1. Introduction
In this paper, we revisit the phenomenon of Negative Concord (NC) with special emphasis on Catalan facts. Catalan is well-known for optionally allowing the negative marker to co-occur with pre-verbal Negative Concord Items (NCIs) (n-words in Laka Reference Laka1990) such as ningú ‘n-body’, res ‘n-thing’, and the like (Fabra Reference Fabra1912, Reference Fabra1918, Reference Fabra1956; Badia i Margarit Reference Margarit and Maria1962, Reference Margarit and Maria1994; Solà Reference Solà1973; Quer Reference Quer1993; van der Wouden and Zwarts Reference van der Wouden, Zwarts, Lahiri and Wyner1993; Vallduví Reference Vallduví1994; Espinal Reference Espinal2000, Reference Espinal, Joan Solà, Mascaró and Pérez-Saldanya2002; Zeijlstra Reference Zeijlstra2004; Tubau Reference Tubau2008; Déprez et al. Reference Déprez, Tubau, Cheylus and Espinal2015) and is, hence, difficult to classify in a parametric division of NC into a Strict and a Non-Strict type (Giannakidou Reference Giannakidou1997, Reference Giannakidou1998). In addition, words like ningú and res in Catalan have a wider distribution than NCIs in other languages with NC.Footnote 2 Although ningú, res, and the like can occur in negative contexts as well as in non-negative ones (e.g. questions, conditionals, etc.), NCIs are restricted to negative contexts in other NC languages (e.g. Romanian). Again, then, Catalan is puzzling when it comes to establishing whether NCIs are negative or not and whether they are quantificational or not.
The article is organized as follows. In the remainder of this section, we review different approaches to NC and discuss why this phenomenon has been very often considered problematic for the Principle of Compositionality (as has been noted by Ladusaw Reference Ladusaw, Barker and Dowty1992 or Giannakidou Reference Giannakidou2000, for example) and why Catalan poses a problem for the macro-parametric division of NC languages into the Strict and the Non-Strict type. In Section 2, we address different positions concerning the nature of NCIs and their implications for the understanding of NC with the Catalan data being core to the discussion. In Section 3, we unpack our new proposal to account for NC, which is articulated around the central assumption that NCIs are negative indefinites by virtue of carrying a negative feature [neg] that can be disembodied from the rest of the indefinite by means of overt Move F(eature) (Roberts Reference Roberts1998, cf. Pesetsky Reference Pesetsky2000) to c-command Tense (cf. Davidson Reference Davidson and Rescher1967, Diesing Reference Diesing1992, Weiss Reference Weiss2002). In this new approach, NC and the Strict vs. Non-Strict NC distinction are best described as an epiphenomenon of a syntax–phonology interface requirement imposed on the expression of negation rather than as a syntactic dependency. This interface condition is in compliance with Jespersen’s (Reference Jespersen1917, Reference Jespersen1933) NegFirst principleFootnote 3 (see also Horn Reference Horn1989; and the Negative Early principle, van der Auwera & Van Alsenoy Reference van der Auwera and Van Alsenoy2016). Section 4 concludes the paper.
1.1 Negative Concord and compositionality
It is often pointed out in the literature on NC that this phenomenon is a problem for compositionality. According to the Principle of Semantic Compositionality (Frege Reference Frege1879), the meaning of a given expression is the result of the meaning of its parts. Hence, the fact that a sentence such as (1) is interpreted with a single negation (SN) reading either means that one of the two elements that look like negative is not, or that, if both are, a mechanism exists that combines two negations into one.
Either position corresponds to existing views of NC and NCIs. For Zanuttini (Reference Zanuttini1991), Haegeman & Zanuttini (Reference Haegeman and Zanuttini1991), and Haegeman (Reference Haegeman1995), NCIs are negative universal quantifiers that bear a negative formal feature that needs to be checked in a Specifier–Head configuration with a negative operator sitting in the head Neg(ation). Given that in Zanuttini and Haegeman’s work both the NCI and Neg are assumed to be inherently negative, a semantic process of negative absorption known as Neg-factorisation is postulated. Neg-factorisation is argued to cancel the negative meaning of one or more raised negative quantifiers (NQs) when under the scope of a negative operator. Watanabe (Reference Watanabe2004) updates Zanuttini and Haegeman’s approach by arguing that Neg-factorisation naturally follows from the fact that feature-checking involves copying of the negative feature of the Goal (i.e. the NCI) onto the Probe (i.e. Neg). Co-occurrence of two negative features in the Probe cancels them so that the negative marker becomes non-negative, and it is the NCI that contributes the negative meaning to the sentence. De Swart & Sag (Reference de Swart and Sag2002) also assume NCIs to be NQs that can either engage in resumption (thus yielding a SN reading) or in iteration (thus yielding a double negation (DN) meaning). By contrast, for Bosque (Reference Bosque1980), Laka (Reference Laka1990), and Progovac (Reference Progovac1994), NCIs are polarity items (PIs) and, as such, they must be bound by a suitable operator which includes, but is not restricted to, negation. Ladusaw (Reference Ladusaw, Barker and Dowty1992) argues that NCIs are self-licensing (they introduce their own licensing negative operator in certain contexts). Finally, NCIs have also been argued to be lexically ambiguous between NQs and PIs (Herburger Reference Herburger2001). This is because apart from the debate on the (non-)negativity of NCIs, their quantificational status has also been at the heart of the vast literature on NC. NCIs have been argued to be negative universal quantifiers (Haegeman & Zanuttini Reference Haegeman and Zanuttini1991; Zanuttini Reference Zanuttini1991; Haegeman Reference Haegeman1995), non-negative universal quantifiers (Giannakidou Reference Giannakidou2000), non-negative PIs (Bosque Reference Bosque1980; Laka Reference Laka1990), non-negative indefinites (Ladusaw Reference Ladusaw, Barker and Dowty1992, Reference Ladusaw, Harvey and Santelman1994; Acquaviva Reference Acquaviva1993, Reference Acquaviva1997; Giannakidou & Quer Reference Giannakidou, Quer, Gabriele, Hardison and Westmoreland1997; Zeiljstra 2004; Tubau Reference Tubau2008), negative indefinites (Suñer Reference Suñer1995), and indefinites incorporated into a zero numeral (Déprez Reference Déprez1997; Espinal Reference Espinal2000).
