1 Introduction
Fuchs [Reference Fuchs10] introduced fragments of Todorčević’s strong reflection principle $\mathsf {SRP} $ (see [Reference Bekkali1, p. 57]) for forcing classes $\Gamma $ other than the class $\mathsf {SSP} $ of all stationary set preserving forcings. The focus was on the class of all subcomplete forcings, and the goal was to find a principle that relates to the forcing axiom for $\Gamma $ in much the same way that $\mathsf {SRP} $ relates to $\mathsf {MM} $ , the forcing axiom for $\mathsf {SSP} $ , namely such that:
-
(1) The forcing axiom for $\Gamma $ , $\mathsf {FA}(\Gamma )$ , implies $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {SRP} $ .
-
(2) Letting $\mathsf {SSP} $ be the class of all stationary set preserving forcing notions, $\mathsf {SRP} $ is equivalent to $\mathsf {SSP} $ - $\mathsf {SRP} $ .
-
(3) Letting $\mathsf {SC} $ be the class of all subcomplete forcing notions, $\mathsf {SC} $ - $\mathsf {SRP} $ captures many of the major consequences of $\mathsf {SCFA} $ , the forcing axiom for subcomplete forcing.
Subcomplete forcing was introduced by Jensen [Reference Jensen16, 17], and shown to be iterable with revised countable support. The main feature of subcomplete forcing that makes it interesting is that subcomplete forcing notions cannot add reals, and as a consequence, $\mathsf {SCFA} $ is compatible with $\mathsf {CH} $ . In fact, Jensen [Reference Jensen15] showed that $\mathsf {SCFA} $ is even compatible with $\diamondsuit $ , and hence does not imply that the nonstationary ideal on $\omega _1$ is $\omega _2$ -saturated. On the other hand, $\mathsf {SCFA} $ does have many of the major consequences of Martin’s Maximum, such as the singular cardinal hypothesis. Since $\mathsf {SRP} $ is known to imply that the nonstationary ideal on $\omega _1$ is $\omega _2$ -saturated, and that $\mathsf {CH} $ fails, finding a fragment of $\mathsf {SRP} $ for subcomplete forcing was subtle, but in [Reference Fuchs10], a principle satisfying the two desiderata listed above was found. While the original strong reflection principle can be formulated as postulating that every projective stationary subset of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ contains a continuous $\in $ -chain, for regular $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ , the subcomplete fragment of $\mathsf {SRP} $ asserts this only for spread out sets, and for $\kappa>2^\omega $ .
Naturally, there are limitations to the extent to which (3) can be true. Thus, Larson [Reference Larson18] introduced a diagonal version of simultaneous reflection of stationary sets of ordinals, called $\mathsf {OSR}_{\omega _2}$ , which follows from Martin’s Maximum, but not from $\mathsf {SRP} $ . This principle can be generalized to any regular cardinal $\kappa $ greater than $\omega _2$ , and it was shown in [Reference Fuchs and Lambie-Hanson11] that $\mathsf {SRP} $ does not even imply the weakest versions of these principles, while Fuchs [Reference Fuchs9] showed that these principles do follow from $\mathsf {SCFA} $ , as long as $\kappa>2^\omega $ . Since $\mathsf {SC} $ - $\mathsf {SRP} $ is weaker than $\mathsf {SRP} $ , this shows that $\mathsf {SC} $ - $\mathsf {SRP} $ does not capture these diagonal reflection principles either, which do follow from $\mathsf {SCFA} $ .
Since these ordinal diagonal reflection principles are underlying the results on the failure of weak square principles under $\mathsf {SCFA} $ shown in [Reference Fuchs9], we push here further in this direction, to find a principle of reflection of generalized stationarity that does capture these consequences of $\mathsf {SCFA} $ / $\mathsf {MM} $ , and that can be relativized to an arbitrary forcing class (resulting in the “fragments” of the principle), just like $\mathsf {SRP} $ . We call the resulting principle the diagonal strong reflection principle, $\mathsf {DSRP} $ . It unifies both the (relevant fragment) of $\mathsf {SRP} $ and certain diagonal reflection principles the first author introduced in [Reference Cox3]. It also gives rise to some new kinds of exact diagonal reflection principles for sets of ordinals.
For the most part, we will be working with a technical simplification of the notion of subcompleteness, called $\infty $ -subcompleteness and introduced in [Reference Fuchs and Switzer12]. This leads to a simplification of the adaptation of projective stationarity to the context of this version of subcompleteness. Working with the original notion of subcompleteness adds some technicalities, but does not change much.
The article is organized as follows. In Section 2, we will give some background on generalized stationarity, subcomplete forcing, and some material from [Reference Fuchs10] on the fragments of $\mathsf {SRP} $ . Then, in Section 3, we will formulate the $\Gamma $ -fragment of the diagonal strong reflection principle in full generality, for an arbitrary forcing class $\Gamma $ . In the subsequent Sections 4 and 5, we will treat the cases where $\Gamma $ is the class of all stationary set preserving forcing notions, or the class of all subcomplete forcing notions, respectively, and formulate these principles combinatorially. Here, the notion of a spread out set will make a reappearance, emphasizing its naturalness. Then, in Section 6, we will derive consequences of the principles mentioned above. We divide these consequences in two parts: first, Section 6.1 contains consequences that filter through an appropriate version of the diagonal reflection principles of [Reference Cox3], while Section 6.2 contains some consequences that don’t, among them some new principles of simultaneous stationary reflection that can be viewed as diagonal reflection principles, enriched with exactness (in a sense to be made explicit).
In Section 7, we say a few words about limitations of some of the principles under investigation. We separate the diagonal stationary reflection principle from $\mathsf {MM} $ , we show a localized version of this separation for the subcomplete fragment of these principles, and we show that the diagonal reflection principle of [Reference Cox3] does not limit the size of $2^{\omega _1}$ .
We close with a few open questions in Section 8.
2 Some background
This section summarizes some definitions and facts we will need. For more detail, we refer to [Reference Fuchs10]. We begin by introducing some notation around generalized stationarity (see [Reference Jech, Foreman, Kanamori and Magidor14] for an overview article).
Definition 2.1. Let $\kappa $ be a regular cardinal, and let $A\subseteq \kappa $ be unbounded. Let $\kappa \subseteq X$ . Then
is the lifting of A to $[X]^\omega $ . Now let $S\subseteq [X]^\omega $ be stationary. If $W\subseteq X\subseteq Y$ , then we define the projections of S to $[Y]^\omega $ and $[W]^\omega $ by
and
Definition 2.2. Let $\kappa $ be a regular uncountable cardinal, and let $S\subseteq [H_\kappa ]^\omega $ be stationary. A continuous $\in $ -chain through S of length $\lambda $ is a sequence ${\langle X_i\;|\;} {i<\lambda \rangle }$ of members of S, increasing with respect to $\in $ , such that for every limit $j<\lambda $ , $X_j=\bigcup _{i<j}X_i$ .
Definition 2.3 (Feng and Jech [Reference Feng and Jech5])
Let D be a set (usually of the form $H_\kappa $ , for some regular uncountable $\kappa $ ) with $\omega _1\subseteq D$ . Then a set $S\subseteq [D]^\omega $ with $\bigcup S=D$ is projective stationary (in D) if for every stationary set $T\subseteq \omega _1$ , the set $\{X\in S\;|\; X\cap \omega _1\in T\}$ is stationary.
The following is not the original formulation of $\mathsf {SRP} $ due to Todorčević, but it was shown by Feng and Jech to be an equivalent way of expressing the principle.
Definition 2.4. Let $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ be regular. Then the strong reflection principle at $\kappa $ , denoted $\mathsf {SRP} (\kappa )$ , states that whenever S is projective stationary in $H_\kappa $ , then there is a continuous $\in $ -chain of length $\omega _1$ through S. The strong reflection principle $\mathsf {SRP} $ states that $\mathsf {SRP} (\kappa )$ holds for every regular $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ .
Definition 2.5. Let $\Gamma $ be a class of forcing notions. The forcing axiom for $\Gamma $ , denoted $\mathsf {FA}(\Gamma )$ , states that whenever ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ is a forcing notion in $\Gamma $ and ${\langle D_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ is a sequence of dense subsets of ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , there is a filter $F\subseteq {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ such that for all $i<\omega _1$ , $F\cap D_i\neq \emptyset $ .
Definition 2.6. We write $\mathsf {SSP} $ for the class of all forcing notions that preserve stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ .
The principle $\mathsf {FA}(\mathsf {SSP} )$ is known as Martin’s Maximum, $\mathsf {MM} $ . The next definition introduces the canonical forcing that can be used to show that Martin’s Maximum implies $\mathsf {SRP} $ .
Definition 2.7. ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}_S$ is the forcing notion consisting of continuous $\in $ -chains through S of countable successor length, ordered by end-extension.
Fact 2.8 (Feng and Jech)
Let $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ be an uncountable regular cardinal. Then a stationary set $S\subseteq [H_\kappa ]^\omega $ is projective stationary iff ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}_S\in \mathsf {SSP} $ .
The concept of projective stationarity was generalized in [Reference Fuchs10] as follows.
Definition 2.9. Let $\Gamma $ be a forcing class. Then a stationary subset S of $H_\kappa $ , where $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ is regular, is $\Gamma $ -projective stationary iff ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}_S\in \Gamma $ .
Generalizing the above formulation of $\mathsf {SRP} $ , we arrive at the fragments of this principle, as introduced in [Reference Fuchs10].
Definition 2.10. Let $\Gamma $ be a forcing class. Let $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ be regular. The strong reflection principle for $\Gamma $ at $\kappa $ , denoted $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {SRP} (\kappa )$ , states that whenever $S\subseteq [H_\kappa ]^\omega $ is $\Gamma $ -projective stationary, then S contains a continuous chain of length $\omega _1$ . The strong reflection principle for $\Gamma $ , $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {SRP} $ , states that $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {SRP} (\kappa )$ holds for every $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ .
By design, $\mathsf {FA}(\Gamma )$ implies $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {SRP} $ . Let us now turn to subcompleteness and its simplification, $\infty $ -subcompleteness, introduced in [Reference Fuchs and Switzer12].
Definition 2.11. A transitive model N of ${\mathsf {ZFC} }^- $ is full if there is an ordinal $\gamma>0$ such that $L_\gamma (N)\models {\mathsf {ZFC} }^- $ and N is regular in $L_\gamma (N)$ , meaning that if $a\in N$ , $f:a\longrightarrow N$ and $f\in L_\gamma (N)$ , then $ {\mathrm ran} (f)\in N$ . A set X is full if the transitive isomorph of $ {\langle X,\in \cap X^2 \rangle } $ is full.
Definition 2.12. The density of a poset ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , denoted $\delta ({\mathord {\mathbb P}})$ , is the least cardinal $\delta $ such that there is a dense subset of ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ of size $\delta $ .
