M., “Abortion: A Woman's Private Choice,” Texas Law Review 95, no. 6 (2017): 1189-1247, at 1245 (“Many states have adopted various types of laws requiring that women be informed of the characteristics of the fetus at the time of abortion.”); Manian, M., “Irrational Woman: Informed Consent and Abortion Regret,” Duke Journal of Gender Law and Policy 16, no. 2 (2009): 223-292, at 226 (noting the Supreme Court's culmination of “[a] growing disrespect for women's decision-making capabilities…”).Google Scholar
Kukura, E., “Obstetric Violence,” Georgetown Law Review 106, no. 3 (2018): 721-801.Google Scholar
See Sawicki, N., “The Abortion Informed Consent Debate: More Light, Less Heat,” Cornell Journal of Law and Public Policy 21, no. 1 (2011): 1-38, at 37 (“A nuanced view of informed consent doctrine will be helpful in resolving the heated debate surrounding abortion disclosure statutes.”); see also Hill, B.J., “Reproductive Rights as Health Care Rights,” Columbia Journal of Gender and Law 18, no. 2 (2009): 501-549, at 502-503 (“If abortion is placed in the framework of health care, the right to access abortion may then be considered to be an aspect of the right to health. This right to health, moreover, should be conceived as a negative right, not as a positive right … A negative right to health could … be understood as a right against government interference in health care access and medical decision making, rather than a right to government-provided medical services.); see also Lindgren, Y., “The Rhetoric of Choice: Restoring Healthcare to the Abortion Right,” Hastings Law Journal 64, no. 5 (2013): 385-422, at 391-392 (“Reclaiming abortion as a right of both healthcare and choice offers the potential for reclaiming the right within the larger framework of reproductive justice by granting all pregnant women, women who carry to term as well as women who choose to terminate their pregnancies, the right to exercise bodily autonomy and access healthcare in every aspect of their reproductive lives.”)Google Scholar
See Ross, supra note 16, at 4-5.Google Scholar
Nedelsky, J., Law's Relations: A Relational Theory of Self, Autonomy, and Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011): at 5; Mackenzie, C. and Stoljar, N., eds., Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000): at 5; Llewellyn, J. and Downie, J., eds., in Being Relational: Reflections on Relational Theory and Health Law (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 2011): at 4. (“We can see the ways in which being in relationship is integral to self-understanding and to interactions with others at individual, collective, and even institutional levels.”)Google Scholar
See Nedelsky, supra note 14, at 5 (“Generally, the rights the relational self is entitled to will need to be relational rather than individualistic conceptions. Both law and rights will then be understood in terms of the relations they structure-and how those relations can structure core values, such as autonomy.”)Google Scholar
Nedelsky, J., “Reconceiving Autonomy: Sources, Thoughts, and Possibilities,” Yale Journal Law and Feminism 1, no. 1 (1989): 7-36.Google Scholar
Braudo-Bahat, Y., “Towards A Relational Conceptualization of the Right to Personal Autonomy,” American University Journal of Gender, Society Policy, and Law 25, no. 2 (2017): 111-154, at 129-130 (“Contrary to the liberal, individualistic conception of autonomy, the relational conception highlights the relational nature of persons, and the development of their identity and autonomy through social connections and relationships with others. Being a part of relationships and social networks makes all persons interdependent; however, interdependence does not infringe their autonomy, but is rather simply an inherent part of their personhood.”)Google Scholar
Laufer-Ukeles, P., “Reproductive Choices and Informed Consent: Fetal Interests, Women's Identity, and Relational Autonomy,” American Journal Law & Medicine 37, no. 4 (2011): 567-623, at 568-569 (“Based on the uniquely intertwined relationship between women and fetuses during gestation, and the importance of reproduction to women's identity, the individualistic, narrow informed consent doctrine is unsuited to support women's autonomy in the context of reproductive choices.”)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Id., at 573.Google Scholar
Id., at 571 (“Based on the uniquely intertwined relationship between women and fetuses during gestation, and the importance of reproduction to women's identity, the individualistic, narrow informed consent doctrine is unsuited to support women's autonomy in the context of reproductive choices.”)Google Scholar
See Suter, S.M., “The ‘Repugnance’ Lens of Gonzales v. Car-hart and Other Theories of Reproductive Rights: Evaluating Advanced Reproductive Technologies,” George Washington Law Review 76, no. 6 (2008): 1514-1598, at 1593 (“… a richer notion of self-definition (and the autonomy or decisional privacy interests that derive from this conception) requires us to think of the self in relation to family, friends, and community.”); see also Mohapatra, S., “Using Egg Freezing to Extend the Biological Clock: Fertility Insurance or False Hope?” Harvard Law and Policy Review, 8, no. 2 (2014): 381-411, at 409 (“When a woman chooses to freeze her eggs, the choice may not be truly autonomous if she is doing it because of constraints she faces at work, with family life, or with childcare. If having a child earlier means that she will take a step back in her career or not have enough money for child care due to a lack of support at home and lack of affordable child care options, then a woman may not be exercising autonomy by delaying motherhood. Instead, she may feel like this is choosing the best of many bad options.”)Google Scholar
Llewellyn, J., “A Healthy Conception of Rights? Thinking Relationally about Rights in a Health Care Context,” in Downie, J. and Gibson, E., eds., Health Law At The Supreme Court of Canada (Toronto: Irwin Law Inc., 2007): at 57.Google Scholar
Wright, M.S., “End of Life and Autonomy: The Case for Relational Nudges in End-of-Life Decision-Making Law and Policy,” Maryland Law Review 77, no. 4 (2018): 1061-1141, at 1093-1094 (“Coupled with the reality that most people never make decisions without the participation of others, feminist philosophers, bioethicists, and critical disability scholars have thus advanced the concept of “relational autonomy.” Importantly, relational autonomy is autonomy, just conceptualized in a way that accords with social reality.”) Internal quotations omitted; Igel, L.H. and Lerner, B.H., “Moving Past Individual and ‘Pure’ Autonomy: The Rise of Family-Centered Patient Care,” American Medical Association Journal of Ethics 18, no.1 (2016): 56-62, at 58; Ho, A., “Relational Autonomy or Undue Pressure? Family's Role in Medical Decision-Making,” Scandinavian Journal of Caring Sciences 22, no. 1 (2008): 128-135, at 131 (“… our self is constituted to an important degree by relations with and responsibilities towards our intimates, and these relations and the welfare of our loved ones may be more significant than the interests of any individual self in isolation.”)Google Scholar
Downie, J. and Lllewellyn, J., “Relational Theory and Health Law and Policy,” Health Law Journal 193, Special Edition (2008): 193-210, at 197.Google Scholar
Id., at 198.Google Scholar
See Wright, supra note 36, at 1139.Google Scholar
Mantel, J., “An Unintended Consequence of Payment Reforms: Providers Avoiding Nonadherent Patients,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 46, no. 4 (2018): 931-934, at 933 (“Nonadherent patients, with their poorer health outcomes and higher costs, threaten providers' financial success under new payment models that reward quality improvements and reduced health costs. Providers can escape this predicament by firing or otherwise refusing to treat nonadherent patients, actions permitted under current legal standards and the medical profession's ethical guidelines.”)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leonard, M. et al., Achieving Safe and Reliable Healthcare: Strategies and Solutions (Chicago: Health Administration Press, 2004): at 3.Google Scholar
Petersen, E.E., et al., “Vital Signs: Pregnancy-Related Deaths, United States, 2011–2015, and Strategies for Prevention, 13 States, 2013–2017,” Morbidity and Mortality Weekly Report 68, no. 18 (2019): 423-429.Google Scholar
Gallo, K. and Smith, L., “Meeting Tomorrow's Healthcare Needs: Teamwork Trumps Autonomy,” Nursing Education Perspectives 31, no. 4 (2010): 207 at 207.Google Scholar
Ikemoto, L.C., “In the Shadow of Race: Women of Color in Health Disparities Policy,” University of California Davis Law Review 39, no. 3 (2006): 1023-1060, at 1055; see also, Vanderstar, E.S., “Workplace Bullying in the Healthcare Professions,” Employee Rights and Employment Policy Journal 8, no. 2 (2004): 455-473, at 460 (“The medical professions can be neatly arranged in a hierarchy resembling a caste system from the most influential and powerful to the least: doctors, physician's assistants, nurse practitioners, registered nurses, licensed practical nurses, technicians, orderlies, transport staff, nurse assistants, housekeeping staff.”); see also, Shannon, G. et al., “Gender Equality In Science, Medicine, And Global Health: Where Are We At And Why Does It Matter?” The Lancet 393, no. 10171 (2019): 560-569, at 562 (“Approximately 75% of the global health workforce is female, yet women disproportionately represent lower cadres of health workers.”)Google Scholar
Smith, L.G. and Anderson, M., “New Directions in American Health Care,” Hofstra Law Review 39, no. 1 (2011): 23-39 at 39 (“Many doctors have clung to the nineteenth century model of status, hierarchy, autonomy, and privilege that has served them, but not always their patients, so well for so long.”) These hierarchies often are exacerbated by racial inequalities in the health care workforce and between physicians and patients. See Bridges, K. M., Reproducing Race: An Ethnography of Pregnancy as a Site of Racialization (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2011) (“There was a fascinating racially significant chain of command in the clinic: white persons, with the most power and prestige in the clinic sat at the top of the hierarchy with their non-white assistants populating the ranks below them. Furthermore the racial dynamic within the clinic made even more fascinating by the racial composition of the patients served there — the large majority were racial minorities. This was a predominantly white group of providers practicing medicine upon a largely disempowered disenfranchised, marginalized and importantly non-white group of patients.”)Google Scholar
Trubek, L.G. and Das, M., “Achieving Equality: Healthcare Governance in Transition,” American Journal of Law & Medicine 29, no. 2 (2003): 395-430, at 415 (“By working in a non-hierarchical fashion and deeming all members of the team to be “clinical professionals,” these new teams of nurses, physician assistants, community outreach workers, quality managers and physicians create better outcomes by working together rather than individually.”)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabinovich-Einy, O., “Beyond IDR: Resolving Hospital Disputes and Healing Ailing Organizations Through ITR,” Saint John's Law Review 81, no. 1 (2007): 173-196, at 183.Google Scholar
Glen, E.N., “From Servitude to Service Work: Historical Continuities in the Racial Division of Paid Reproductive Labor,” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 18, no. 1 (1992): 1-43, at 23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, J.E., “Cultural Collisions and the Limits of the affordable Care Act,” Journal of Gender Social Policy & the Law 22, no. 2 (2014): 387-449, at 446.Google Scholar
Logghe, H. et al., “#ILookLikeASurgeon: Embracing Diversity to Improve Patient Outcomes,” British Medical Journal 359, no. 8125 (2017): j4653, at j4653 (“Participants using this hashtag have acknowledged both the need to change the image of surgeons, and that there must be no singular image — that the appearance, motivations, and behaviours of surgeons are as varied as humanity.”)Google Scholar
Shannon, G. et al., “Gender Equality in Science, Medicine, and Global Health: Where Are We At And Why Does It Matter?” The Lancet, 393, no. 10171 (2019): 560-569, at 566.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Id., at 566 (“A study investigating mortality of female patients with acute myocardial infarction found higher mortality in women treated by male doctors than in those treated by female doctors. The effect was attenuated if male doctors had higher exposure to female patients and physician colleagues.”)Google Scholar
Ikemoto, L.C., “Racial Disparities in Health Care and Cultural Competency,” St. Louis University Law Journal 48, no. 3 (2003): 75-131, at 82; see also, Law, S.A., “A Consumer Perspective on Medical Malpractice, Law and Contemporary Problems,” Law and Contemporary Problems 49, no. 2 (1986): 305-326, at 314 (“Doctors, nurses, and other health care workers…are divided by hierarchical organizational structures. It is difficult to develop relationships of mutual respect, sharing, and criticism between physicians who are generally white, male, and affluent, and the people, often nonwhite women, who provide most ‘hands-on’ patient care in the hospital.”)Google Scholar
See Davies, K., “The Body and Doing Gender: The Relations between Doctors and Nurses in Hospital Work,” Sociology of Health & Illness 25, no. 7 (2003): 720-742; West, C., “When the Doctor Is a “Lady”: Power, Status and Gender in Physician-Patient Encounters,” Symbolic Interaction 7, no. 1 (1984): 87-106; Cassell, J., “Doing Gender, Doing Surgery: Women Surgeons in a Man's Profession,” Human Organization 56, no. 1 (1997): 47-52; Tabassum, N. and Chiesi, A., “Doing and Undoing Gender in the Hospital Workplace,” Journal of Interdisciplinary Feminist Thought 10, no. 1 (2017): 1-23, at 15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See supra note 54 (Tabassum and Chiesi), at 10.Google Scholar
Crossley, M., “Infected Judgment: Legal Responses to Physician Bias,” Villanova Law Review 48, no. 1 (2017): 195-324, at 302-303 (“Published studies suggest that bias based on a clinically irrelevant characteristic of a patient at times influences some physicians' medical judgments. These biased medical decisions can have adverse impacts on the particular patient who is the victim of the biased decision, as well as on the public's health more broadly.”)Google Scholar
Hoope-Bender, P.T., et al., “Improvement of Maternal and Newborn Health through Midwifery,” The Lancet 384, no. 9949 (2014): 1226-1235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Declercq, E. R. et al., “Serving Women in Need: Nurse-Midwifery Practice in the United States,” Journal of Midwifery & Women's Health 46, no. 1 (2011): 11-16, at 13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suarez, S.H., “Midwifery Is Not the Practice of Medicine,” Yale Journal of Law & Feminism 5, no. 2 (1992): 315-364, at 315.Google Scholar
Greenwood, B.N., Carnahan, S., and Wang, L., “Patient-Physician Gender Concordance and Increased Mortality among Female Heart Attack Patients,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Science 115, no. 34 (2018): 8569-8574.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pateman, C., “Feminist Critiques of the Public/Private Dichotomy,” in Benn, S.I. and Gaus, G.F., eds., Public and Private in Social Life 281-303, at 281 (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1983) (“The dichotomy between the private and the public is central to almost two centuries of feminist writing and political struggle; it is, ultimately, what the feminist movement is about.”); Gavison, R., “Feminism and the Public/Private Distinction,” Stanford Law Review 45, no. 1 (1992): 1-45.Google Scholar
Prokhovnik, R., “Public and Private Citizenship: From Gender Invisibility to Feminist Inclusiveness,” Feminist Review 60, no. 3 (1998): 84-104, at 87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanisch, C., “The Personal Is Political,” in Firestone, S., ed., Notes From the Second Year: Women's Liberation (1970): at 76-78, available at <https://repository.duke.edu/dc/wlmpc/wlmms01039> (last visited November 22, 2019); cited in Cohen, R. and O'Byrne, S., “‘Can You Hear me Now…Good!’ Feminism(s), the Public/Private Divide, and Citizens United v. FEC,” UCLA Women's Law Journal 20, no. 1 (2013): 39-70.Google Scholar
See Fineman, supra note 12.Google Scholar
Stone, D., “The Struggle for the Soul of Health Insurance,” Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law 18, no. 2 (1993): 287-317, at 289 (contrasted the principle of mutual aid, whereby “sickness is widely accepted as a condition that should trigger mutual aid,” and the principle of actuarial fairness, which holds that “each person should pay for his own risk.”); Gluck, A. and Huberfeld, N., “What Is Federalism in Health Care For?” Stanford Law Review 70, no. 6 (2018): 1689-1803, at 1698 (although the ACA “pushed the needle toward solidarity by enacting policies aimed at universal coverage,” health law “remains caught in centuries-old, unresolved tension between the so-called ‘social solidarity’ model … and the ‘individual responsibility’ model.”); E. McCuskey, supra note 7, at 310 (“Health reform movements of late suffer from that tension, but tilt definitively toward social solidarity and recognition of social determinants.”)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See McCuskey, supra note 7, at 315.Google Scholar
Waysdorf, S.L., “Fighting for Their Lives: Women, Poverty, and the Historical Role of United States Law in Shaping Access to Women's Health Care,” Kentucky Law Journal 84, no. 4 (1996): 745-826.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Huberfeld, N. and Roberts, J.L., “Health Care and the Myth of Self-Reliance,” Boston College Law Review 57, no. 1 (2016): 1-60, at 3 (“The ACA reversed [the] norm [of exclusion in health care], espousing a principle of inclusion or “universality” by facilitating universal health insurance coverage.”); cf. Majette, G.R., “Global Health Law Norms and the PPACA Framework to Eliminate Health Disparities,” Howard Law Journal 55, no. 3 (2012): 887-936, at 892. (“[The ACA] constitutes framework legislation that complies with global health law norms protecting a right to health in its approach to the reduction of health care disparities for racial and ethnic minorities in the United States.”)Google Scholar
See McCuskey, supra note 7, at 314.Google Scholar
Franke-Ruta, G., “Why Is Maternity Care Such an Issue for Obamacare Opponents?” The Atlantic, November 22, 2013, available at <https://www.theatlantic.com/politics/archive/2013/11/why-is-maternity-care-such-an-issue-forobamacare-opponents/281396/> (last visited November 22, 2019).+(last+visited+November+22,+2019).>Google Scholar
See, e.g., MacDougall, V.L., “Medical Gender Bias and Managed Care,” Oklahoma City University Law Review 27, no. 3 (2002): 781-910; Theodos, T. F., “The Patient's Bill of Rights: Women's Rights Under Managed Care and ERISA Preemption,” American Journal of Law & Medicine 26, no. 1 (2000): 89-108; Oberman, M. and Schaps, M., “Women's Health and Managed Care,” Tennessee Law Review 65, no. 2 (1998): 555-583.Google Scholar
See MacDougall, supra note 71.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Fineman, M.A., “The Vulnerable Subject and the Responsive State,” Emory Law Journal 60, no. 2 (2010): 251-275, at 266; Fineman, M.A., “The Vulnerable Subject: Anchoring Equality in the Human Condition,” Yale Journal of Law & Feminism 20, no. 1 (2008): 1-23.Google Scholar
Ahmed, A., “‘Rugged Vaginas’ and ‘Vulnerable Rectums’: The Sexual Identity, Epidemiology, and Law of the Global HIV Epidemic,” Columbia Journal of Gender and Law 26, no. 1 (2013): 1-57, at 49 (“Martha Fineman argues that instead of an identity-based legal reform project we should instead focus on the construction of a new liberal subject based on an appreciation of the human condition in order to effectively displace the rhetoric of personal responsibility, small government, and condemnation of state intervention.”)Google Scholar
Kohn, N.A., “Vulnerability Theory and the Role of Government,” Yale Journal of Law & Feminism 26, no. 1 (2014): 1-27, at 13 (critiquing the application of vulnerability theory in elder care but noting that “vulnerability theory helps us understand why we might favor laws that provide broad-based social support and why we might be concerned about selectively allocating resources based on group identity.”)Google Scholar
See Stephens, S.M., “Freedom from Religion: A Vulnerability Theory Approach to Restricting Conscience Exemptions in Reproductive Healthcare,” Yale Journal of Law & Feminism 29, no. 1 (2017): 93-121, at 106 (“ [T]he healthcare industry is not regulated in a way that ensures access to healthcare resources that will improve human resiliency. To the contrary, the state of the law actually discourages access to critical reproductive care that can improve not only individual health outcomes but broader social and economic outcomes for patients, their families, and, in turn, their wider communities.”)Google Scholar
Fineman, M.A., “Vulnerability and Inevitable Inequality,” Oslo Law Review 4, no. 3 (2017): 133-149; see also, Fineman, supra note 11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Huberfeld and Roberts, supra note 68, at 1.Google Scholar
Lawrence, M.B., “Against the Safety Net,” Florida Law Review 72, no. 1 (forthcoming 2020).Google Scholar
Hoffman, A. K., “Reimagining the Risk of Long-Term Care,” Yale Journal of Health Policy, Law & Ethics 16, no. 2 (2016): 239-315.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Bobinski, M., “Women and HIV: A Gender-Based Analysis of a Disease and its Legal Regulation,” Texas Journal of Women and the Law 3, no. 1 (1994): 7-56; Ahmed, A., “Feminism, Power, and Sex Work in the Context of HIV/AIDS: Consequences for Women's Health,” Harvard Journal of Law & Gender 34, no. 1 (2011): 225-258.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Koo, K.H. and Maguen, S., “Military Sexual Trauma and Mental Health Diagnoses in Female Veterans Returning from Afghanistan and Iraq: Barriers and Facilitators to Veterans affairs Care,” Hastings Women's Law Journal 25, no. 1 (2014): 27-38.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Arnold, K.D., “The Right to Live: A Constitutional Argument for Mandatory Preventative Health Care for Female Prisoners,” William and Mary Journal of Women and the Law 10, no. 2 (2004): 343-366; Weatherhead, K., “Cruel But Not Unusual Punishment: The Failure to Provide Adequate Medical Treatment to Female Prisoners in the United States,” Health Matrix: Journal of Law-Medicine 13, no. 2 (2003): 429-472; Chandler, C., “Death and Dying in America: The Prison Industrial Complex's Impact on Women's Health,” Berkeley Women's Law Journal 18, no. 1 (2003): 40-60.Google Scholar
Makhlouf, M.D., “Health Justice for Immigrants,” University of Pennsylvania Journal of Law and Public affairs 4, no. 2 (2019): 235-311.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Daniels, N., “Treatment and Prevention: What Do We Owe Each Other?” in Prevention vs. Treatment: What's the Right Balance? (Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 2011): 176-193, at 176 (“I … argue that we have a robust social obligation to protect and promote health and that this obligation means we owe each other a reasonable array of both preventive and curative interventions.”)Google Scholar
Rebouché, R., “Reproducing Rights: The Intersection of Reproductive Justice and Human Rights,” University of California Irvine Law Review 7, no. 3 (2017): 579-610, at 593; Blake, V., “It's an ART not a Science: State-Mandated Insurance Coverage of Assisted Reproductive Technologies and Legal Implications for Gay and Unmarried Persons,” Minnesota Journal of Law, Science, and Technology 12, no. 2 (2011): 651-713, at 678; Mohapatra, S., “Politically Correct Eugenics,” Florida International University Law Review 12, no. 1 (2016): 51-80 (applying a reproductive justice lens to issues related to reproductive technologies such as CRISPR and suggesting cost and access to such technologies may exacerbate disparities); Mohapatra, S., “Fertility Preservation for Medical Reasons and Reproductive Justice,” Harvard Journal of Racial and Ethnic Justice 30 (2014): 601-633 (applying a reproductive justice lens to fertility preservation for cancer patients and arguing for the necessity for insurance coverage for such patients).Google Scholar