The literature is divided concerning the nature of NCIs because there is evidence for them to be analysed as inherently negative and, at the same time, evidence for them to be analysed as non-negative. The strongest argument for the analysis of NCIs as negative comes from the observation that in all NC languages, NCIs can be used as answers to questions in the absence of an overt negative marker; see (2A) and (3A).Footnote 5
Given that in some languages (e.g. Spanish, Italian) pre-verbal NCIs cannot co-occur with the (alleged) negative marker, (4), it may also be argued that this is because they are inherently negative.
Yet, in some other languages (e.g. Greek, Romanian), pre-verbal NCIs must co-occur with the (alleged) negative marker, (5), and, hence, this makes it difficult to argue that they are inherently negative.
In addition, postverbal NCIs must co-occur with the purported negative marker in all languages that allow NC – see (6) and (7). This is the strongest argument to claim that NCIs are inherently non-negative.
In short, when it comes to whether NCIs introduce an instance of negation or not, the choice amounts to a yes-no answer, with ‘yes’ and ‘no’ only straightforwardly accounting for part of the data. If NCIs are assumed to be negative, isolated NCIs used as answers to wh-questions are easy to accommodate, but the distribution of post-verbal NCIs across languages with NC and the distribution of pre-verbal NCIs in languages such as Romanian or Greek (which must co-occur with the (alleged) negative marker) are problematic. So is the phenomenon known as negative spread (den Besten Reference den Besten, Muysken and Smith1986), as in (8), where a pre-verbal NCI licenses one or more post-verbal NCIs in the absence of a negative marker. In all the problematic cases, the central question is how two (or more) negations end up being interpreted as only one.
By contrast, if NCIs are assumed to be non-negative, the distribution of post-verbal NCIs is straightforward, and the problematic data would be the use of isolated NCIs as answers to wh-questions, the distribution of pre-verbal NCIs in languages such as Spanish and Italian, and negative spread. For these problematic cases, it is not obvious where the negative meaning of the sentence comes from.
The Strict vs. Non-Strict NC classification, which is based on the distribution of pre-verbal NCIs and whether they must or must not co-occur with the alleged negative marker in this position, has also led to the assumption that the so-called negative marker is not negative in every language. According to Zeijlstra (Reference Zeijlstra2004), the negative marker carries an interpretable negative feature in languages with Non-Strict NC, but an uninterpretable negative feature in languages with Strict NC. In other words, whereas the negative marker would be truly negative in languages such as Spanish or Italian, it would not be negative in languages such as Romanian or Greek. In languages with Strict NC, Zeijlstra claims that the uninterpretable negative feature of the negative marker is checked by an abstract negative operator that is inserted for this purpose as a Last Resort. It is, therefore, this abstract negative operator and not the negative marker that reverses the truth-conditions of a proposition.
Zeijlstra’s (Reference Zeijlstra2004) analysis raises an important theoretical concern for the characterization of negation in languages with Strict NC: if the (purported) negative marker is semantically non-negative and it always triggers the Last Resort insertion of an abstract negative operator that is covert, why does the negative marker always have to be overt both in NC and non-NC structures? For Catalan, which has been reported to optionally allow the negative marker to co-occur with pre-verbal NCIs, Zeijlstra’s (Reference Zeijlstra2004) analysis amounts to claiming that the negative marker is lexically ambiguous between the non-negative type that is found in Strict NC languages and the negative type of Non-Strict NC languages. The purpose of the present article is to put forward a new approach to NC that can explain the cross-linguistic similarities in the distribution of NCIs in the post-verbal position and the cross-linguistic differences in the distribution of pre-verbal NCIs with respect to the necessary presence/compulsory absence of no in Catalan (or non, dhen, nu, ne in Italian, Greek, Romanian, Russian, etc.) and possibly accommodate the NC-type flexibility attested in Catalan. We hereby hypothesize that (i) NCIs are negative indefinites with a formal feature [neg] that semantically translates as a negative operator ¬; (ii) the negative marker is always negative (i.e. it also corresponds to a negative operator ¬), and (iii) the Strict vs. Non-Strict NC contrast is the result of whether the formal feature [neg] in an NCI moves overtly to c-command the Tense features of the sentence via Move F, or it ends up doing so after the NCI opportunistically moves via Move α for reasons independent from the expression of negation.Footnote 6 We claim that the choice of Move F (à la Roberts Reference Roberts1998) to satisfy the syntax–phonology constraint that we are proposing has observable consequences for the syntax–phonology mapping of negation.
In the next section, we examine how Catalan poses a problem for the Strict vs. Non-Strict classification if this is understood as parametric. In Section 2, we review the evidence in favor and against analysing Catalan NCIs as PIs or as NQs. In Section 3, we develop our new approach to NC based on hypotheses (i)–(iii).
1.2 Catalan poses a problem for a macro-parametric Strict vs. Non-Strict NC classification
The Strict vs. Non-Strict NC classification is based on whether pre-verbal NCIs must co-occur with the alleged negative marker (Strict NC) or if, by contrast, they cannot (Non-Strict NC). This distinction has been assumed to be connected to parametric variation in the morphosyntactic features of the negative marker. In Strict NC languages, the purported negative marker is assumed to carry a [uNeg] feature and, hence, needs to be licensed by an operator carrying a matching interpretable negative feature [iNeg] very much in the same way NCIs do. In Non-Strict NC languages, the negative marker is assumed to carry an [iNeg] feature (Zeijlstra Reference Zeijlstra2004). The underlying structure of the Romanian and the Spanish sentences in (9a, b) is, therefore, claimed to be different.
As shown in (10), in Romanian, the [uNeg] feature of nu triggers the insertion of a covert Last Resort negative operator endowed with the feature [iNeg] (Op¬[iNeg]) that can check the [uNeg] feature of nu and the NCI under Multiple Agree (Ura Reference Ura1996; Hiraiwa Reference Hiraiwa2001; cf. Chomsky Reference Chomsky1995, Reference Chomsky and Kenstowicz2001).Footnote 7 Checking is indicated by the strikethrough. In (11), by contrast, it is no, endowed with an [iNeg] feature, that engages in the checking relation mediated by Agree.
As shown in (12), Catalan allows no to optionally co-occur with pre-verbal NCIs (Fabra Reference Fabra1912, Reference Fabra1918, Reference Fabra1956; Badia i Margarit Reference Margarit and Maria1962, Reference Margarit and Maria1994; Solà Reference Solà1973; Quer Reference Quer1993; van der Wouden & Zwarts Reference van der Wouden, Zwarts, Lahiri and Wyner1993; Vallduví Reference Vallduví1994; Espinal Reference Espinal2000, Reference Espinal, Joan Solà, Mascaró and Pérez-Saldanya2002; Zeijlstra Reference Zeijlstra2004; Tubau Reference Tubau2008) and is thus a misfit in the landscape of NC (Déprez et al. Reference Déprez, Tubau, Cheylus and Espinal2015).Footnote 8
If the parametric difference between Strict and Non-Strict NC lies upon the [uNeg] vs. [iNeg] feature distinction of the purported negative marker, as Zeijlstra (Reference Zeijlstra2004) suggests, then (12) must be accounted for as the co-existence of two dialects for CatalanFootnote 9 (van der Wouden & Zwarts Reference van der Wouden, Zwarts, Lahiri and Wyner1993; Zeijlstra Reference Zeijlstra2004), each with a differently specified negative marker, or two registers (a formal one with Strict NC and an informal one with Non-Strict NC) (Penka Reference Penka2011, van der Auwera & Van Alsenoy Reference van der Auwera and Van Alsenoy2016, van der Auwera & Krasnoukhova Reference van der Auwera, Krasnoukhova, Déprez and Espinal2020). However, in Déprez et al. (Reference Déprez, Tubau, Cheylus and Espinal2015), empirical evidence is provided against this position. Before discussing such evidence though, let us note that in Section 2, we argue that Catalan res, ningú, etc. exist as NCIs and also as PIs, with the two series being homophonous (Espinal & Llop Reference Espinal and Llop2022).Footnote 10 As will be later discussed, PIs are excluded from the pre-verbal position and cannot be used in isolation without an overt c-commanding licensor. When in post-verbal position though, NCIs res, ningú, etc. cannot be distinguished from PIs res, ningú, etc. Therefore, in what follows, in our examples we gloss PIs by means of any forms in English and NCIs by means of n-forms. Whenever there is ambiguity, it is reflected in the glosses.
We return now to Déprez et al.’s (Reference Déprez, Tubau, Cheylus and Espinal2015) experimental evidence against van der Wouden & Zwarts’ (Reference van der Wouden, Zwarts, Lahiri and Wyner1993) and Zeijlstra’s (Reference Zeijlstra2004) account of the optionality of no with Catalan pre-verbal NCIs as the result of dialectal variation. Déprez et al. (Reference Déprez, Tubau, Cheylus and Espinal2015) conduct two experiments to explore various research questions related to NC (hence SN) and DN in Catalan. Of relevance for our present discussion are two questions – namely, (i) whether NC is the default interpretation for sequences with no and multiple NCIs in Catalan and (ii) whether the co-presence of no could boost DN readings. The critical stimuli that the participants were asked to match with one of two available pictures (one corresponding to a SN reading resulting from NC, and one corresponding to an affirmative reading resulting from DN) contained pre-verbal and post-verbal NCIs with and without no, (13a, b).
These authors show that there are no speakers for whom NC in Catalan is always Strict, as stimuli such as (13a) and (13b) are both most often interpreted as SN by all the participants; likewise, there are no speakers of the alleged Non-Strict NC variety that systematically attribute DN to NC sentences with no and a pre-verbal NCI such as (13b). Although Déprez et al. (Reference Déprez, Tubau, Cheylus and Espinal2015) do not discuss their findings against the formal vs. informal distinction attributed to Catalan, we take them to also disconfirm that the optionality of no with preverbal NCIs in Catalan is the result of register variation. Given that the experiment in Déprez et al. involved the evaluation of written stimuli, a deviation towards favoring a Strict NC system could have been expected in the participants’ answers. Interestingly, not only was this not the case, but quite the opposite happened, as the proportion of DN readings in the participants’ answers significantly increased with the presence of no in the stimuli with pre-verbal NCIs (though DN still remained a marginal reading in comparison with the dominant SN one). This is unexpected within a system of Strict NC which requires the presence of no with pre-verbal NCIs.
In addition, several theoretical concerns arise from Zeijlstra’s (Reference Zeijlstra2004) theory of NC as well. The most pressing one concerns the syntax of post-verbal NCIs and the unrestricted nature of the insertion of a Last Resort abstract negative operator for the licensing of NCIs. If the presence of a [uNeg] feature that can be potentially left unchecked can trigger the insertion of Op¬[iNEG], a Last Resort operator that negates the sentence, what prevents (14a), which could in principle have the underlying structure in (14b), from being well-formed?