Definition 2.13. A forcing notion ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ is subcomplete if there is a cardinal $\theta $ which verifies the subcompleteness of ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , which means that ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}\in H_\theta $ , and for any ${\mathsf {ZFC} }^- {}$ model $N=L_\tau ^A$ with $\theta <\tau $ and $H_\theta \subseteq N$ , any $\sigma :{\bar {N}}\prec N$ such that ${\bar {N}}$ is countable, transitive and full and such that ${\mathord {\mathbb P}},\theta ,\eta \in {\mathrm ran} (\sigma )$ , any $\bar {G}\subseteq \bar {{\mathord {\mathbb P}}}$ which is $\bar {{\mathord {\mathbb P}}}$ -generic over ${\bar {N}}$ , any $\bar {s}\in {\bar {N}}$ , and any ordinals ${\bar {\lambda }}_0,\ldots ,{\bar {\lambda }}_{n-1}$ such that ${\bar {\lambda }}_0= {\mathrm On} \cap {\bar {N}}$ and ${\bar {\lambda }}_1,\ldots ,{\bar {\lambda }}_{n-1}$ are regular in ${\bar {N}}$ and greater than $\delta (\bar {{\mathord {\mathbb P}}})^{\bar {N}}$ , the following holds. Letting $\sigma ( {\langle \bar {\theta },\bar {{\mathord {\mathbb P}}},\bar {\eta } \rangle } )= {\langle \theta ,{\mathord {\mathbb P}},\eta \rangle } $ , and setting $\bar {S}= {\langle \bar {s},\bar {\theta },\bar {{\mathord {\mathbb P}}} \rangle } $ , there is a condition $p\in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ such that whenever $G\subseteq {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ is ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ -generic over $\mathrm {V} $ with $p\in G$ , there is in $\mathrm {V} [G]$ a $\sigma '$ such that:
-
(1) $\sigma ':{\bar {N}}\prec N$ ,
-
(2) $\sigma '(\bar {S})=\sigma (\bar {S})$ ,
-
(3) $(\sigma ')"\bar {G}\subseteq G$ ,
-
(4) $\sup \sigma "{\bar {\lambda }}_i=\sup \sigma '"{\bar {\lambda }}_i$ for each $i<n$ .
${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ is $\infty $ -subcomplete iff the above holds, with condition (4) removed.
We denote the classes of subcomplete and $\infty $ -subcomplete forcing notions by $\mathsf {SC} $ and $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ , respectively.
The following definition, again from [Reference Fuchs10], is designed to capture $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ -projective stationarity.
Definition 2.14. Let D be a set (usually of the form $D=H_\kappa $ , for some uncountable regular cardinal $\kappa $ ). A set $S\subseteq [D]^\omega $ with $\bigcup S=D$ is spread out (in D) if for every sufficiently large cardinal $\theta $ with $S\in H_\theta $ , whenever $\tau $ , A, $X,$ and a are such that $H_\theta \subseteq L_\tau ^A=N\models {\mathsf {ZFC} }^- $ , $\theta <\tau $ , $S,a,\theta \in X$ , $N|X\prec N$ , and $N|X$ is countable and full, then there are a Y such that $N|Y\prec N$ and an isomorphism $\pi :N|X\longrightarrow N|Y$ such that $\pi (a)=a$ and $Y\cap H_\kappa \in S$ .
The remaining definitions and results are from [Reference Fuchs10].
Definition 2.15. Let D be a set. A set $S\subseteq [D]^\omega $ with $\bigcup S=D$ is weakly spread out if there is a set b such that the condition described in Definition 2.14 is true of all X with $S,\theta ,b\in X$ .
Fact 2.16. Let $\kappa $ be an uncountable regular cardinal. A stationary set $S\subseteq [H_\kappa ]^\omega $ is spread out iff it is weakly spread out.
The following theorem is the analog of Fact 2.8 for $\infty $ -subcompleteness, giving us a combinatorial characterization of $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ -projective stationarity.
Theorem 2.17. Let $\kappa $ be an uncountable regular cardinal, and let $S\subseteq [H_\kappa ]^\omega $ . Then S is spread out iff S is $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ -projective stationary.
Spread out sets are stationary, and in fact projective stationary.
Observation 2.18 [Reference Fuchs10, Observation 2.28]
If a set $S\subseteq [D]^\omega $ is spread out in D, with $\omega _1\subseteq D$ , then S is projective stationary in D.
Spread out sets satisfy some natural closure properties.
Observation 2.19. Let $\kappa $ be an uncountable regular cardinal, let $S\subseteq [H_\kappa ]^\omega $ be spread out, and let $C\subseteq [H_\kappa ]^\omega $ be club. Then $S\cap C$ is spread out.
Observation 2.20. Let $A\subseteq B\subseteq C$ , and suppose S is spread out in B. Then both $S\mathbin {\downarrow }[A]^\omega $ and $S\mathbin {\uparrow }[C]^\omega $ are spread out.
The natural analogs of these closure properties are known to hold for projective stationary sets as well. We will use the following standard notation frequently.
Definition 2.21. Let $\kappa $ be an ordinal, and let $\rho $ be a regular cardinal. Then we write
The following provides an important collection of spread out sets.
Lemma 2.22. Let $\kappa>2^\omega $ be a regular cardinal, and let $B\subseteq S^\kappa _\omega $ be stationary. Then the set
is spread out.
3 The diagonal strong reflection principle for a forcing class
The idea for the diagonal strong reflection principle is that instead of guaranteeing the existence of a continuous $\in $ -chain of length $\omega _1$ through each projective stationary set individually, it postulates the existence of such a sequence through a whole collection $\mathcal {S}$ of (appropriate) sets. The way the sequence passes through the sets is designed so as to give it a “diagonal” flavor. The following definition makes this precise.
Definition 3.1. Let $\mathcal {S}$ be a collection of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ . Let ${\vec {T}}={\langle T_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ be a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , and let X be a set. Then $ {\langle \vec {Q},{\vec {S}} \rangle } $ is a diagonal chain through $\mathcal {S}$ up to X with respect to ${\vec {T}}$ if:
-
(1) $\vec {Q}={\langle Q_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ is a continuous $\in $ -chain of countable subsets of $H_\kappa $ :
-
(a) For all $i<\omega _1$ , $Q_i\in Q_{i+1}$ .
-
(b) And for limit $\lambda <\omega _1$ , $Q_\lambda =\bigcup _{i<\lambda }Q_i$ .
-
-
(2) ${\vec {S}}={\langle S_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ is a sequence of members of $\mathcal {S}$ , such that whenever $i\in T_j$ , then $Q_i\in S_j$ .
-
(3) $H_\kappa \cap X=\bigcup _{\alpha <\omega _1}Q_\alpha $ , and for all $\alpha <\omega _1$ , ${\langle Q_i\;|\;} {i<\alpha \rangle }\in H_\kappa \cap X$ .
-
(4) $\mathcal {S}\cap X=\{S_i\;|\; i<\omega _1\}$ .
We also formulate a slightly simpler version of this concept, independent of the particular sequence ${\vec {T}}$ . All we need is $\mathcal {S}$ , a collection of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ . Then ${\langle Q_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ is a diagonal chain through $\mathcal {S}$ up to X if:
-
(1) $\vec {Q}={\langle Q_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ is a continuous $\in $ -chain of countable subsets of $H_\kappa $ .
-
(2) For every $S\in X\cap \mathcal {S}$ , the set $\{i<\omega _1\;|\; Q_i\in S\}$ is stationary in $\omega _1$ .
-
(3) $H_\kappa \cap X=\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}Q_i$ , and for all $\alpha <\omega _1$ , ${\langle Q_i\;|\;} {i<\alpha \rangle }\in H_\kappa \cap X$ .
Such a chain is exact if in addition,
-
(4) for every $i<\omega _1$ , $Q_i\in \bigcup (X\cap \mathcal {S})$ .
Observation 3.2. Let $\mathcal {S}$ , $\kappa $ , ${\vec {T}}$ be as in Definition 3.1, and suppose that $ {\langle \vec {Q},{\vec {S}} \rangle } $ is a diagonal chain through $\mathcal {S}$ up to X with respect to ${\vec {T}}$ . Then $:$
-
(1) $\vec {Q}$ is a diagonal chain through $\mathcal {S}$ up to X.
-
(2) If $\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i=\omega _1$ , then $\vec {Q}$ is an exact diagonal chain through $\mathcal {S}$ up to X.
-
(3) If $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ is regular, $ {\langle H_\kappa \cap X,\in \rangle } \prec {\langle H_\kappa ,\in \rangle } $ , ${\vec {T}}\in X$ and $\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ contains a club, then there is a diagonal chain $ {\langle {\vec {R}},{\vec {S}} \rangle } $ through $\mathcal {S}$ up to X with respect to some ${\langle \bar {T}_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ such that $\bigcup \bar {T}_i=\omega _1$ . Hence, ${\vec {R}}$ is an exact diagonal chain through $\mathcal {S}$ up to X.
Proof We outline the straightforward proof of (3). By elementarity of $H_\kappa \cap X$ , and since ${\vec {T}}\in X$ , it follows that there is a club $C\subseteq \bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ in X. Hence, the monotone enumeration f of C is also in X. Define for $i<\omega _1$ :
It is then easy to check that $\vec {{\bar {T}}}$ is a partition of $\omega _1$ into stationary sets and $ {\langle {\vec {R}},{\vec {S}} \rangle } $ is a diagonal chain through $\mathcal {S}$ with respect to $\vec {{\bar {T}}}$ , as wished. Since $f\in X$ and for all $\alpha <\omega _1$ , $\vec {Q}{\restriction }\alpha \in X$ , it follows that for all $\alpha <\omega _1$ , ${\vec {R}}{\restriction }\alpha \in X$ , as $ {\langle H_\kappa \cap X,\in \rangle } \prec {\langle H_\kappa ,\in \rangle } $ .
We introduce a canonical forcing to add diagonal chains. It is a variation of a forcing notion from Cox [Reference Cox3], which, in turn, is based on a poset defined by Foreman [Reference Foreman6].
Definition 3.3. Let $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ be regular, $\vec {T} = \langle T_i \ : \ i < \omega _1 \rangle $ be sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , and let $\mathcal {S}$ be a nonempty collection of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ . The poset $\mathbb {P}^{\mathsf {DSRP} }_{\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}}}$ consists of conditions of the form
where, for some $\delta ^p,\lambda ^p<\omega _1$ :
-
(1) $\vec {Q}^p={\langle Q^p_\alpha \;|\;} {\alpha \le \delta ^p\rangle }$ is a continuous $\in $ -chain of elements of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ .
-
(2) $\vec {S}^p={\langle S^p_i\;|\;} {i<\lambda ^p\rangle }$ is a sequence such that for every $i<\lambda ^p$ , $S^p_i\in \mathcal {S}$ .
-
(3) Whenever $\alpha \le \delta ^p$ and $i<\omega _1$ are such that $\alpha \in T_i$ , then $i<\lambda ^p$ and $Q^p_\alpha \in S^p_i$ .
