Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T08:33:49.662Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Tax the Rich! Tax the Research Participants?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 September 2023

Emily A. Largent*
Affiliation:
UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA, PHILADELPHIA, PA, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Independent Articles: Commentary
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of American Society of Law, Medicine & Ethics

Waltz, David, and Fisher claim that the bioethics literature has been “silent about any tax liability associated with [research] payments.”Reference Waltz, Davis and Fisher1 But there has, at the very least, been a whisper that taxation is one amongst a host of ethical and legal issues that ought to be considered when payment is offered to research participants.Reference Largent, Heffernan, Joffe and Lynch2 Offers of payment can serve various functions — to reimburse reasonable research-related expenses, to compensate participants for their time and other contributions to research, and to incentivize research participation.Reference Gelinas, Largent, Cohen, Kornetsky, Bierer and Lynch3 As Waltz et al. note, participant payments, excluding reimbursements, are taxable income, and as such must be reported to the Internal Revenue Service (IRS). Though this may seem like a dull bureaucratic detail, it is a detail worthy of ethical reflection.

What are the ethical implications of taxing research-related income? If participants pay their taxes, their take-home pay from research participation is lower than their gross pay. Although there are often worries that participants are paid too much, this concern generally affixes to what is paid prior to deductions. When we think instead about net pay, it may change our sense of what counts as fair payment and, perhaps, lend support to the argument that we should worry less about over-paying and more about under-paying participants.Reference Largent and Lynch4

If participants do not pay their taxes, they are exposed to financial and legal risks. It has long been recognized that the risks of research participation are not limited to the physical and psychological but can also encompass the economic and social. Risks must be minimized and accurately communicated to participants through an informed consent process.Reference Wendler and Grady5 Yet, as Waltz et al note, and as I too have found in prior empirical research, the tax implications of participant payments are often not sufficiently addressed in consent documents.Reference Wickliffe, Lynch and Largent6

There is another financial risk associated with payment for research participation that must be made clear. Participants may find that earning research-related income affects their eligibility for Supplemental Security Income (SSI) — monthly payments to low-income older adults and persons with disabilities — and other public benefits programs. Waltz et al. make the irony apparent. People often express concerns that there is an unjust reliance on — even exploitation of — worse-off individuals to fill Phase I trials. Yet, participation in these same trials may make it more difficult to access or prevent individuals from accessing public assistance programs intended for the worse-off.7

Some may wish to argue that this is good: if income is a primary driver of program eligibility, becoming ineligible is a sign of less need. Others (including myself) will cast aside such optimism in favor of skepticism. Payments from Phase I trials are more likely to yield short-term changes in income or circumstances, rendering individuals temporarily ineligible, than to create sustainable changes. Income volatility is not problem-free. Consider that people on Medicaid who experience “churn” — a temporary loss of coverage, often due to income fluctuations, characterized by individuals disenrolling and reenrolling in a brief window — leads to coverage gaps, erects barriers to accessing care, and is associated with greater administrative costs.Reference Corallo, Garfield, Tolbert and Rudowitz8 Appreciating these complications, we can see why “perverse” efforts to keep one’s research-related income low, a finding reported by Waltz et al, are also rational.

What are the ethical implications of taxing research-related income? If participants pay their taxes, their take-home pay from research participation is lower than their gross pay. Although there are often worries that participants are paid too much, this concern generally affixes to what is paid prior to deductions. When we think instead about net pay, it may change our sense of what counts as fair payment and, perhaps, lend support to the argument that we should worry less about over-paying and more about under-paying participants

In their article, Waltz et al. focus on participants in Phase I studies, in which average payments to participants are larger, because that was the sampling frame for their qualitative research. Yet, the issues they identify arise in later-phase studies too, and when payments are relatively more modest. For example, I led a qualitative study to understand the effects of payment on individuals’ decisions to participate in a randomized controlled trial evaluating an ambulation intervention; the trial was deemed minimal risk and offered a prospect of direct benefit to patient-participants. One participant asserted that the $300 payment offered to participants “helped me with my financial problems” but also described feeling “uneasy about the tax [consequences]…[b]ecause I am on SSI.”Reference Largent, Eriksen, Barg, Greysen and Halpern9 Thus, the authors’ call for greater attention to the tax and benefit implications of payment applies to research broadly, though the stakes may be heightened in Phase I studies.