Tovino, S.A., “Scientific Understandings of Postpartum Illness: Improving Health Law and Policy?” Harvard Journal of Law & Gender 33, no. 1 (2010): 99-173.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Faloon, K. and Rosoff, P.M., “Who Pays? Mandated Insurance Coverage for Assisted Reproductive Technology,” American Medical Association Journal of Ethics 16, no. 1 (2014): 63-69 (surveying existing literature debating whether infertility treatments should be financed collectively through private insurance mandates and public programs).Google Scholar
See Daniels, supra note 86, at 176.Google Scholar
Id., at 177.Google Scholar
See Wiley, L., “The Struggle for the Soul of Public Health,” Journal of Health Politics, Policy, & Law 41, no. 6 (2016): 1147-1160, at 1149 (“The powerful resonance of “personal responsibility” indicates deep-seeded antagonism to understanding health as socially determined, to acting collectively in response to health threats, and to communitarian rationales for doing so. When health is viewed primarily as an individual, personal matter, the realm that is properly designated for ‘public’ concern is naturally understood to be narrowly defined.”)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See, e.g., Winkler, I.T. and Roaf, V., “Taking the Bloody Linen Out of the Closet: Menstrual Hygiene as a Priority for Achieving Gender Equality,” Cardozo Journal of Law & Gender 21, no. 1 (2014): 1-37.Google Scholar
Cf. Pope, T.M., “The Slow Transition of U.S. Law Toward a Greater Emphasis on Prevention,” in Faust, H.S. and Menzel, P.T., eds., Prevention vs. Treatment: What's the Right Balance? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011): 219-244.Google Scholar
Wiley, supra note 92.Google Scholar
Cf. Rogers, W.A., “Feminism and Public Health Ethics,” Journal of Medical Ethics 32, no. 6 (2006): 351-354, at 351 (“[Some public health activities raise] significant questions about autonomy, paternalism, and the regulation of bodies with potentially ‘dangerous’ features (breasts, cervixes, pregnant uteruses, adipose tissue) … [M]any of the preventive aspects of public health[, which are subject to paternalistic intervention] — for example, diet, personal hygiene, or childhood exercise — are activities that are traditionally mediated through the actions of women as family carers and custodians of health and wellbeing.”); Parmet, W.E., “Beyond Privacy: A Population Approach to Reproductive Rights,” in Culhane, J.G., ed., Reconsidering Law and Policy Debates: A Public Health Perspective (Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press, 2010): at 15-39 (exploring how each side in the reproductive rights debate has employed public health arguments and the impact of those arguments on the courts' recognition of reproductive rights); Burris, S., “Law and the Social Risk of Health Care: Lessons from HIV Testing,” Albany Law Review 61, no. 3 (1997): 831-896, at 835-836 (arguing for the application of existing disability, privacy, confidentiality, and informed consent laws — as well as the adoption of new legal frameworks specific to HIV/AIDS — “to protect people with HIV from discrimination … and … [to] protect medical privacy and limit HIV testing in the absence of informed consent.”).Google Scholar
See Rogers, supra note 89, at 351 (“A feminist approach to health inequities leads us to examine the connections between disadvantage and health, and the distribution of power in the process of public health, using gender as an analytic category.”)Google Scholar
See, e.g., Flood, C. M. and Gross, A., eds., The Right to Health at the Public/Private Divide: A Global Comparative Study (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 2014): at 1 (“Does a right to health care serve to advance greater equity or does it in fact advance the opposite result? Does the recognition of a right to health care help sustain public values (like equality) in systems that are undergoing privatization? Or, to the contrary, does a focus on rights-based norms foster individualism and exacerbate inequalities brought about by privatization? … How do courts balance the rights of an individual against collective needs in the distribution of health care?”)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Williams, supra note 8, at 129-130.Google Scholar
See West, supra note 11, at 1.Google Scholar