According to Zeijlstra (Reference Zeijlstra2004: 247), the Last Resort Op¬[iNeg] binds all free variables introduced in vP or below. Thus, (14a) should be grammatical with a syntax such as the one represented in (14b). In the absence of a Neg head, the [uNeg] in the NCI res would have to be checked by Op¬[iNeg], inserted as a Last Resort.Footnote 11 Notice that there is no overt Neg head in NC sequences with a pre-verbal NCI in Non-Strict NC. Hence, if it were the case that the presence of a Neg head in (14) is mandatory, thus excluding the insertion of Op¬[iNeg], what would need to be explained in the first place is why this is so for post-verbal NCIs, but not for pre-verbal NCIs in Non-Strict NC.
2. On the Nature of Negative Concord Items in Catalan
In this section, we compare NCIs to PIs and to NQs with Catalan as a case in point. We aim at showing that Catalan has two homophonous series of polarity-sensitive lexical items. The items in one of these two series behave exactly as PIs do, and the items in the other series show the distribution of NCIs (Espinal & Llop Reference Espinal and Llop2022).
2.1 Are Negative Concord Items polarity items in Catalan?
PIs can be licensed by negation, but also by a wider range of non-veridical operators such as conditionals and interrogatives, whereas NCIs are restricted to licensing by anti-veridical operators (Giannakidou Reference Giannakidou2001). Consider, for instance, the case of non-emphatic Greek PIs tipota ‘anything’ and kanenas ‘anybody’, (15), and compare it to emphatic TIPOTA ‘n-thing’ and KANENAS ‘n-body’, which are NCIs, (16).
Unlike PIs tipota and kanenas, NCIs TIPOTA and KANENAS are grammatical in pre-verbal position and as isolated answers to wh-questions. Compare (17) and (18) to (19) and (20).
PIs tipota and kanenas (but not TIPOTA and KANENAS) are licensed in the context of ‘before’, (21), whereas NCIs TIPOTA and KANENAS (but not tipota and kanenas) are licensed in the context of ‘without’, (22).Footnote 12
Finally, although PIs tipota and kanenas can be licensed long-distance by negation, NCIs TIPOTA and KANENAS cannot, as they must be licensed by a clause-mate negation, (23); see (16a) and (19).
If we now move to Catalan, examples (24), (25), and (26) show that res ‘n-thing’ and ningú ‘n-body’ have the same distribution as Greek PIs tipota and kanenas when it comes to the operators that can possibly license them and the grammaticality of long-distance licensing (Espinal & Llop Reference Espinal and Llop2022). However, as shown in (27) and (28), they also have the same distribution as TIPOTA and KANENAS when it comes to the possibility of res and ningú occurring pre-verbally and as isolated answers to wh-questions.
The data above thus make it difficult to classify res and ningú as either PIs or as NCIs. The situation improves if, as is the case for Greek, it is assumed that a series of PIs co-exists with a series of NCIs. In Greek, they are distinguished by emphasis, but this is not the case in Catalan. Therefore, (24a) and (27a, b) may be derived both with res being a PI ‘anything’ or an NCI ‘n-thing’; and (24b, c), (25), and (26) would only be grammatical with the PI ningú; and (27a, b) and (28) are only grammatical with the NCI ningú and res, respectively. Notice that Catalan also allows PIs (e.g. gaire ‘much, many’) to occur in isolation as answers to wh-questions provided that they are under the scope of the overt negative marker no ‘not’, (29).
If, as we claim, res, ningú, etc. can be PIs, they should be fine used as answers to wh-questions with an overt negative marker. This is indeed the case for res in all varieties of Catalan, and for ningú in some (Rigau Reference Rigau1998; Espinal Reference Espinal, Joan Solà, Mascaró and Pérez-Saldanya2002).
2.2 Are Negative Concord Items negative quantifiers in Catalan?
In the previous section, we claimed that Catalan has a series of NCIs which is homophonous to a series of PIs, which is licensed in a broader set of non-veridical contexts. In this section, we evaluate whether they can be assumed to be NQs.
Standard English NQs nobody, nothing and the like occur in the absence of a negative licensor in all contexts (including post-verbal contexts), (31), and do not allow negative spread (i.e. they cannot co-occur with each other yielding a SN reading). Thus, in Standard English, (32) is ill-formed under a SN interpretation. An example parallel to (31a) is not possible with a post-verbal NCI in Catalan, (33a), whereas the parallel to (32) is grammatical with a SN interpretation in Catalan, (33b). Hence, although the distribution of NCIs in Catalan (and in other NC languages) overlaps with that of NQs, it does so only partially, thus indicating that NCIs are not NQs.
But is there something special and specific to NQs when it comes to their lexical characterization (in comparison with NCIs)? There is a tradition in the literature according to which NQs contain an incorporated semantic negation alongside an existential quantifier (Klima Reference Klima, Fodor and Katz1964; Jacobs Reference Jacobs1980; Ladusaw Reference Ladusaw, Barker and Dowty1992; Penka & Zeijlstra Reference Penka and Zeijlstra2010; Iatridou & Sichel Reference Iatridou and Sichel2011; among others). When in a post-verbal position, the semantic negation in the NQ can covertly take sentential scope. Example (33a) would presumably be interpreted as negative, if native speakers were forced to interpret it but – even in accounts that take NCIs to be inherently negative – res, in contrast to nobody, requires a negative expression to c-command Tense features, as in (33b, c). This means that if NCIs carry negative import, as we argue, this must have a different syntactic status from the negation that is incorporated in NQs. We discuss this issue further in Section 3.
It is pointed out by Corblin (Reference Corblin1995, Reference Corblin1996), de Swart (Reference de Swart2010), and van der Auwera & Van Alsenoy (Reference van der Auwera and Van Alsenoy2016), among others, that in French, two readings are attested for the sentence in (34). Although the SN reading is expected if French NCIs can participate in negative spread, the DN reading would follow from an analysis in which personne and rien are considered NQs, ‘nobody’ and ‘nothing’, respectively.