I was somewhat surprised that neither the authors nor the individuals they interviewed offered a robust argument for paying research participants more. Perhaps they viewed this as a non-starter given ethical debates swirling around payment. Rather, Waltz et al. conclude that “research compensation should be categorized as non-taxable income.” In fact, there is a precedent for this. The Ensuring Access to Clinical Trials Act of 2015, signed into law by President Obama, allows individuals participating in clinical trials for rare diseases to receive up to $2,000 in research compensation without having this counted as income for SSI and Medicaid eligibility calculations. This could serve as a model for broader legislation — broader in terms of the total allowable compensation or the research encompassed by it.

Yet, this is not a straightforward solution. We must still grapple with what amount of research-related income it is appropriate to exempt from tax calculations and for what kinds of studies. Tax exemption would function as a research subsidy. Participants would surely enjoy the additional personal consumption that came from untaxed income, potentially making research participation relatively more attractive than alternative uses of their time. Tax exemption would likely also benefit sponsors (often pharmaceutical companies) and funders, who would not themselves be paying participants more, and perhaps eventually taxpayers. But to what extent is research participation simply a job to be done and to what extent is it special, deserving of special tax status?

Perhaps a friendly amendment to Benjamin Franklin’s famous adage is that nothing is certain but death and taxes … and the persistence of ethical questions regarding payments to research participants.

Note

The author has no conflicts of interest to disclose.

References

Waltz, M., Davis, A. M., and Fisher, J. A., “Death and Taxes’: Why Financial Compensation for Research Participants is an Economic and Legal Risk,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 50, no. 2 (2023): 413425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Largent, E.A., Heffernan, K.G., Joffe, S., and Lynch, H.F., “Paying Clinical Trial Participants: Legal Risks and Mitigation Strategies,” Journal of Clinical Oncology 38, no. 6 (2020), doi:10.1200/JCO.19.00250.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gelinas, L., Largent, E.A., Cohen, I.G., Kornetsky, S., Bierer, B.E., Lynch, H. Fernandez, “A Framework for Ethical Payment to Research Participants,” New England Journal of Medicine 378, no. 8 (2018): 766771, doi:10.1056/NEJMsb1710591.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Largent, E.A. and Lynch, H. F., “Paying Research Participants: Regulatory Uncertainty, Conceptual Confusion, and a Path Forward,” Yale Journal of Health Policy, Law, and Ethics 17, no. 1 (2017): 61141.Google Scholar
E.J. Emanuel, Wendler, D., and Grady, C., “What Makes Clinical Research Ethical?JAMA 283, no. 20 (2000): 27012711.Google Scholar
Wickliffe, C., Lynch, H.F., and Largent, E.A., “Offering Payment in Clinical Research: Enrolling Individuals With or at Risk for Opioid Use Disorder,” Journal of Empirical Research on Human Research Ethics 15, no. 3 (2020): 163174, doi:10.1177/1556264619898972.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Largent, supra note 2.Google Scholar
Corallo, B., Garfield, R., Tolbert, J., and Rudowitz, R., “Medicaid Enrollment Churn and Implications for Continuous Coverage Policies,” December 14, 2021, available at <https://www.kff.org/medicaid/issue-brief/medicaid-enrollment-churn-and-implications-for-continuous-coverage-policies/> (last visited June 13, 2023).+(last+visited+June+13,+2023).>Google Scholar
Largent, E.A., Eriksen, W., Barg, F.K., Greysen, S.R., and Halpern, S.D., “Participants’ Perspectives on Payment for Research Participation: A Qualitative Study,” Ethics & Human Research 44, no. 6 (2022): 1422, doi:10.1002/eahr.500147.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed