Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T08:17:04.452Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Solid Organ Donation Between Strangers

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

In August 2000, Arthur Matas and his colleagues de scribed a protocol in which their institution began to accept as potential donors, individuals who came to the University of Minnesota hospital offering to donate a kidney to any patient on the waiting list. Matas and his colleagues refer to these donors as nondirected donors by which is meant that the donors are altruistic and that they give their organs to an unspecified pool of recipients with whom they have no emotional relationship. This paper represents an ethical and policy critique of the nondirected donation protocol that was implemented at the University of Minnesota in August 1999. Specifically, I address the ethical questions: Whether altruistic living solid organ donations by strangers (nondirected donations) should be permitted? And if so, What are appropriate ethical guidelines for such donations?

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2002

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Matas, A.J. et al. , “Nondirected Donation of Kidneys from Living Donors,” N. Engl. J. Med., 343, (2000): 433–36.Google Scholar
Lee, H.K., “Uncle Donates Kidney In Teen's Third Transplant; Inmate Father's Attempt to Save Daughter Failed,” The San Francisco Chronicle, April 8, 1999,): at A15.Google Scholar
Galashan, S., “Baby Camilo Departs for New York: While Liver Donors Wait in Canada for the Call, Surgeons are to Assess Boy's Condition,” Vancouver Sun, March 21, 2001,): at B1.Google Scholar
Steinkohl, V.S., “Nach der Nierenentnahme Spender Jochem Hoyer will Anst abbauen,” Sueddeutscher Zeitung, July 27, 1996 at section: Muenchen.Google Scholar
Grady, D., “The New Organ Donors are Living Strangers,” The New York Times, September 20, 1999,): at A1.Google Scholar
Matas, et al. , supra note 1.Google Scholar
Id. at 434.Google Scholar
Joel Feinberg defines other-regarding interests as interests which directly promote the well-being of another for the sake of the other. This contrasts with self-regarding interests in which the concern is with either one's own well-being, or the well-being of others to the extent that they promote one's own well-being See Feinberg, J., Harm to Others. Volume 1: The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984): at 74-75.Google Scholar
Elliott, C., “Doing Harm: Living Organ Donors, Clinical Research and the Tenth Man,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 21 (1995): 9196, at 95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See, for example, Simmons, R.G. Klein, S.D. Simmons, R.L., Gift of Life: The Social and Psychological Impact of Organ Transplantation (New York: Wiley, 1977): at 176–87;.Google Scholar
Johnson, E.M. et al. , “Long Term Follow-up of Living Kidney Donors: Quality of Life After Donation,” Transplantation, 67, (1999): 717–21.Google Scholar
See, for example, Wendler, D. Dickert, N, “The Consent Process for Cadaveric Organ Procurement: How Does It Work? How Can It Be Improved?” JAMA 285, (2001): 329–33; an Capron, A.M., “Reexamining Organ Transplantation,” JAMA 285, (2001): 334–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elliott, , supra note 12, at 95.Google Scholar
Currently there is no consensus as to what constitutes “significant” risk. Kasiske and Bia document the wide variability of exclusion criteria for living kidney donors.Google Scholar
See Kasiske, B.L. Bia, M.J., “The Evaluation and Selection of Living Kidney Donors,” American Journal of Kidney Diseases, 26 (1995): 387–98, at 394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
In June 2000, over one hundred representatives of the transplant community (physicians, nurses, ethicists, psychologists, lawyers, scientists, social workers, transplant recipients, and living donors) convened for a workshop on living solid organ donors. They issued a report in JAMA in December 2000.Google Scholar
The report outlines areas of consensus and areas of controversy. It does not provide specific criteria for the exclusion or inclusion of live donors but describes what factors need to be considered for the donor to be medically and psychologically suitable. It also refers to other documents that provide some specific guidelines for particular organs. See The Authors for the Live Organ Donor Consensus Group, “Consensus Statement on the Live Organ Donor,” JAMA 284 (2000): 2919–26.Google Scholar
Spital, A. Spital, M., “Living Kidney Donation: Attitudes Outside the Transplant Center,” Archives of Internal Medicine 148, (1988): 1077–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Press Release, National Kidney Foundation (June 22, 2000), available at <http://www.kidney.org/general/news/strangers.cfm> (last visited October 16, 2002).+(last+visited+October+16,+2002).>Google Scholar
Matas, et al. , supra note 1, at 434.Google Scholar
The United Network for Organ Sharing (UNOS) is a non-profit organization that maintains the nation's organ transplant waiting list under federal contract with the Health Resources and Services Administration of the U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. See <http://www.unos.org/frame_default.asp> for general information about UNOS. It has performed this role since 1986. UNOS has an ethics committee comprised of both ethicists and physicians. This committee has examined a variety of ethical and policy issues including the question of how priority should be given on the transplant wait list, whether alcoholics should be listed for liver transplantation, and if so, whether or not they should be given lower priority. Some of these discussions are described by Robert Veatch, a medical ethicist who has served three terms on the UNOS ethics committee. for general information about UNOS. It has performed this role since 1986. UNOS has an ethics committee comprised of both ethicists and physicians. This committee has examined a variety of ethical and policy issues including the question of how priority should be given on the transplant wait list, whether alcoholics should be listed for liver transplantation, and if so, whether or not they should be given lower priority. Some of these discussions are described by Robert Veatch, a medical ethicist who has served three terms on the UNOS ethics committee.' href=https://scholar.google.com/scholar?q=The+United+Network+for+Organ+Sharing+(UNOS)+is+a+non-profit+organization+that+maintains+the+nation's+organ+transplant+waiting+list+under+federal+contract+with+the+Health+Resources+and+Services+Administration+of+the+U.S.+Department+of+Health+and+Human+Services.+See++for+general+information+about+UNOS.+It+has+performed+this+role+since+1986.+UNOS+has+an+ethics+committee+comprised+of+both+ethicists+and+physicians.+This+committee+has+examined+a+variety+of+ethical+and+policy+issues+including+the+question+of+how+priority+should+be+given+on+the+transplant+wait+list,+whether+alcoholics+should+be+listed+for+liver+transplantation,+and+if+so,+whether+or+not+they+should+be+given+lower+priority.+Some+of+these+discussions+are+described+by+Robert+Veatch,+a+medical+ethicist+who+has+served+three+terms+on+the+UNOS+ethics+committee.>Google Scholar
See Veatch, R.M., Transplantation Ethics (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2000).Google Scholar
For a full discussion of directed donations, see id. at 303–04, and 388–411.Google Scholar
Matas, et al. , supra note 1, at 435.Google Scholar
Gridelli, B. Remuzz, G., “Strategies for Making More Organs Available for Transplantation.” N. Engl. J. Med., 343 (2000): 404–10, at 407.Google Scholar
Levinsky, N.G., “Organ Donation by Unrelated Donors,” N. Engl. J. Med., 343 (2000): 430–32 at 431.Google Scholar
Matas, et al. , supra note 1, at 436.Google Scholar
See text, infra note 31–33.Google Scholar
This may or may not be the case. As the case unfolded, Jerry Ewen, Camilo's father admitted to knowing the donor, and in fact, it was reported that she had been in the process of a workup in Canada when “she became unhappy with the ‘grueling and undermining interrogation that felt dehumanizing and made her feel like a criminal,’ says the family's statement.”Google Scholar
See The Canadian Press, “Father Admitted Lying About Son's Living Organ Donor: Ailing Infant's Liver Transplant Called a Success,” The Ottawa Citizen, April 7, 2001, at A3Google Scholar
citing the family's statement. This created much controversy because it meant that the transplant could have been performed in Canada and paid for by the Canadian health system. Camilo's parents, instead, sought altruistic donations, and had collected about $240,000. The Variety Club of British Columbia had collected $140,000. It offered to return all the money it raised to help the family when these facts came to light. See Galashan, S., “Public Funeral Planned for Baby Camilo: Six-Month-Old Died After U.S. Transplant Surgery,” The Vancouver Sun, April 10, 2001,): at A1.Google Scholar
Elliott, , supra note 12, at 95.Google Scholar
Mazzolini, J., “Guidelines Sought for Taking Organs from Patients Not Declared Brain-Dead.” The Plain Dealer (Cleveland), Dec. 20, 1997, at 1A.Google Scholar
Matas, et al. , supra note 1 at 433.Google Scholar
Ross, L.F. et al. , “Should All Living Donors Be Treated Equally?,” Transplantation, 74 (2002): 418–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Id. at 420. This issue is addressed in further detail i Glannon, W. Ross, L.F., “Do Genetic Relationships Create Moral Obligations in Transplantation?,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 11 (2002): 153–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Of note, these arguments also support Matas et al.'s decision to restrict nondirected donations to kidneys given the greater risks of morbidity and mortality of other live organ donations. See text, supra notes 26–28.Google Scholar
Matas, et al. , supra note 1, at 433.Google Scholar
Id. at 435.Google Scholar
See, for example, Neuberger, J. et al. , “Assessing Priorities for Allocation of Donor Liver Grafts: Survey of Public and Clinicians,” British Medical Journal, 317 (1998): 172–75; Neuberger, J. Ubel, P.A., “Finding a Place for Public Preferences in Liver Allocation Decisions,” Transplantation, 70 (2000): 1411–13;.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ratcliffe, J., “Public Preferences for the Allocation of Donor Liver Grafts for Transplantation,” Health Economics, 9 (2000): 137–48.Google Scholar
Ubel, P.A., “Transplantation in Alcoholics: Separating Prognosis and Responsibility from Social Biases,” Liver Transplantation and Surgery, 3 (1997): 343–46.Google Scholar
Peters, T.G. et al. , “Organ Donors and Nondonors. An American Dilemma,” Archives of Internal Medicine, 156 (1996): 2419–24.Google Scholar
See Testerman, J., “Should Donors Say Who Gets Organs?” St Petersburg Times, Jan. 9, 1994, at 1A This case described a man who was a member of the Ku Klux Klan and whose family gave permission for organ procurement provided that the recipient was Caucasian. See also Norton, C. Herbert, I., “How a Dead Man Provoked an Ethical Dilemma that has Convulsed the NHS,” The Independent (London), July 8, 1999, at 3, inGoogle Scholar
which the family also requested that the recipient be Caucasian. Both decisions sparked heavy public and professional criticism.Google Scholar
Levinsky, , supra note 24, at 431.Google Scholar
Rapaport, F.T., “The Case for a Living Emotionally Related International Kidney Donor Exchange Registry,” Transplantation Proceedings, vol. 18, no. 3, Supplement 2 (1986): 59.Google Scholar
The actual distribution of organs under UNOS reveals that current policies do not treat organs as a true national resource. Organs are distributed by an algorithm that gives added weight to the local population. While there are some clinical advantages to local versus national distribution because of shorter cold ischemia times, there have been some recent policy recommendations that would encourage a more national approach. In fact, the Clinton administration ordered UNOS to revamp its system so that organs are shared more broadly across city and state lines. Federal guidelines were published in April 1998 (see 63 Fed. Reg. 16296, Rules and Regulations, Department of Health and Human Services, Health Resources and Services Administration, 42 C.F.R. pt. 121, Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network, Part II), but UNOS complained so vigorously that Congress delayed the regulation and asked the Institute of Medicine, an arm of the National Academy of Sciences, to investigate. See Stolberg, S.G., “Organ Transplant Panel Urges a Broad Sharing of Livers,” The New York Times, July 21, 1999,): at A14.Google Scholar
The Institute of Medicine report was published in September 1999 (see Committee on Organ Procurement and Transplantation Policy, Institute of Medicine, Organ Procurement and Transplantation: Assessing Current Policies and the Potential Impact of the DHHS Final Rule (Washington, D.C.: National Academy Press, 1999)). Final rules were published on October 20, 1999 (see 64 Fed. Reg. 56650, Rules and Regulations, Department of Health and Human Services, Health Resources and Services Administration, 42 C.F.R. pt. 121, Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network, Part VI).Google Scholar