It seems, therefore, that in the same way Catalan has a series of NCIs that is homophonous with a series of PIs, other languages (e.g. French) may have a series of NCIs that is homophonous with a series of NQs. We return to this issue with a more detailed discussion in Sections 3.6 and 3.7.
3. A new approach to Negative Concord
The assumption that NCIs are non-negative is a position that has been widely explored in the literature to account for the phenomenon of NC, and it has led to solutions that involve advocating for a covert source of negation of some kind to explain the distribution of NCIs in pre-verbal position in so-called Non-Strict NC languages and the possibility to use isolated NCIs as answers to wh-questions generally. In this paper, on the contrary, we want to explore the possibility that NCIs are inherently negative. Therefore, in what follows, we present a new approach to NC that combines the three following core hypotheses:
-
(i) NCIs are inherently negative indefinites by means of carrying a feature [neg] that semantically translates as a negative operator ¬ that can reverse the truth-conditions of the proposition;
-
(ii) the negative marker always introduces an instance of logical negation, ¬,Footnote 13 and
-
(iii) the [neg] feature of an NCI can disembody by means of overt Move F (Roberts Reference Roberts1998) to overtly c-command the Tense features of the sentence; the Strict vs. Non-Strict NC contrast is the result of whether this requirement is satisfied by means of movement of [neg] (Move F) or by some other movement of the NCI that contains the feature [neg] (Move α).
In any approach that assumes that NCIs are negative, the fact that these can be used in isolation as answers to wh-questions receives a straightforward explanation, even without having to take sides in the open debate on whether answers to questions are fragments of fuller clauses that are subject to ellipsis or not. In a similar vein, the syntax of pre-verbal NCIs in Non-Strict NC languages (where the pre-verbal NCI seems to contribute the negative meaning to the clause) is also straightforward.
What needs to be explained within an account that takes NCIs to be inherently negative, therefore, are the following research questions in (35):
In the sections that follow, we address each of the above questions in turn but first, in Section 3.1, we outline our assumptions concerning the difference between the negative marker in a negative sentence without NC, and the purported ‘negative marker’ in a sentence with NC. In Section 3.2, we address RQ 1, and in Section 3.3, we deal with RQs 2 and 3. In Sections 3.4 to 3.7, we answer RQs 4 to 7.
3.1 On the expression of negation by means of negative markers and morphosyntactic negative features
In this paper, we assume that negation is a semantic operator that can reverse the truth-conditions of a proposition when at the level of meaning representation, it binds the event variable (sitting in vP, or denoted through the tense feature; Acquaviva Reference Acquaviva1995; Roberts Reference Roberts1998; Zeijlstra Reference Zeijlstra2004, Reference Zeijlstra2008; Penka Reference Penka2011). Take, for example, the sentences in (36). If (36a) expresses the proposition p, the presence of the negative marker no in (36b) results in the expression of ¬p, and the speaking event is negated.
Since Pollock (Reference Pollock1989), negation has been argued to have its own dedicated functional projection, NegP. Thus, in (36b), we assume the Catalan pre-verbal negative marker no to be a syntactic head Neg that projects into NegP in line with Zanuttini (Reference Zanuttini, Baltin and Collins2001).Footnote 14 A relevant question at this point is whether Neg (and NegP) are always present in negative sentences and, more specifically, whether they are always present in sentences with NC if NCIs are assumed to be inherently negative.
In the present paper, we entertain the idea that NCIs are negative by virtue of carrying a negative feature, [neg], but unlike Zeijlstra (Reference Zeijlstra2004), who claims that negative features are either interpretable, [iNeg], or uninterpretable, [uNeg], so that they can participate in an Agree chain where [iF] checks [uF], we do not link the [neg] feature to (un)interpretability. Rather, our account is inspired by proposals such as Puskás (Reference Puskás1998, Reference Puskás2000) or Jäger (Reference Jäger2008), for whom negative indefinites are specified with the feature [+neg]. In this paper, we claim that the feature [neg] has the semantic potential to negate a proposition.Footnote 15 Yet, for a negative sentence containing NCIs to be grammatical (and fully accepted by native speakers), [neg] should occur in a position from where it overtly c-commands the Tense features of the sentence. We take this to be a syntax–phonology interface constraint rather than a constraint on the assignment of sentential scope to negation. (See Espinal et al., in press, for experimental support of this hypothesis).
Furthermore, we also assume that multiple [neg] features can participate in a feature-sharing operation (Kuno Reference Kuno, Torck and Wetzels2006: 150) that ‘…voids the negative meaning of a Neg-feature without actually deleting it.’Footnote 16 In what follows, we address how our proposal accounts for the syntax of NCIs in different positions in Catalan. However, before doing this, it is important to clarify that we do not take the lexical item no in Catalan (as well as in Spanish, or nu in Romanian, dhen in Greek, non in Italian, etc.) to always correspond to the syntactic head Neg. Rather, we claim that although no is the Spell-Out of a syntactic head Neg in negative sentences without an NCI, it is actually the phonetic realization of a disembodied (i.e. displaced by means of Move F) feature [neg] in sentences with an NCI.Footnote 17 That is, we take two sentences such as (37) and (38) to have different underlying syntactic structures. The structure we assume for (37) is (39), with no corresponding to the syntactic head Neg; the analysis of (38) is discussed in Section 3.2, but note that no in this case would not correspond to the syntactic head Neg.
In short, in this paper, we assume that different polarity-sensitive lexical items hold different relations with different forms of negation. So-called NQs (e.g. Standard English nobody, nothing, etc.) contain an incorporated negation (Temmerman Reference Temmerman2012) that can take sentential scope covertly and cannot participate in concord relations (thus disallowing negative spread between a pre-verbal NQ and one or more post-verbal NQs). PIs are existential expressions that depend on a semantically suitable licensor (a non-veridical licensor, according to Giannakidou Reference Giannakidou2001). By contrast, in this paper we argue that NCIs are existential expressions endowed with a negative feature [neg] that can raise to overtly c-command Tense, which is a syntax–phonology interface requirement for the expression of negation in NC languages. What is unique about NCIs is that the [neg] feature can move up by disembodying from the NCI to satisfy this requirement (in compliance with Jespersen’s Reference Jespersen1917, Reference Jespersen1933 NegFirst principle).Footnote 19 When this happens, [neg] is phonologically realized in the same way as the corresponding head Neg (i.e. no, nu, dhen, etc.) and the NCI is (semantically) downgraded to a non-negative indefinite. Crucial to the present analysis is the proposal that the underlying structure of a sentence with an NCI contains no Neg head even if a SN reading is to be composed.
3.2 On the syntax of post-verbal Negative Concord Items
In this section, we address RQ 1 – namely, why post-verbal NCIs must co-occur with what looks like a negative marker in the pre-Infl position in all NC languages. We argue that the [neg] feature of an NCI that is merged post-verbally is too embedded in the structure to fulfil the syntax–phonology interface requirement that we propose for sentential negation in this paper. Given the Phase Impenetrability Condition (PIC) (Chomsky Reference Chomsky, Martin, Michaels and Uriagereka2000), (40), and assuming that negation in Romance languages is higher than the TP (Ouhalla Reference Ouhalla1990), [neg] needs to be extracted via the phase edge.Footnote 20
In phase α with head H, the domain of H is not accessible to operations outside α; only H and its edge are accessible to such operations.
(Chomsky Reference Chomsky, Martin, Michaels and Uriagereka2000: 108)Let us examine a sentence such as (38), repeated here as (41) for convenience.
The Numeration includes the NCI res ‘n-thing’,Footnote 21 endowed with a [neg] feature that can potentially negate the clause due to its negative semantics, but which needs to overtly c-command Tense. The derivation of the first relevant phase is (42). Extraction of the [neg] feature of the NCI to the TP-phase edge by means of Move F adjoins [neg] to TP and yields the structure in (43). Upon transfer of the syntactic structure to exponence (Nevins Reference Nevins and Trommer2012), [neg] undergoes Vocabulary Insertion and is pronounced as no. In (43), the angled brackets indicate traces of movement.
This simple mechanism answers our RQ 1. The reason why post-verbal NCIs are c-commanded by what looks like a negative marker in all languages with NC is because the [neg] feature of a post-verbal NCI, which is responsible for the negative semantics of the NCI, can disembody from the negative indefinite to satisfy a syntax–phonological interface constraint (fully compatible with Jespersen’s NegFirst principle) that negation overtly c-commands the Tense features of the sentence. The disembodied [neg] feature is pronounced with the same phonological realization that a given language uses to Spell-Out negation.Footnote 22
What is novel about the present analysis of NC structures is (i) the possibility for the negation (feature) contained in the NCI to disembody by means of Move F independently from the rest of the lexical item, and (ii) that NC is analysed not as a narrow syntax phenomenon but as a mapping from syntax to exponence. Such an option is considered to fit with minimalist tenets, as only the essential feature overtly moves to the phase-edge.
3.3 On the syntax of pre-verbal Negative Concord Items
Let us now consider RQs 2 and 3 – namely, why pre-verbal NCIs must occur with what looks like a negative marker in some NC languages but not in all (RQ 2), and what is the syntax of strings of a pre-verbal NCI in combination with what looks like a negative marker (also known as Strict NC) (RQ 3). Assuming that the [neg] feature of NCIs is required to overtly c-command Tense features for a sentence with NC to be fully grammatical (i.e. compliant with the syntax–phonology interface conditions), whether it does so by means of Move F or whether it can do so opportunistically (i.e. as a consequence of an instance of Move α that relocates the entire NCI for reasons that have little to do with the expression of negation) might result in the observed difference between so-called Strict NC and Non-Strict NC. If in a structure such as (44), [neg] satisfies the aforementioned syntax–phonology interface constraint by means of Move F, it will be extracted to the TP phase-edge prior to subject movement of the NCI from the Specifier of vP to the Specifier of a left-peripheral projection, here labelled FP (for TopicP, FocusP, etc.).Footnote 23 At the time of Vocabulary Insertion, the F Moved [neg] feature is Spelled-Out as dhen, nu, no, etc. depending on the languages’ vocabulary insertion repertoire. Although the possibility that a [neg] feature disembodies from an NCI is the property that characterizes all NCI languages, by what means (Move F or Move α) a language manages to satisfy the syntax–phonology interface constraint that an expression of negation overtly c-commands Tense is what results in two main types of NC (so-called Strict NC and Non-Strict NC) that are only detected when pre-verbal NCIs are involved.
For the Romanian pair in (45), (45a) has a structure where the NCI subject nimeni remains in the vP-internal position; by contrast, to derive (45b), nimeni moves upwards, as illustrated in the structure in (44). In both the examples in (45), [neg] undergoes Move F and nu is inserted.
In Non-Strict NC languages, by contrast, the syntax–phonology interface constraint that we propose is satisfied by an application of Move α such as movement of the subject NCI from the Specifier of vP to the Specifier of FP, thus sparing the need for the [neg] feature to disembody. In this case, [neg] will not receive distinct phonological content (i.e. what looks like a negative marker will not be present in the clause). That the repositioning of [neg] in a higher position in Non-Strict NC languages is predatory on other movement operations is supported by the contrast that can be observed in (46) for Catalan. Although in (46a), the [neg] feature of the NCI relocates via subject movement, in (46b), the subject NCI does not move further from its first-merge position in the Specifier of the vP, thus forcing the [neg] feature of the NCI to disembody; see (44). After Move F, the disembodied [neg] feature in (46b) will be pronounced as no.
In short, the difference between Strict and Non-Strict NC is connected to how a very specific syntax–phonology interface condition is met (namely, the need for negation to overtly c-command Tense features). Although Strict NC languages use Move F allowing [neg] to relocate, Non-Strict NC languages allow Move α of the NCI for reasons other than the expression of negation to do the job. Yet, the relevant contrast between these two kinds of NC languages is only observed with pre-verbal NCIs: although in Strict NC, pre-verbal NCIs co-occur with what looks like a negative marker, they do not in Non-Strict NC. This is so, we argue, because it is only in the case of pre-verbal NCIs that the [neg] feature can reposition above TP via movement of the entire NCI for syntactic reasons other than the expression of negation. Given that the Strict vs. Non-Strict NC divide is a syntax–phonology interface issue, it is not surprising that Catalan can be flexible in how the [neg] feature of pre-verbal NCIs gets to a position above TP, thus freely alternating between Move F and Move α.Footnote 24
3.4 On the syntax of multiple post-verbal Negative Concord Items
Once the syntax of post-verbal and pre-verbal NCIs in Strict and Non-Strict languages has been examined, RQ 4 follows: what is the syntax of multiple post-verbal NCIs? In other words, if NCIs are assumed to be inherently negative, how is it possible for several of them to co-occur post-verbally? Let us consider the Catalan well-formed sentence in (47).
We argue that the derivation of a negative sentence with multiple post-verbal NCIs involves a concord relation and the disembodiment mechanism prompted by Move F that we have already outlined above for the feature [neg]. For a sentence such as (47), the TP-phase would be that in (48).Footnote 25
As they are in a c-command relation, the two [neg] features in the VP-domain can establish a concord relation and resume into one. We entertain the idea that the mechanism that combines two identical [neg] features is a case of feature-sharing (Kuno Reference Kuno, Torck and Wetzels2006). That is, we assume that when two identical [neg] features occur within a given syntactic domain (the vP in this case) and they are in a c-command relation, the [neg] feature is shared (step 1 in (49)) and, thus interpreted as a single instance of negation at the interface. Furthermore, the shared feature [neg] can then be disembodied (step 2 in (49)) and extracted to the edge of the phase (step 3 in (49)) via Move F. The [neg] feature will be pronounced as no and the sentence in (47) will convey SN.
3.5 On negative spread
Our fifth research question is connected to the syntax of negative spread (den Besten Reference den Besten, Muysken and Smith1986). Recall that this is the possibility that a pre-verbal NCI occurs with one or more post-verbal NCIs in Non-Strict NC languages. Negative spread is illustrated in the Catalan example in (50).
Negative spread fits well with our assumption that a [neg] feature c-commanding another one establish a concord relation that leads to feature-sharing. That is, the [neg] feature of the subject NCI c-commands the [neg] feature of the object NCI, and thus they share a [neg] feature and negation is interpreted only once. In addition, negative spread also follows from the fact that in Non-Strict NC, the syntax–phonology interface requirement that negation overtly c-commands the Tense features of the sentence can be met after [neg] is put in place thanks to an instance of Move α that targets the NCI and occurs independently from the expression of negation. Once movement of the external argument NCI has taken place, there is no need for [neg] to disembody and F Move and, therefore, it is not independently pronounced from the rest of the NCI. The derivation of (50) is shown in (51), with feature-sharing of two [neg] features in the vP-domain and posterior subject movement of the NCI, which guarantees that the shared [neg] feature c-commands Tense.
In Strict NC languages, negative spread is not attested, as what looks like a negative marker always occurs with both a pre-verbal and a post-verbal NCI. Thus, the equivalent of (50) in Romanian, for example, is (52).
In (52), nimeni and nimic also establish a concord relation (as ningú and res in (51) above) and share a [neg] feature. Then [neg] disembodies and is first extracted to the phase-edge via Move F. Later, the rest of the subject NCI (i.e. the existential indefinite, as [neg] has moved on its own) will move. The result is that the NCI is higher than the [neg] feature, which is Spelled-Out as nu, but the interpretation is that of SN. Thus, we propose that the derivation of (52) is that in (53).
3.6 On the syntax of multiple pre-verbal Negative Concord Items
In this section, we discuss our RQ 6 – namely, what the syntax of strings with multiple pre-verbal NCIs is in NC languages. As can be seen in (54) and (55), even when more than one NCI occurs preverbally, the contrast between so-called Non-Strict and Strict NC languages concerning the obligatoriness of the presence/absence of what looks like a negative marker is maintained.
Both in Spanish and in Greek, the order of the two pre-verbal NCIs may be reversed. The underlying structure for the TP-phase in both (54) and (55) would be that in (56). Given that the two NCIs establish a syntactic relation where one [neg] feature c-commands another, feature-sharing obtains both in Spanish and Greek. For Greek, the shared [neg] feature will disembody and relocate to a position above TP via Move F; [neg] will end up pronounced as dhen. Move-α will be responsible for the final position of the two pre-Infl NCIs, both in Greek and in Spanish.
What sets the difference is the point at which the shared [neg] satisfies the syntax-phonology requirement to overtly c-command the Tense features of the sentence.
3.7 On double negation
Our last RQ 7 concerns how DN emerges in NC languages. We argue here that it can arise in two different ways: (i) DN can be compositional and emerge as a result of combining a syntactic Neg head and an NCI endowed with a formal feature [neg], or (ii) by combining two NQs, if a given language has a series of NCIs that is homophonous with a series of NQs (e.g. French). We discuss each possibility in turn.
In our approach to NC, the syntactic head Neg is not part of the derivation of a negative sentence when an NCI is present in the lexical selection (or Numeration). This happens, of course, when/if the intended meaning is that of SN. Suppose, nonetheless, that the intended meaning is DN. It may then be possible to include both an NCI and a Neg head in the Numeration. These two negations, we have discussed, do not actually interact in NC, as they are of different syntactic status. Thus, it is expected that they will both be interpreted, hence cancelling each other out and yielding a DN reading. For cases such as (57), which, despite being most often interpreted as conveying a SN reading, were found to yield some proportion of DN in Déprez et al. (Reference Déprez, Tubau, Cheylus and Espinal2015), a compositional DN reading can obtain if the underlying structure of (57) is assumed to be the one in (58), where the negative head no combines with [neg] within a sentential domain and they both translate into ¬.Footnote 26
Earlier in the paper, we presented some data from French showing that two NCIs may give rise to a SN reading as the result of negative spread, but also to a DN reading, (34), repeated here as (59) and (60) for each reading (Corblin Reference Corblin1995, Reference Corblin1996).
Although the SN reading in (59) follows from the mechanism described in Section 3.5, we argue that the DN reading attested in sentences such as (60) follows from the fact that French has a series of NQs that is homophonous with a series of NCIs. If personne and rien are NQs (like Standard English nobody and nothing), their negation is incorporated (Temmerman Reference Temmerman2012) and cannot disembody in the way that the [neg] feature of NCIs does. In a structure involving them both in a c-commanding relation, therefore, no feature-sharing will take place, as this is, in our account, an option reserved for identical formal features and thus available to NCIs only. Thus, one negation will cancel out the other, predicting a DN interpretation as a consequence.
4. Conclusion and further discussion
With Catalan as a case in point, in this paper we have put into question the syntactic macro-parametric division between Strict and Non-Strict NC as characterized by Zeijlstra (Reference Zeijlstra2004). We align with a micro-parametric approach that drives NC from the properties assigned to the NCI. The optionality of no with preverbal NCIs shows that the difference Strict vs. Non-Strict cannot be due to the feature-marking of the negative marker. In the new proposal that we have developed, negative markers are inherently negative across all so-called NC languages, and so are NCIs, but negative markers and NCIs are formally distinct. It is precisely because NCIs are inherently negative that they can occur, in the absence of the negative marker, as answers to wh-questions.
As far as the Strict vs. Non-Strict NC distinction is concerned, we have argued that it follows from by what means a language must satisfy the syntax–phonology requirement that the Tense features of the sentence be overtly c-commanded by a negative expression, a requirement which is ultimately an instantiation of Jespersen’s NegFirst principle. In so-called Strict NC, [neg] relocates by means of Move F on all occasions. Move F of [neg] consists in disembodying [neg] from the rest of the NCI so that it can move to a position above TP, downgrading the NCI to an existential under the scope of negation. At the stage of Vocabulary Insertion, a disembodied [neg] feature will be Spelled-Out in different NC languages by means of items that are homophonous to a negative marker. The novelty of our analysis, therefore, consists in claiming that in NC structures (i.e. sentences containing one or more NCIs), what looks like the negative marker (e.g. Catalan/Spanish no, Italian non, Greek dhen, Romanian nu, etc.) is actually not a syntactic head Neg but the phonological realization of a [neg] feature that has moved independently from the rest of the NCI. Given that post-verbal NCIs are too embedded for [neg] to get to a position above TP unless it disembodies, they co-occur with what looks like a negative marker in all NC languages (regardless of whether they are classified as Strict or Non-Strict).
For the so-called Non-Strict NC languages, [neg] does not have to disembody when the NCI occurs pre-verbally, as [neg] is allowed to opportunistically relocate above TP as a consequence of any other movement of the NCI to a pre-verbal position. Regarding the need for negation to meet the syntax–phonology interface requirement we have proposed results in all NC structures having a phonological manifestation of [neg] with postverbal NCIs, but only some having a phonological manifestation of [neg] with pre-verbal NCIs (in Strict NC structures).
To motivate our proposal, we have taken into account the differences between NCIs and PIs, and NCIs and NQs. We have suggested that PIs are inherently non-negative, whereas NQs contain an incorporated negation. The difference between the negation in an NQ and the feature [neg] in NCIs is that although the latter can participate in concord configurations that involve feature-sharing (of identical [neg] formal features), the former is not allowed to do so. That is, if a [neg] feature c-commands another one within the vP, the co-occurring NCIs share their feature [neg], thus yielding a SN reading for structures containing more than one NCI.
We have also addressed the case of Catalan, which we concluded has a series of NCIs that is homophonous with a series of PIs. This gives the false impression of NCIs having a much wider distribution in Catalan than they have in other NC languages. In addition, the optionality of the (alleged) negative marker with pre-verbal NCIs has traditionally put Catalan in a gray area when having to classify it as having either Strict or Non-Strict NC. In the present paper, we claim that NC in Catalan displays flexibility between the Strict and the Non-Strict type because this division results from how a well-formedness syntax–phonology interface constraint is met.
We have discussed how DN readings can be accommodated in the new proposal we have developed. In summary, we have claimed that by virtue of being negative, NCIs that co-occur with a Neg syntactic head will give rise to DN readings because the semantic operator ¬ in Neg cannot participate in feature-sharing with the formal feature [neg] of the NCI, since they have different syntactic status and do not share identical formal properties in the same syntactic domain. Both NQs (which carry an incorporated negation) and NCIs (by virtue of a [neg] feature) are semantically negative; yet, the possibility that two [neg] features express only one logical negation as a consequence of feature-sharing is what sets NCIs apart from NQs. By virtue of allowing the [neg] feature to disembody, NCIs are close to PIs in the sense that at LF, they would both be translated as existentials under the scope of an operator. Yet, the licensor of PIs in negative contexts is either a negative marker or an NCI with a [neg] feature in it, whereas NCIs are self-licensing. This means that what looks like a negative marker co-occurring with NCIs in post-verbal position in all NC structures and with pre-verbal NCIs in Strict NC structures is just the phonological realization of the formal feature [neg] that used to be part of the NCI when it entered the derivation.
Conflict of Interest Statement
The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.