The ordering is by extension of functions in both coordinates.
Let us note some basic properties of this forcing notion.
Fact 3.4. Let $\kappa $ be an uncountable regular cardinal, $\emptyset \neq \mathcal {S}\subseteq {\mathcal {P}}([H_\kappa ]^\omega )$ a collection of stationary subsets, and ${\vec {T}}$ an $\omega _1$ -sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , and let ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}={\mathord {\mathbb P}}^{\mathsf {DSRP}}_{\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}}}$ . Then $:$
-
(1) For every countable ordinal $\gamma $ , the set of conditions p with $\delta ^p,\lambda ^p\ge \gamma $ is dense in ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}_S$ .
-
(2) For every $a\in H_\kappa $ , the set of conditions p such that there is an $\alpha \le \delta ^p$ with $a\in Q^p_\alpha $ is dense in ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ .
-
(3) For every $S\in \mathcal {S}$ , the set of conditions p such that there is an $i<\lambda ^p$ such that $S^p_i=S$ is dense.
Proof We need some facts before being able to prove this. The first fact is a generalization of a result from [Reference Friedman8].
Fact 1: Let ${\langle A_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ be a sequence of stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , and let $t:\omega _1\longrightarrow \omega _1$ be a function. Then, for any $\beta ,\alpha <\omega _1$ , with $\alpha>0$ , there is a normal (that is, strictly increasing and continuous) function $f:\alpha \longrightarrow \omega _1$ such that for all $\xi <\alpha $ , $f(\xi )\in A_{t(\xi )}$ and $f(0)>\beta $ .
Proof of Fact 1
Let $\gamma ,\alpha ,\sigma $ be countable ordinals, $\alpha $ a limit. Say that $\gamma $ is $\alpha $ -approachable from $\sigma $ if for every $\delta <\gamma $ , there is a normal function $f:[\sigma ,\sigma +\alpha ]\longrightarrow [\delta ,\gamma ]$ such that for all $\xi \in [\sigma ,\sigma +\alpha ]$ , $f(\xi )\in A_{t(\xi ),}$ and $f(\sigma +\alpha )=\gamma $ . We refer to such a function as a nice function from $[\sigma ,\sigma +\alpha ]$ to $[\delta ,\gamma ]$ .
We will prove by induction on limit ordinals $\alpha <\omega _1$ : for every $\sigma <\omega _1$ , the set of $\lambda <\omega _1$ such that $\lambda $ is $\alpha $ -approachable from $\sigma $ is unbounded in $\omega _1$ . This clearly proves Fact 1.
If $\alpha =\omega $ , then let $\sigma <\omega _1$ be given. Fixing any $\beta <\omega _1$ , we have to find a countable $\lambda \ge \beta $ that is $\alpha $ -approachable from $\sigma $ . To this end, let
Given any $\delta <\lambda $ , it is then easy to define $f:[\sigma ,\sigma +\omega ]\longrightarrow [\delta ,\lambda ]$ recursively so that f is strictly increasing, $f(\sigma )>\delta $ , for $\xi <\omega $ , $f(\xi )\in A_{t(\xi )}$ , and $\sup \{f(\sigma +n)\;| n<\omega \}=\lambda $ . Thus, setting $f(\sigma +\omega )=\lambda $ yields a nice function from $[\sigma ,\sigma +\omega ]$ to $[\delta ,\lambda ]$ , as wished.
Now suppose this has been proven for $\alpha $ . We have to show the claim for $\alpha +\omega $ . To this end, fix $\sigma <\omega _1$ . Given an arbitrary $\beta <\omega _1$ , we have to find a countable $\lambda \ge \beta $ which is $\alpha +\omega $ -approachable from $\sigma $ . Let $D=\{\gamma <\omega _1\;|\;\gamma $ is $\alpha $ -approachable from $\sigma $ }. Inductively, this set is unbounded in $\omega _1$ . Let
To see that $\lambda $ is $\alpha +\omega $ -approachable from $\sigma $ , let $\delta <\lambda $ . Let $\gamma \in (D\cap \lambda )\setminus (\delta +1)$ . Since $\gamma $ is $\alpha $ -approachable from $\sigma $ , there is a nice function ${\bar {f}}$ from $[\sigma ,\sigma +\alpha ]$ to $[\delta ,\gamma ]$ . As in the case $\alpha =\omega $ , we can extend ${\bar {f}}$ to a normal and cofinal function ${\bar {f}}':[\sigma ,\sigma +\alpha +\omega )\longrightarrow \lambda $ , such that for each $n<\omega $ , ${\bar {f}}'(\sigma +\alpha +n)\in A_{t(\sigma +\alpha +n)}$ . Since $\lambda =\sup {\mathrm ran} ({\bar {f}}')$ and $\lambda \in A_{t(\sigma +\alpha +\omega )}$ , we can extend ${\bar {f}}'$ to a nice function from $[\sigma ,\sigma +\alpha +\omega ]$ to $[\delta ,\lambda ]$ by specifying that $f(\sigma +\alpha +\omega )=\lambda $ .
Finally, suppose $\alpha $ is a limit of limit ordinals, and the claim has been proven for all limit ordinals below $\alpha $ . Fixing $\sigma ,\beta <\omega _1$ , we have to find a countable $\lambda>\beta $ which is $\alpha $ -approachable from $\sigma $ . Let ${\langle s_n\;|\;} {n<\omega \rangle }$ be increasing and cofinal in $\alpha $ , $s_0=0$ . Let $\sigma _n=\sigma +s_n$ . Let
Inductively, $D_n$ is unbounded in $\omega _1$ , for each $n<\omega $ . Let
To see that $\lambda $ is $\alpha $ -approachable from $\sigma $ , fix $\delta <\lambda $ . Find an increasing sequence ${\langle \delta _n\;|\;} {n<\omega \rangle }$ cofinal in $\lambda $ such that $\delta _0>\delta $ and $\delta _n\in D_n$ , for all $n<\omega $ . Using the definition of $D_n$ , we can now find a sequence of functions ${\langle f_n\;|\;} {n<\omega \rangle }$ such that:
-
• $f_n$ is a nice function from $[\sigma _n,\sigma _{n+1}]$ to $[\delta _n,\delta _{n+1}]$ .
-
• $f_{n+1}(\sigma _{n+1})=\delta _{n+1}=f_n(\sigma _{n+1})$ .
Thus, the union $\bigcup _{n<\omega }f_n$ is a function that can be extended to a nice function from $[\sigma ,\sigma +\alpha ]$ to $[\delta ,\lambda ]$ by mapping $\sigma +\alpha $ to $\lambda $ .
Fact 2: If ${\langle S_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ is a sequence of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ and ${\langle T_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ is a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , then for any $\gamma <\omega _1$ , there is a continuous $\in $ -chain ${\langle Q_\alpha \;|\;} {\alpha <\gamma \rangle }$ such that for all $\alpha <\gamma $ , if $\alpha \in T_i$ , then $Q_\alpha \in S_i$ .
Proof of Fact 2
This is a strengthening of [Reference Feng and Jech5, Lemma 1.2], and the proof of that lemma can be adapted to the present situation. Let ${\mathord {\mathbb Q}}$ be the forcing to add a continuous $\in $ -chain of countable subsets of $H_\kappa $ , of length $\omega _1$ , by initial segments of successor length. This forcing is $\sigma $ -closed. Let ${\langle Q_\alpha \;|\;} {\alpha <\omega _1\rangle }$ be a sequence added by ${\mathord {\mathbb Q}}$ , i.e., $\vec {Q}=\bigcup G$ , for some ${\mathord {\mathbb Q}}$ -generic G. In $V[G]$ , every $S_i$ is still stationary, so the set $A_i=\{\alpha <\omega _1\;|\; Q_\alpha \in S_i\}$ is stationary in $V[G]$ . So by Fact 1, applied in $V[G]$ to the function $t:\omega _1\longrightarrow \omega _1$ defined by
there is a normal function $f:\gamma \longrightarrow \omega _1$ such that for all $\alpha <\gamma $ , $f(\alpha )\in A_{t(\alpha )}$ , which means that if $\alpha \in T_i$ , then $f(\alpha )\in A_i$ , and this means that $Q_{f(\alpha )}\in S_i$ . So, the sequence $\vec {Q}'={\langle Q_{f(\alpha )}\;|\;} {\alpha <\gamma \rangle }$ is as wished, and it belongs to V, since ${\mathord {\mathbb Q}}$ is countably distributive.
We can now prove clauses (1), (2), and (3) simultaneously. Fix a condition $p\in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}_S$ , and let $\gamma <\omega _1$ , $a\in H_\kappa $ and $S\in \mathcal {S}$ be given. We may assume that $\gamma>\delta ^p$ . We may also assume that $\delta ^p+1\in \bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ , for if not, then we may just define ${\vec {T}}'$ to be like ${\vec {T}}$ , except that $\delta ^p+1\in T^{\prime }_0$ , say. Then $p\in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}^{\mathsf {DSRP}}_{\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}}'}$ , and an extension of p in ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}^{\mathsf {DSRP}}_{\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}}'}$ with the desired properties is also an extension of p in ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}^{\mathsf {DSRP}}_{\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}}}$ . So let’s let $i_0$ be such that $\delta ^p+1\in T_{i_0}$ .
Since it is trivial to extend the second coordinate of a condition, we may assume that $\lambda ^p>\gamma $ , that for every $\alpha \le \gamma $ , if $i<\omega _1$ is such that $\alpha \in T_i$ , then $i<\lambda ^p$ , and that there is some $i<\lambda ^p$ such that $S^p_i=S$ , taking care of clause (3). In order to be able to use Fact 2 now, we have to perform a little index translation, shifting by $\delta ^p+1$ . Thus, let’s define a sequence ${\vec {T}}'={\langle T^{\prime }_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ by letting $T^{\prime }_i=\{\xi <\omega _1\;|\;(\delta ^p+1)+\xi \in T_i\}$ . Let’s also define ${\vec {S}}={\langle S_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ by
Clearly, ${\vec {S}}$ is a sequence of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ , and ${\vec {T}}'$ is a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , so we may apply Fact 2 to give us a continuous $\in $ -chain ${\langle R_\xi \;|\;} {\xi <{\bar {\gamma }}\rangle }$ , where ${\bar {\gamma }}=(\gamma +1)-(\delta ^p+1)$ , such that for all $i<{\bar {\gamma }}$ , if $i\in T^{\prime }_j$ , then $R_i\in S_j$ . The condition $q= {\langle \vec {Q}^p{{}^\frown }{\vec {R}},{\vec {S}}^p \rangle } $ is then an extension of p with all the desired properties. This is because for $i<{\bar {\gamma }}$ , if $\delta ^p+1+i\in T_j$ , then $i\in T^{\prime }_j$ , so that $Q^q_{\delta ^p+1+i}=R_i\in S_j=S^q_j$ , and in particular, $Q^q_{\delta ^p}=Q^p_{\delta ^p}\in Q^q_{\delta ^p+1}$ , as $Q^q_{\delta ^p+1}\in S_{i_0}$ .
The following lemma is an immediate consequence of Fact 3.4.
Lemma 3.5. Let G be generic for $\mathbb {P}^{\mathsf {DSRP} }_{\mathcal {S},\vec {T}}$ , where $\mathcal {S}$ is a nonempty collection of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ and ${\vec {T}}$ is an $\omega _1$ -sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ . Let $\vec {Q}=\bigcup _{p\in G}\vec {Q}^p$ and ${\vec {S}}=\bigcup _{p\in G}{\vec {S}}^p$ . Then $:$
-
(1) $\vec {Q}$ is a continuous $\in $ -chain of length $\omega _1^V$ whose union is $H_\kappa ^V$ .
-
(2) ${\vec {S}}$ is a sequence of length $\omega _1^V$ , and $\mathcal {S}=\{S_i\;|\; i<\omega _1^V\}$ .
-
(3) For all $i<\omega _1$ and all $\alpha \in T_i$ , we have that $Q_\alpha \in S_i$ .
We should now define the instances of the diagonal strong reflection principle.
Definition 3.6. Let $\mathcal {S}$ be a collection of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ , where $\kappa>\omega _1$ is regular, ${\vec {T}}$ is an $\omega _1$ -sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , and $\theta $ a sufficiently large regular cardinal (so that $\mathcal {S}\subseteq H_\theta $ , that is, $\theta>2^{{<}\kappa }$ ). Then the diagonal strong reflection principle for $ {\langle \mathcal {S},{\vec {T}} \rangle } $ , $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}})$ , says that
is stationary in $H_\theta $ .
The diagonal strong reflection principle for $\mathcal {S}$ , $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ , says that
is stationary in $H_\theta $ .
The exact diagonal strong reflection principle for $\mathcal {S}$ , $\mathsf {eDSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ , says that
is stationary in $H_\theta $ .
Remark 3.7. Let $\mathcal {S}$ , $\kappa $ and ${\vec {T}}$ be as in Definition 3.6. Then we have the following implications:
-
(1) $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}})\implies \mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S}).$
-
(2) If $\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i=\omega _1$ , then $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}})\implies \mathsf {eDSRP} (\mathcal {S}).$
Lemma 3.8. Let $\mathcal {S}$ be a nonempty collection of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ , and let ${\vec {T}}$ be an $\omega _1$ -sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ such that $\mathsf {FA}(\{{\mathord {\mathbb P}}^{\mathsf {DSRP} }_{\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}}}\})$ holds. Then $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}})$ holds.
Proof Let ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}={\mathord {\mathbb P}}^{\mathsf {DSRP}}_{\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}}}$ . Let $\theta $ be a sufficiently large regular cardinal, and let $\mathcal {A}= {\langle H_\theta ,\in ,{\mathord {\mathbb P}},\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}},F,<^* \rangle } $ , where F is some function from $H_\theta ^{{<}\omega }$ to $H_\theta $ and $<^*$ is a well-order of $H_\theta $ . Let
To show that A is stationary, it suffices to show that there is an $X\in A$ such that $\mathcal {A}|X\prec \mathcal {A}$ and $X\cap \omega _2\in \omega _2$ (see [Reference Jech13, Exercise 38.10]). By the argument of the proof of [Reference Woodin20, Lemma 2.53], it follows from $\mathsf {FA}(\{{\mathord {\mathbb P}}\})$ that there is an $X\in [H_\theta ]^{\omega _1}$ with $\omega _1\subseteq X$ and $\mathcal {A}|X\prec \mathcal {A}$ , such that there is a G which is ( $X,{\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ )-generic (meaning that G is a filter in ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ such that for every dense subset $D\subseteq {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ with $D\in X$ , $G\cap D\cap X\neq \emptyset $ ). Since $\omega _1\subseteq X$ , it follows that $X\cap \omega _2\in \omega _2$ . To see that $X\in A$ , let $\vec {Q}=\bigcup _{p\in G}\vec {Q}^p$ and ${\vec {S}}=\bigcup _{p\in G}{\vec {S}}^p$ . It then follows from Lemma 3.5 that $ {\langle \vec {Q},{\vec {S}} \rangle } $ is a diagonal chain through $ {\langle X,\mathcal {S} \rangle } $ with respect to ${\vec {T}}$ . To see that for $\alpha <\omega _1$ , $\vec {Q}{\restriction }\alpha ={\langle Q_i\;|\;} {i<\alpha \rangle }\in H_\kappa \cap X$ , note that the set $D_\alpha $ of conditions $p\in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ with $\delta ^p\ge \alpha $ is dense in ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ and an element of X. Hence, there is a $p\in G\cap D_\alpha \cap X$ . The restriction of the first component of p to $\alpha $ is then also in X, and it is the sequence $\vec {Q}{\restriction }\alpha $ .
Definition 3.9. Let $\vec {T}$ be an $\omega _1$ -sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be regular, and let $\mathcal {S}\subseteq {\mathcal {P}}([H_\kappa ]^\omega )$ be a nonempty family of stationary sets. Let $\Gamma $ be a forcing class. Then we say that $ {\langle \mathcal {S},\vec {T} \rangle } $ is $\Gamma $ -projective stationary if ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}^{\mathsf {DSRP} }_{\mathcal {S},\vec {T}}\in \Gamma $ . We say that $\mathcal {S}$ is $\Gamma $ -projective stationary if there is a $\vec {T}$ such that $ {\langle \mathcal {S},\vec {T} \rangle } $ is $\Gamma $ -projective stationary.
Motivated by Lemma 3.8, it thus makes sense to define:
Definition 3.10. For a forcing class $\Gamma $ and a regular $\kappa>\omega _1$ , the $\Gamma $ -fragment of the diagonal strong reflection principle at $\kappa $ , $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa )$ , says that whenever $\mathcal {S}$ is a collection of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ and ${\vec {T}}$ is an $\omega _1$ -sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ such that $ {\langle \mathcal {S},{\vec {T}} \rangle } $ is $\Gamma $ -projective stationary, then $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}})$ holds.
And generally, $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} $ says that $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa )$ holds for every regular $\kappa>\omega _1$ .
If $\Gamma =\mathsf {SSP} $ , then we may omit mention of $\Gamma $ .
Another way to express Lemma 3.8 is as follows:
Lemma 3.11. Let $\Gamma $ be a forcing class. Then $\mathsf {FA}(\Gamma )$ implies $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} $ .
4 The stationary set preserving fragment of the diagonal strong reflection principle
The appeal of the principle $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} $ is that it can be formulated in a way that’s purely combinatorial and does not directly refer to the forcing class $\Gamma $ in the cases of main interest to us. We treat the case where $\Gamma $ is the class of all stationary set preserving forcing notions in the present section. Thus, we have to analyze which pairs $ {\langle \mathcal {S},\vec {T} \rangle } $ are $\mathsf {SSP} $ -projective stationary, and to this end, we will employ a few definitions.
Definition 4.1. Let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be regular, $S\subseteq [H_\kappa ]^\omega $ , and $A\subseteq \omega _1$ . Then S is projective stationary on A if for every set $B\subseteq A$ that is stationary in $\omega _1$ , the set $\{M\in S\;|\; M\cap \omega _1\in B\}$ is a stationary subset of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ .
Remark 4.2. Note that projective stationarity on A is vacuous unless A is a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ .
The following definition is designed to capture $\mathsf {SSP} $ -projective stationarity of pairs $ {\langle \mathcal {S},{\vec {T}} \rangle } $ .
Definition 4.3. Let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be regular, and let $\mathcal {S}\subseteq {\mathcal {P}}([H_\kappa ]^\omega )$ be a nonempty collection of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ . Let $\vec {T}$ be a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ . Then $\mathcal {S}$ is projective stationary on $\vec {T}$ if the following hold:
-
(a) For every $i<\omega _1$ , and for every $S\in \mathcal {S}$ , S is projective stationary on $T_i$ .
-
(b) $\bigcup \mathcal {S}$ is projective stationary on $\{\alpha \in \bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i\;|\;\forall \beta <\alpha \quad \alpha \notin T_\beta \}$ .
Note that clause (b) can be expressed as saying that $\bigcup \mathcal {S}$ is projective stationary on $\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i\setminus \bigtriangledown _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ , and is vacuous if this set is nonstationary (see Remark 4.2). Let’s say that ${\vec {T}}$ is maximal in this case. This is equivalent to saying that for every stationary subset $A\subseteq \bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ , there is an $i<\omega _1$ such that $A\cap T_i$ is stationary. In fact, maximality simplifies the whole concept considerably.
Remark 4.4. If $\kappa>\omega $ is regular, $\vec {T}$ is an $\omega _1$ -sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ that is maximal, and $\mathcal {S}$ is a collection of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ , then $\mathcal {S}$ is projective stationary on $\vec {T}$ iff every $S\in \mathcal {S}$ is projective stationary on $D=\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ .
Thus, if ${\vec {T}}$ is a maximal partition of $\omega _1$ into stationary sets, then $\mathcal {S}$ is projective stationary on ${\vec {T}}$ iff every $S\in \mathcal {S}$ is projective stationary.
Proof For the direction from left to right, if A is a stationary subset of D, then by maximality of $\vec {T}$ , there is an $i<\omega _1$ such that $A\cap T_i$ is stationary, so that condition (a) of Definition 4.3 implies that $\{M\in S\;|\; M\cap \omega _1\in A\}$ is stationary, for every $S\in \mathcal {S}$ . Vice versa, if $\mathcal {S}$ is projective stationary on D, then condition (a) of Definition 4.3 follows immediately, and by the remark above, condition (b) is vacuous by the maximality of $\vec {T}$ .
Maximal partitions always exist (see [Reference Fuchs10, Remark 3.17]), and we don’t have a use for nonmaximal ones, so the reader may think of this special case in what follows with no loss. Nevertheless, we carry out the analysis in the more general setting.
The assumptions of the following lemma could be weakened, but the present form suffices for our purposes.
Lemma 4.5. Let $\kappa $ be an uncountable regular cardinal, $\emptyset \neq \mathcal {S}\subseteq {\mathcal {P}}([H_\kappa ]^\omega )$ a collection of stationary subsets, and ${\vec {T}}$ an $\omega _1$ -sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , and let ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}={\mathord {\mathbb P}}^{\mathsf {DSRP}}_{\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}}}$ . If every $S\in \mathcal {S}$ is projective stationary on $T_0$ , then ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ is countably distributive.
Proof We have to show that, given a sequence $\vec {D}={\langle D_n\;|\;} {n<\omega \rangle }$ of dense open subsets of ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , the intersection $\Delta =\bigcap _{n<\omega }D_n$ is dense in ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ . So, fixing a condition $p\in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , we have to find a $q\le p$ in $\Delta $ . We may assume that $S=S^p_0$ is defined.
Let $\lambda $ be a regular cardinal much greater than $\kappa $ , say $\lambda>2^{2^{|{\mathord {\mathbb P}}|}}$ , and consider the model $\mathcal {N}= {\langle H_\lambda ,\in ,<^*,{\mathord {\mathbb P}},\vec {D},p \rangle } $ , where $<^*$ is a well-ordering of $H_\lambda $ .
Since $S'=\{X\in S\;|\; X\cap \omega _1\in T_0\}$ is stationary, we can let $\mathcal {M}=\mathcal {N}|X\prec \mathcal {N}$ be a countable elementary submodel with $X\cap H_\kappa \in S'$ , so that $X\cap \omega _1\in T_0$ .
Since $\mathcal {M}$ is countable, we can pick a filter G which is $\mathcal {M}$ -generic for ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ and contains p. Let
Using items (1) and (2) of Fact 3.4, it follows that $\delta := {\mathrm dom} (\vec {Q}^{\bar {q}})= {\mathrm dom} (\vec {S}^{\bar {q}})=X\cap \omega _1$ , and that $\bigcup _{i<\delta }Q^{\bar {q}}_i=X\cap H_\kappa \in S$ . Thus, if we set $q= {\langle \vec {Q}^{\bar {q}}{{}^\frown }(X\cap H_\kappa ),{\vec {S}}^{\bar {q}} \rangle } $ , then $q\in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , and q extends every condition in G. Moreover, since $D_n\in M$ , for each $n<\omega $ , it follows that G meets each $D_n$ , and hence that $p\ge q\in \Delta $ , as desired.
We are now ready to prove our characterization of the pairs that are $\mathsf {SSP} $ -projective stationary.
Theorem 4.6. Let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be regular, $\mathcal {S}\subseteq {\mathcal {P}}([H_\kappa ]^\omega )$ a nonempty collection of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ , and $\vec {T}$ an $\omega _1$ -sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ . The following are equivalent $:$
-
(1) $\mathcal {S}$ is projective stationary on $\vec {T}$ .
-
(2) $ {\langle \mathcal {S},\vec {T} \rangle } $ is $\mathsf {SSP} $ -projective stationary.
Proof Let $D=\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ , let $t:D\longrightarrow \omega _1$ be defined by $\alpha \in T_{t(\alpha )}$ , and set ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}={\mathord {\mathbb P}}^{\mathsf {DSRP} }_{\mathcal {S},\vec {T}}$ .
(1) $\implies $ (2): Let $A\subseteq \omega _1$ be stationary, $p\in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ and $\dot {C}\in \mathrm {V} ^{\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ such that $p\Vdash _{\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ “ $\dot {C}$ is a club subset of $\omega _1$ .” We will find a condition $q\le p$ in ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ that forces that $\dot {C}$ intersects $\check {A}$ . Let $\theta $ be a sufficiently large regular cardinal, say $\theta>2^{2^\kappa }$ .
Case 1: There is an $i_0<\omega _1$ such that $A\cap T_{i_0}$ is stationary.
In this case, fix such an $i_0$ . By assumption, for every $S\in \mathcal {S}$ , $\{M\in S\;|\; M\cap \omega _1\in A\cap T_{i_0}\}$ is stationary. By strengthening p if necessary, we may assume that $i_0<\lambda ^p$ . Let $N\prec {\langle H_\theta ,\in ,p,\dot {C},{\mathord {\mathbb P}},\mathcal {S},\vec {T},<^* \rangle } $ be a countable elementary submodel such that $M=N\cap H_\kappa \in S^p_{i_0}$ and $\delta =M\cap \omega _1\in A\cap T_{i_0}$ . Let g be ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ -generic over N with $p\in g$ , and let $\vec {Q}=\bigcup _{q\in g}\vec {Q}^q$ and $\vec {S}=\bigcup _{q\in g}\vec {S}^q$ . Then $\vec {Q}$ is a sequence of length $\delta $ , and $M=\bigcup _{i<\delta }Q_i\in S_{i_0}$ . So since $\delta \in T_{i_0}$ , $q= {\langle \vec {Q}{{}^\frown } M,\vec {S} \rangle } $ is a condition that strengthens p and forces that $\delta \in \dot {C}$ , since $\dot {C}^g$ is club in $\delta $ . Since $\delta \in A$ , this means that q forces that $\dot {C}$ intersects $\check {A}$ , as desired.
Case 2: $A\setminus D$ is stationary.
Let $N\prec {\langle H_\theta ,\in ,\mathcal {S},\vec {T},{\mathord {\mathbb P}},p,\dot {C},<^* \rangle } $ be countable with $N\cap \omega _1=\delta \in A\setminus D$ . Let $g\subseteq {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ be N-generic with $p\in g$ . Let $\vec {Q}=\bigcup _{q\in g}\vec {Q}^q$ and $\vec {S}=\bigcup _{q\in g}\vec {S}^q$ . Since $\delta = {\mathrm dom} (\vec {Q})\notin D$ , it follows that $q= {\langle \vec {Q}{{}^\frown }(N\cap H_\kappa ),{\vec {S}} \rangle } \in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , and since $\dot {C}^g$ is club in $\delta $ , it follows that q forces that $\check {\delta }\in \dot {C}$ , hence that $\check {A}\cap \dot {C}\neq \emptyset $ .
Case 3: Cases 1 and 2 fail.
Then $A\cap D$ is stationary and for all $i<\omega _1$ , $A\cap T_i$ is nonstationary. Fix, for every $i<\omega _1$ , a club $C_i\subseteq \omega _1$ disjoint from $A\cap T_i$ . Let $A^*=A\cap D\cap (\operatorname *{\mathrm {\bigtriangleup }}_{i<\omega _1}C_i)$ . Then $A^*$ is stationary and has the property that for all $\alpha \in A^*$ and all $\beta <\alpha $ , $\alpha \notin T_\beta $ . So $A^*\subseteq Z=\{\alpha \in D\;|\;\forall \beta <\alpha \ \alpha \notin T_\beta \}$ , and by condition (b) of Definition 4.3, $\bigcup \mathcal {S}$ is projective stationary on Z. Thus, we can pick a countable $N\prec {\langle H_\theta ,\in ,{\mathord {\mathbb P}},p,\dot {C},A^*,\mathcal {S},\vec {T} \rangle } $ such that $\delta =N\cap \omega _1\in A^*$ and $M=N\cap H_\kappa \in \bigcup \mathcal {S}$ . Let $S\in \mathcal {S}$ be such that $M\in S$ . Let $g\subseteq {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ be N-generic for ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ . Let $\vec {Q}=\bigcup _{q\in g}\vec {Q}^q$ and $\vec {S}=\bigcup _{q\in g}\vec {S}^q$ . Then $ {\mathrm dom} ({\vec {S}})= {\mathrm dom} (\vec {Q})=\delta \in A^*$ , and it follows that $t(\delta )\ge \delta $ . Thus, $t(\delta )\notin {\mathrm dom} (f)$ , and we can extend ${\vec {S}}$ to some ${\vec {S}}'$ of length $t(\delta )+1$ so that ${\vec {S}}'{\restriction }\delta ={\vec {S}}$ and $S^{\prime }_{t(\delta )}=S$ . We can then let $\vec {Q}'=\vec {Q}{{}^\frown } M$ , resulting in a condition $q= {\langle \vec {Q}',{\vec {S}}' \rangle } $ extending p and forcing that $\delta \in \dot {C}\cap \check {A}^*$ . Note that $A^*\subseteq A$ .
Thus, in each case, we have found an extension q of p forcing that $\dot {C}$ intersects $\check {A}$ . Thus, the stationarity of A is preserved by ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , and since this holds for any stationary subset of $\omega _1$ , ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ is stationary set preserving, that is, $ {\langle \mathcal {S},\vec {T} \rangle } $ is $\mathsf {SSP} $ -projective stationary.
(2) $\implies $ (1): Let ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ be stationary set preserving. We have to show that $\mathcal {S}$ is projective stationary on $\vec {T}$ . This amounts to proving the two conditions listed in Definition 4.3.
For condition (a), let $i<\omega _1$ , $S\in \mathcal {S}$ , and let $A\subseteq T_i$ be stationary. We have to show that $S_A=\{M\in S\;|\; M\cap \omega _1\in A\}$ is a stationary subset of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ . If not, then let $C\subseteq [H_\kappa ]^\omega $ be club with $S_A\cap C=\emptyset $ . Let G be ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ -generic over $\mathrm {V} $ , such that G contains a condition p with $i<\lambda ^p$ and $S^p_i=S$ . Let $\vec {Q}=\bigcup _{q\in G}\vec {Q}^q$ and $\vec {S}=\bigcup _{q\in G}\vec {S}^q$ . In $\mathrm {V} [G]$ , A is still stationary, so there is a
But then $\delta =Q_\delta \cap \omega _1$ and $Q_\delta \in C$ , and since $\delta \in A\subseteq T_i$ , we have that $Q_\delta \in S_i$ . So $Q_\delta \in S_A\cap C\neq \emptyset $ . Since C was arbitrary, this shows that $S_A$ is stationary, as claimed.
For condition (b), suppose $A\subseteq D$ is stationary in $\omega _1$ and has the property that for all $\alpha \in A$ and all $\beta <\alpha $ , $\alpha \notin T_\beta $ . Letting $S^*=\bigcup \mathcal {S}$ , we have to show that
is stationary. So let $C\subseteq [H_\kappa ]^\omega $ be club. Let G be ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ -generic, and let $\vec {Q}=\bigcup _{q\in g}\vec {Q}^q$ and $\vec {S}=\bigcup _{q\in g}\vec {S}^q$ . Let
This is possible, because A is stationary in $\mathrm {V} [G]$ . It follows that $\delta =Q_\delta \cap \omega _1\in A\subseteq D$ , so that $t(\delta )$ is defined and $Q_\delta \in S_{t(\delta )}\in \mathcal {S}$ . It follows that $Q_\delta \in S^*_A\cap C$ .
Remark 4.7. If the nonstationary ideal on $\omega _1$ is $\omega _2$ -saturated, then it was shown in [Reference Feng and Jech5] that for every stationary subset S of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ , where $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ is regular, there is a stationary set $D\subseteq \omega _1$ such that S is projective stationary on D. By the previous remark, if $\vec {T}$ is any partition of such a D into stationary sets, and this partition is maximal, then $\mathcal {S}=\{T\subseteq [H_\kappa ]^\omega \;|\; T\ \text {is projective stationary on }D\}$ is projective stationary on $\vec {T}$ , and $S\in \mathcal {S}$ .
5 The subcomplete fragment of the diagonal strong reflection principle
We will now carry out the analysis of Section 4 for the class of $\infty $ -subcomplete forcing, that is, $\Gamma =\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ . Thus, we have to find a description of the pairs $ {\langle \mathcal {S},\vec {T} \rangle } $ that are $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ -projective stationary. To this end, we first make the following definition, corresponding to the notion of projective stationarity on a subset of $\omega _1$ .
Definition 5.1. Let D be a set, usually of the form $H_\kappa $ , for some regular $\kappa>\omega _1$ , and let $T\subseteq \omega _1$ . Then a set $S\subseteq [D]^\omega $ with $\bigcup S=D$ is spread out on T if for all sufficiently large $\theta $ , whenever $\tau $ , A, X and a are such that $H_\theta \subseteq L_\tau ^A=N\models {\mathsf {ZFC} }^- $ , $S,a,T,\theta \in X\prec N$ , X is countable and full, and $X\cap \omega _1\in T$ , then there are a $Y\prec N$ and an isomorphism $\pi :N|X\longrightarrow N|Y$ such that $\pi (a)=a$ and $Y\cap D\in S$ .
As with projective stationarity on a nonstationary set, this notion is also vacuous in this case (see Remark 4.2).
Remark 5.2. Let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be regular, and let $S\subseteq [D]^\omega $ be stationary in D. If $T\subseteq \omega _1$ is nonstationary, then S is spread out on T.
Proof Let $\theta>\kappa $ , and let $\tau $ , A, $X,$ and a be as in Definition 5.1. In particular, $T\in X$ . By elementarity, X sees that T is not stationary, so there is a club set $C\subseteq \omega _1$ in X, disjoint from T. Letting $\delta =X\cap \omega _1$ , it follows that $C\cap \delta $ is unbounded in $\delta $ , and hence that $\delta \in C$ . Thus, $X\cap \omega _1\notin T$ , and hence, the condition stated in Definition 5.1 holds vacuously.
The following definition, which corresponds to Definition 4.3 in the stationary set preserving case, is designed to capture $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ -projective stationarity.
Definition 5.3. Let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be regular, $\mathcal {S}$ a nonempty collection of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ , and $\vec {T}$ a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ . Then $\mathcal {S}$ is spread out on $\vec {T}$ if:
-
(a) For every $i<\omega _1$ and for every $S\in \mathcal {S}$ , S is spread out on $T_i$ .
-
(b) $\bigcup \mathcal {S}$ is spread out on $\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i\setminus \bigtriangledown _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ .
As before, condition (b) is vacuous if $\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i\setminus \bigtriangledown _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ is nonstationary, that is, if ${\vec {T}}$ is maximal, and as before, maximality results in a considerable simplification of the concept.
Remark 5.4. Let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be regular, let ${\vec {T}}={\langle T_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ be a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ that is maximal, and let $\mathcal {S}$ be a collection of subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ . Then $\mathcal {S}$ is spread out on ${\vec {T}}$ iff every $S\in \mathcal {S}$ is spread out on $\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ .
Thus, if ${\vec {T}}$ is a maximal partition of $\omega _1$ into stationary sets, then $\mathcal {S}$ is spread out on ${\vec {T}}$ iff every $S\in \mathcal {S}$ is spread out.
Proof Set $D=\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ . For the implication from left to right, fix $S\in \mathcal {S}$ . Let $\theta $ be sufficiently large, and let $H_\theta \subseteq L_\tau ^A=N\models {\mathsf {ZFC} }^- $ . Let X be countable and full, with $N|X\prec N$ , and assume that $\theta , S, D\in X$ . Fix some $a\in X$ . By a version of Fact 2.16 may also assume that ${\vec {T}}\in X$ . But then, $Z=D\setminus \bigtriangledown _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ is also in X, and Z is nonstationary, by assumption. As in the proof of Remark 5.2, it follows that $\delta =X\cap \omega _1\notin Z$ . Now suppose that $\delta \in D$ . Since $\delta \notin Z$ , this means that $\delta \in T_{i_0}$ , for some $i_0<\delta $ . But since S is spread out on $T_{i_0}$ , there are $\pi $ , Y such that $\pi :N|X\longrightarrow N|Y\prec N$ is an isomorphism that fixes a, and such that $Y\cap H_\kappa \in S$ , as wished.
The converse is trivial, because if every $S\in \mathcal {S}$ is spread out on $\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ , then it is trivially also spread out on each $T_i$ (we may assume that D belongs to the relevant X). And condition (b) of Definition 5.3 is vacuous, since ${\vec {T}}$ is maximal.
As before, the reader may focus on the situation where ${\vec {T}}$ is maximal, but we treat the general case here.
Theorem 5.5. Let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be regular, $\vec {T}$ an $\omega _1$ -sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , and $\mathcal {S}$ a nonempty collection of stationary subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ . The following are equivalent $:$
-
(1) $\mathcal {S}$ is spread out on $\vec {T}$ .
-
(2) $ {\langle \mathcal {S},\vec {T} \rangle } $ is $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ -projective stationary.
Proof Let $D=\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ , let $t:D\longrightarrow \omega _1$ be defined by $\alpha \in T_{t(\alpha )}$ , and let ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}={\mathord {\mathbb P}}^{\mathsf {DSRP} }_{\mathcal {S},\vec {T}}$ . We treat each implication separately.
(1) $\implies $ (2): Assuming that $\mathcal {S}$ is spread out on $T_i$ , for every $i<\omega _1$ , we have to show that ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ is $\infty $ -subcomplete. To this end, let $\theta $ be large enough for Definition 5.1 to apply to every $T_i$ , every $S\in \mathcal {S}$ , as well as to $\bigcup \mathcal {S}$ and $D\setminus \bigtriangleup _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ . Let $N=L_\tau ^A\models {\mathsf {ZFC} }^- $ with $H_\theta \subseteq N$ , and let ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}\in X\prec N$ be countable and full. Let a be some member of X, and let $\sigma :{\bar {N}}\longrightarrow X$ be the inverse of the Mostowski collapse of X, ${\bar {N}}$ transitive. Let ${\bar {{\mathord {\mathbb P}}}}=\sigma ^{-1}({\mathord {\mathbb P}}_S)$ , $\bar {a}=\sigma ^{-1}(a)$ , and let ${\bar {G}}\subseteq {\bar {{\mathord {\mathbb P}}}}$ be ${\bar {N}}$ -generic. As usual, we may assume that certain parameters are in X (see [Reference Jensen, Chong, Feng, Slaman, Woodin and Yang17, p. 116, Lemma 2.5]). Here, we will assume that $\mathcal {S},\vec {T}\in X$ . Let ${\bar {\kappa }}=\sigma ^{-1}(\kappa )$ , $\bar {\mathcal {S}}=\sigma ^{-1}(\mathcal {S})$ and $\vec {\bar {T}}=\sigma ^{-1}(\vec {T})$ . It follows from Lemma 3.5 that if we set $\vec {\bar {Q}}=\bigcup \{\vec {Q}^{\bar {p}}\;|\;\bar {p}\in \bar {G}\}$ and $\vec {{\bar {S}}}=\bigcup \{{\vec {S}}^{\bar {p}}\;|\;\bar {p}\in \bar {G}\}$ , then $\vec {\bar {Q}}$ and $\vec {{\bar {S}}}$ are sequences of length $\omega _1^{\bar {N}}$ .
Let $\delta =X\cap \omega _1=\omega _1^{\bar {N}}$ .
Case 1: $\delta \notin D$ .
In this case we define
Then $q\in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , since $X\cap \omega _1\notin D$ . Moreover, q extends every member of $\sigma "\bar {G}$ . Thus, q forces that $\sigma $ itself satisfies the subcompleteness conditions (1)–(4) of Definition 2.13.
Case 2: $\delta \in D$ .
Let $i_0<\omega _1$ be such that $\delta \in T_{i_0}$ , that is, $i_0=t(\delta )$ .
Case 2.1: $i_0<\delta $ .
In this case, let $\bar {S}={\bar {S}}_{i_0}$ . $\bar {S}$ is then in $\bar {\mathcal {S}}$ , and so, $S=\sigma (\bar {S})\in \mathcal {S}\cap X$ . In particular, S is spread out on $T_{i_0}$ . Moreover, $T_{i_0}\in X$ . So, since $\delta =X\cap \omega _1\in T_{i_0}$ , we can choose a $Y\prec N$ with $Y\cap H_\kappa \in S$ and an isomorphism $\pi :N|X\longrightarrow N|Y$ that fixes a, S and ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ . Let $\sigma '=\pi \circ \sigma :{\bar {N}}\prec N$ . Let
Since $Y\cap H_\kappa \in S$ , it follows that $q\in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ (note that $X\cap \omega _1=Y\cap \omega _1=\delta \in T_{i_0}$ , and $Y\cap H_\kappa \in S=\sigma ({\bar {S}}_{i_0})=\sigma '({\bar {S}}_{i_0})$ ), and whenever $G\ni q$ is ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}_S$ -generic over $\mathrm {V} $ , then $\sigma '"{\bar {G}}\subseteq G$ . Since $\sigma '(\bar {a})=a$ , the conditions defining $\infty $ -subcompleteness are satisfied.
Case 2.2: $i_0\ge \delta $ .
In this case, $\delta \in Z=D\setminus \bigtriangledown _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ . By assumption, $\bigcup \mathcal {S}$ is spread out on Z. Moreover, $\bigcup {\mathcal {S}}$ and Z are in X. Let Y, $\sigma '$ be such that $\sigma ':N|X\longrightarrow N|Y$ is an isomorphism fixing a, $\mathsf {S}$ , ${\vec {T,}}$ and ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , and such that $Y\cap H_\kappa \in \bigcup \mathcal {S}$ . Let $S\in \mathcal {S}$ be such that $Y\cap H_\kappa \in S$ . Let ${\vec {S}}'$ be a sequence of length $i_0+1$ extending ${\langle \sigma '({\bar {S}}_i)\;|\;} {i<\delta \rangle }$ with $S^{\prime }_{i_0}=S$ and $S^{\prime }_i\in \mathsf {S}$ for every $i\le i_0$ . Let
Then q is a condition, forcing that $\sigma '"\bar {G}\subseteq \dot {G}$ .
(2) $\implies $ (1): To prove that condition (a) of Definition 5.3 holds, fix an $S\in \mathcal {S}$ and an $i_0<\omega _1$ . Let $\theta $ be large enough to verify that ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ is $\infty $ -subcomplete. Let $\tau ,a,X,A,N$ be as in Definition 5.1. So $X\prec N=L_\tau ^A$ is countable and full, $S,a,T_{i_0}\in X$ , and suppose that $\delta =X\cap \omega _1\in T_{i_0}$ , that is, $t(\delta )=i_0$ . By (a variation of) Fact 2.16, we may assume that X contains certain parameters we care about. So let us assume that $\mathcal {S},\vec {T}\in X$ . Since $T_{i_0}$ and $\vec {T}$ are in X, it follows that $i_0\in X$ , and hence that $i_0<\delta $ . Let $\sigma :{\bar {N}}\longrightarrow X$ be the transitive isomorph of X, and let $\bar {{\mathord {\mathbb P}}}$ , $\bar {S}$ , $\bar {\mathcal {S}}$ , $\vec {\bar {T}}$ be the preimages of ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , S, $\mathcal {S}$ , $\vec {T}$ under $\sigma $ , respectively.
Let $\bar {G}$ be $\bar {{\mathord {\mathbb P}}}$ -generic over ${\bar {N}}$ , containing a condition $\bar {p}$ such that $S^{\bar {p}}_{i_0}=\bar {S}$ . By assumption, there is a condition $q\in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ such that whenever G is ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ -generic over $\mathrm {V} $ and contains q, then there is in $\mathrm {V} [G]$ an elementary embedding $\sigma ':{\bar {N}}\longrightarrow N$ with $\sigma '(\bar {a})=a$ , $\sigma '(\bar {S})=S$ , $\sigma '(\bar {\mathcal {S}})=\mathcal {S}$ , $\sigma '(\vec {\bar {T}})={\vec {T}}$ , and such that $\sigma '"\bar {G}\subseteq G$ . Note that for any $S'\in \mathcal {S}$ , and any $i<\omega _1$ , $S'$ is projective stationary on $T_i$ , since $S'$ is even spread out on $T_i$ . This can be easily shown directly. Hence, by Lemma 4.5, ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ is countably distributive, so that $\sigma '$ already exists in $\mathrm {V} $ . We have already argued that the union of the first coordinates of conditions in $\bar {G}$ is of the form ${\langle \bar {Q}_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1^{\bar {N}}\rangle }$ , where $\bigcup _{i<\delta }\bar {Q}_i=H_{\bar {\kappa }}^{\bar {N}}$ , and that the union of the second coordinates is a sequence ${\langle \bar {S}_i\;|\;} {i<\delta \rangle }$ . Now let $r\in G$ be a condition with $\delta ^r\ge \delta $ , and let $Y= {\mathrm ran} (\sigma ')$ . Then
Moreover, $Y\cap \omega _1=X\cap \omega _1\in T_{i_0}$ , so that $Q^r_\delta \in S^r_{i_0}=\sigma '(\bar {Q}_{i_0})=S$ , by clause (3) of Definition 3.3. Thus, $Y\cap H_\kappa \in S$ , and letting $\pi =\sigma '\circ \sigma ^{-1}$ , we have that $\pi :N|X\prec N|Y$ is an isomorphism fixing a, showing that S is spread out on $T_{i_0}$ .
To prove condition (b) of Definition 5.3, we start in the same setup, but we assume that $\delta \in \bigcup _{i<\omega _1}T_i\setminus \bigtriangledown _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ , that is, $\delta \in T_{i_0}$ , where $i_0\ge \delta $ . Let ${\bar {G}}$ be generic over ${\bar {N}}$ for $\bar {{\mathord {\mathbb P}}}$ , and let $q\in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ force the existence of a $\sigma ':{\bar {N}}\prec N$ as before, moving $\vec {{\bar {T}}}$ , $\bar {{\mathord {\mathbb P}}}$ , $\bar {\mathcal {S}}$ and $\bar {a}$ the same way as $\sigma $ , and so that if G is ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ -generic with $q\in G$ , then $\sigma '"{\bar {G}}\subseteq G$ . As before, it follows that $\sigma '\in \mathrm {V} $ . Let $r\in G$ be such that $\delta ^r\ge \delta $ . It follows that, letting $Y= {\mathrm ran} (\sigma ')$ , $Q^r_\delta =Y\cap H_\kappa $ . So, since $\delta \in T_{i_0}$ , $i_0<\lambda ^r$ and $Q^r_\delta \in S^r_{i_0}\in \mathcal {S}$ . Hence, $Y\cap H_\kappa \in \bigcup \mathcal {S}$ , and $\pi =\sigma '\circ \sigma ^{-1}$ can serve as our wanted isomorphism.
6 Consequences of the $\Gamma $ -fragment of $\mathsf {DSRP} $
Now that we have characterizations of the pairs $ {\langle \mathcal {S},{\vec {T}} \rangle } $ that are $\Gamma $ -projective stationary, if $\Gamma $ is either the class of stationary set preserving or subcomplete forcing notions, we should like to describe some consequences of the corresponding $\Gamma $ -fragment of $\mathsf {DSRP} $ . First, let us summarize the most important consequence of what was done in Sections 4 and 5.
Theorem 6.1. Let $\Gamma $ be either the class of stationary set preserving or of $\inf $ -subcomplete forcing notions. Let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be regular, and suppose that $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa )$ holds. Then $:$
-
(1) If $\mathcal {S}\neq \emptyset $ is such that every $S\in \mathcal {S}$ is $\Gamma $ -projective stationary in $H_\kappa $ , then $\mathsf {eDSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ holds.
-
(2) If $A\subseteq \omega _1$ is a stationary set such that every $S\in \mathcal {S}\neq \emptyset $ is $\Gamma $ -projective stationary in $H_\kappa $ on A, then $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ holds.
Proof Part (1): if $\Gamma $ is the class of stationary set preserving forcing notions, then $\Gamma $ -projective stationarity is just the usual concept of projective stationarity. So let $\mathcal {S}$ be a nonempty collection of projective stationary sets in $H_\kappa $ . Let ${\vec {T}}$ be a maximal partition of $\omega _1$ into stationary sets. By Remark 4.4, $ {\langle \mathcal {S},{\vec {T}} \rangle } $ is $\mathsf {SSP} $ -projective stationary, so by assumption, $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}})$ holds. But since ${\vec {T}}$ is a partition of all of $\omega _1$ , this implies $\mathsf {eDSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ , by Remark 3.7.
The case where $\Gamma $ is the class of all $\inf $ -subcomplete forcing notions is handled similarly. This time, $\Gamma $ -projective stationarity means being spread out. Given $\mathcal {S}$ and a partition ${\vec {T}}$ as above, it follows by Remark 5.4 that $ {\langle \mathcal {S},{\vec {T}} \rangle } $ is $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ -projective stationary, so that $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}})$ holds, which again implies $\mathsf {eDSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ , as ${\vec {T}}$ is a partition of $\omega _1$ .
Part (2) is similar. We can work with a maximal partition ${\vec {T}}$ of A into stationary sets now.
The relationship between the diagonal strong reflection principle and other diagonal reflection principles is maybe best understood in an analogy to the relationship between the strong reflection principle and other reflection principles. In fact, it may be easiest to understand the difference by thinking about Friedman’s problem and the reflection principle, in the context of reflection of stationary sets of ordinals. Friedman’s problem at an uncountable regular cardinal $\kappa $ greater than $\omega _1$ says that whenever $A\subseteq S^\kappa _\omega $ is stationary, then there is a closed subset C of A of order type $\omega _1$ . Letting $\rho =\sup C$ , then, $A\cap \rho $ is stationary, that is, A reflects at $\rho $ . But $A\cap \rho $ is not only stationary; it contains a club. In preparation for the following subsections, let us define some concepts that capture the difference between reflection in the usual sense and the kind of reflection resulting from strong reflection principles. The terminology around exact reflection comes from [Reference Fuchs10, Definition 3.13].
Definition 6.2. Let $\kappa $ be an ordinal of uncountable cofinality, and let $A\subseteq \kappa $ be stationary in $\kappa $ . An ordinal $\rho <\kappa $ of uncountable cofinality is a reflection point of A if $A\cap \rho $ is stationary in $\rho $ . It is an exact reflection point of A if $A\cap \rho $ contains a club in $\rho $ . Given a regular cardinal $\delta $ , the $\delta $ -trace of A, $\operatorname {\mathrm {\mathsf {Tr}}}_\delta (A)$ , is the set of all reflection points of A that have cofinality $\delta $ , and the exact $\delta $ -trace of A, $\operatorname {\mathrm {\mathsf {eTr}}}_\delta (A)$ , is the set of all exact reflection points of A that have cofinality $\delta $ .
If $\mathcal {S}$ is a collection of stationary subsets of $\kappa $ , then $\rho $ is a simultaneous reflection point of $\mathcal {S}$ if $\rho $ is a reflection point of every $A\in \mathcal {S}$ . It is an exact simultaneous reflection point of $\mathcal {S}$ if it is a simultaneous reflection point of $\mathcal {S}$ and $(\bigcup \mathcal {S})\cap \rho $ contains a club in $\rho $ . Again fixing a regular cardinal $\delta $ , the $\delta $ -trace of $\mathcal {S}$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {\mathsf {Tr}}}_\delta (\mathcal {S})$ , is the set of all simultaneous reflection points of $\mathcal {S}$ that have cofinality $\delta $ , and the exact $\delta $ -trace of $\mathcal {S}$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {\mathsf {eTr}}}_\delta (\mathcal {S})$ , is the set of all exact simultaneous reflection points of $\mathcal {S}$ that have cofinality $\delta $ .
Since we will be mainly interested in the case that $\delta =\omega _1$ , we will drop mention of $\delta $ if $\delta =\omega _1$ , that is, $\operatorname {\mathrm {\mathsf {eTr}}}(\mathcal {S})$ means $\operatorname {\mathrm {\mathsf {eTr}}}_{\omega _1}(\mathcal {S})$ .
Thus, Friedman’s problem at $\kappa $ says that every stationary subset of $S^\kappa _\omega $ has an exact reflection point. In fact, let us define the exact versions of some classical reflection principles for stationary sets of ordinals.
Definition 6.3. Suppose $\lambda $ is a cardinal of uncountable cofinality. Let $A\subseteq \lambda $ . Let $\kappa $ be a cardinal, and let $\delta $ be a regular cardinal. Then $\mathsf {Refl}_\delta ({<}\kappa ,A)$ says that whenever $\mathcal {S}$ is a collection of stationary subsets of A that has cardinality less than $\kappa $ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {\mathsf {Tr}}}_\delta (\mathcal {S})\neq \emptyset $ . We write $\mathsf {Refl}_\delta (\kappa ,A)$ for $\mathsf {Refl}_\delta ({<}\kappa ^+,A)$ .
Similarly, $\mathsf {eRefl} _\delta ({<}\kappa ,A)$ says that whenever $\mathcal {S}$ is a collection of stationary subsets of A that has size less than $\kappa $ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {\mathsf {eTr}}}_\delta (\mathcal {S})\neq \emptyset $ . As before, we write $\mathsf {eRefl} _\delta (\kappa ,A)$ for $\mathsf {eRefl} _\delta ({<}\kappa ^+,A)$ .
And as before, we will drop mention of $\delta $ if $\delta =\omega _1$ , so that $\mathsf {eRefl} (\kappa ,A)$ means $\mathsf {eRefl} _{\omega _1}(\kappa ,A)$ .
We are here most concerned with the principles of the form $\mathsf {Refl}(\omega _1,A)$ and $\mathsf {eRefl} (\omega _1,A)$ . It is shown in [Reference Fuchs10] that $\mathsf {eRefl} (\omega _1,A)$ is equivalent to a simultaneous version of Friedman’s Problem that has its origins in [Reference Foreman, Magidor and Shelah7]:
Observation 6.4 [Reference Fuchs10, Observation 3.14]
Let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be regular and fix a stationary subset A of $\kappa $ . The following are equivalent $:$
-
(1) Whenever $\mathcal {S}=\{A_i\;|\; i<\omega _1\}$ is a set of stationary subsets of A, there is a partition ${\langle T_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ of $\omega _1$ into stationary sets and a normal function $f:\omega _1\longrightarrow \kappa $ such that for every $i<\omega _1$ , $f"T_i\subseteq A_i$ .
-
(2) $\mathsf {eRefl} (\omega _1,A)$ holds.
-
(3) For any set $\mathcal {S}$ of stationary subsets of A that has size $\omega _1$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {\mathsf {eTr}}}(\mathcal {S})$ is stationary in $\kappa $ .
Exact simultaneous reflection has consequences on cardinal arithmetic (and this was known since [Reference Foreman, Magidor and Shelah7], even though this was not filtered through the simultaneous exact reflection principle):
Fact 6.5 [Reference Fuchs10, Fact 3.15]
Let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be regular, and suppose there is a stationary $A\subseteq \kappa $ such that $\mathsf {eRefl} (\omega _1,A)$ holds. Then $\kappa ^{\omega _1}=\kappa $ .
It was shown in [Reference Foreman, Magidor and Shelah7] that $\mathsf {MM} $ implies $\mathsf {eRefl} (\omega _1,S^{\kappa }_\omega )$ , for any regular $\kappa>\omega _1$ . Todorčević showed that already $\mathsf {SRP} $ has this consequence, and in [Reference Fuchs10], it was shown that the $\infty $ -subcomplete fragment of $\mathsf {SRP} $ implies this for $\kappa>2^\omega $ .
The strong diagonal reflection principle is a principle of reflection of generalized stationarity, designed to capture exact versions of diagonal reflection. Note that an exact reflection point of some collection of stationary sets is a reflection point of each of those sets, but it is explicitly not a reflection point of the complement of the union of these stationary sets. Thus, principles of exact reflection provide selective reflection: points at which some sets reflect but others don’t. The diagonal reflection principles, introduced by the first author, talk about reflection of generalized stationarity, and in a sense, they try to maximize the collection of sets that reflect. They are thus not designed to produce phenomena of exact reflection. For example, they do not imply $\mathsf {eRefl} (\omega _1,A)$ , for any set A stationary in $\omega _2$ , since they don’t imply that $2^{\omega _1}=\omega _2$ , as we will show in Section 7 (compare with Fact 6.5).
We will present in the following two subsections some consequences of fragments of the diagonal strong reflection principle. First, we will focus on consequences that don’t have much to do with the exact reflection $\mathsf {DSRP} $ provides. These filter through certain versions of the diagonal reflection principle that were introduced in [Reference Cox3]. In the subsection after that, we will provide some applications that do make use of the exact quality of the reflection $\mathsf {DSRP} $ provides. These don’t follow from the principles of [Reference Cox3].
6.1 Consequences that filter through weak diagonal reflection principles
Let us begin by showing that $\mathsf {DSRP} $ implies various “weak” diagonal reflection principles of [Reference Cox3], as well as some slight modifications thereof. For the present purposes, we say that a set N is internally approachable if it is the union of an $\in $ -chain ${\langle N_\alpha \;|\;} {\alpha <\omega _1\rangle }$ such that for every $\alpha <\omega _1$ , ${\langle N_\xi \;|\;} {\xi <\alpha \rangle }\in N$ .
Lemma 6.6. Let $\kappa $ be regular, and let $\mathcal {S}\subseteq {\mathcal {P}}([H_\kappa ]^\omega )$ be a collection of stationary sets such that $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ holds. Then $:$
-
(1) The principle $\mathsf {w}\mathsf {DRP} _{\mathsf {IA}}(\mathcal {S})$ holds $:$ whenever $\theta $ is large enough that $\mathcal {S}\subseteq H_\theta $ , there are stationarily many $W\in [H_\theta ]^{\omega _1}$ such that $:$
-
(a) $W\cap H_\kappa $ is internally approachable.
-
(b) For every $S\in W\cap \mathcal {S}$ , $S\cap [W\cap H_\kappa ]^\omega $ is stationary in $W\cap H_\kappa $ .
-
-
(2) The following slight strengthening of $\mathsf {w}\mathsf {DRP} _{\mathsf {IA}}(\mathcal {S})$ holds: whenever $\theta $ is large enough that $\mathcal {S}\subseteq H_\theta $ , there are stationarily many $W\in [H_\theta ]^{\omega _1}$ such that for every $S\in W\cap \mathcal {S}$ and every regular ${\bar {\kappa }}\in W\cap [\omega _2,\kappa ]$ , $W\cap H_{\bar {\kappa }}$ is internally approachable and $(S\mathbin {\downarrow } H_{\bar {\kappa }})\cap [W\cap H_{\bar {\kappa }}]^\omega $ is stationary in $W\cap H_{\bar {\kappa }}$ .
Proof For (1), let $\theta $ be regular and large enough that $\mathcal {S}\subseteq H_\theta $ . We know by $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ that there are stationarily many $W\in [H_\theta ]^{\omega _1}$ such that $\omega _1\subseteq W$ and there is a diagonal chain $\vec {Q}$ through $\mathcal {S}$ up to W. We claim that each such W belongs to the set defined in (1). Note that $\vec {Q}$ witnesses that $W\cap H_\kappa $ is internally approachable. Now let $S\in W\cap \mathcal {S}$ . We have to show that $S\cap [W\cap H_\kappa ]^\omega $ is stationary in $W\cap H_\kappa $ . Let
Since $\vec {Q}$ is a diagonal chain through $\mathcal {S}$ up to W, T is stationary. Now let $f:[W\cap H_\kappa ]^{{<}\omega }\longrightarrow W\cap H_\kappa $ . We have to find an $x\in S\cap [W\cap H_\kappa ]^\omega $ that’s closed under f. Clearly, the set of $\alpha <\omega _1$ such that $f"[Q_\alpha ]^{{<}\omega }\subseteq Q_\alpha $ is club in $\omega _1$ . Hence, there is such an $\alpha $ in T. But then, $x=Q_\alpha \in S$ is as wished.
For (2), we argue mostly as above. Given a W as above, let $\vec {Q}$ be a diagonal chain through $\mathcal {S}$ up to W, and let ${\bar {\kappa }}\in [\omega _2,\kappa ]\cap W$ . Then the sequence ${\langle Q_\alpha \cap H_{\bar {\kappa }}\;|\;} {\alpha <\omega _1\rangle }$ witnesses that $W\cap H_{\bar {\kappa }}$ is internally approachable. Letting $S\in \mathcal {S}\cap W$ , and letting T be the stationary set of countable $\alpha $ such that $Q_\alpha \in S$ , we have that for all $\alpha \in T$ , $Q_\alpha \cap H_{\bar {\kappa }}\in S\mathbin {\downarrow } H_{\bar {\kappa }}$ . As above, given $f:[W\cap H_{\bar {\kappa }}]^{{<}\omega }\longrightarrow W\cap H_{\bar {\kappa }}$ , we can now find an $\alpha \in T$ such that $Q_\alpha \cap H_{\bar {\kappa }}$ is closed under f, and $Q_\alpha \cap H_{\bar {\kappa }}$ is then in $S\mathbin {\downarrow } H_{\bar {\kappa }}$ .
Remark 6.7. In the notation of the previous lemma, if $\mathcal {T}\subseteq \mathcal {S}$ , then $\mathsf {w}\mathsf {DRP} _{\mathsf {IA}}(\mathcal {S})\implies \mathsf {w}\mathsf {DRP} _{\mathsf {IA}}(\mathcal {T})$ .
This remark drives a point home that was made earlier: one cannot expect to get any phenomena of exact reflection from these principles. Yet they will, by design, imply certain diagonal reflection principles for sequences of stationary sets of ordinals.
Definition 6.8. The following collections of stationary sets will be focal for our analysis, for a regular cardinal $\kappa>\omega _1$ :
Furthermore, for a forcing class $\Gamma $ , let $\mathcal {S}_\Gamma (\kappa )$ be the collection of all $S\subseteq [H_\kappa ]^\omega $ that are $\Gamma $ -projective stationary in $H_\kappa $ .
In [Reference Cox3], $\mathsf {wDRP}_{\mathsf {IA}}(\kappa )$ was defined as $\mathsf {wDRP}_{\mathsf {IA}}(\mathcal {S}_{\mathsf {SSP}} (\kappa ))$ , and $\mathsf {wDRP}_{\mathsf {IA}}$ states that $\mathsf {wDRP}_{\mathsf {IA}}(\kappa )$ holds for every regular $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ . Thus, by Lemma 3.11, Theorem 4.6, and Lemma 6.6, we have the following implications:
for every regular $\kappa>\omega _1$ . If we similarly define $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {wDRP}_{\mathsf {IA}}(\kappa )$ to be the principle $\mathsf {wDRP}_{\mathsf {IA}}(\mathcal {S}_{\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} }(\kappa )$ , then we obtain the corresponding implications
for any regular $\kappa>\omega _1$ , using Lemma 3.11, Theorem 5.5, and Lemma 6.6.
We now aim to find a connection to diagonal reflection principles of stationary sets of ordinals. Combining Theorem 6.15, Lemma 2.22, and Lemma 6.6, we obtain:
Corollary 6.9. Suppose $\kappa $ is a regular cardinal greater than $2^\omega $ , and $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa )$ holds. Then $\mathsf {w}\mathsf {DRP} _{\mathsf {IA}}(\mathcal {S}_{\mathsf {lift}}(\kappa ))$ holds.
The same conclusion holds if $\kappa $ is a regular cardinal greater than $\omega _1$ and $\mathsf {SSP} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa )$ holds.
The principles of reflection of stationary sets of ordinals we are interested in here are of the following form.
Definition 6.10 (See [Reference Fuchs9, 11, 18])
Let $\lambda $ be a regular cardinal, let $S\subseteq \lambda $ be stationary, and let $\kappa <\lambda $ . The diagonal stationary reflection principle $\mathsf {DSR}({<}\kappa ,S)$ says that whenever $\langle S_{\alpha ,i}\;|\;\alpha <\lambda ,i<j_\alpha \rangle $ is a sequence of stationary subsets of S, where $j_\alpha <\kappa $ for every $\alpha <\lambda $ , then there are an ordinal $\gamma <\lambda $ of uncountable cofinality and a club $F\subseteq \gamma $ such that for every $\alpha \in F$ and every $i<j_\alpha $ , $S_{\alpha ,i}\cap \gamma $ is stationary in $\gamma $ .
The version of the principle in which $j_\alpha \le \kappa $ is denoted $\mathsf {DSR}(\kappa ,S)$ .
We will denote the collection of all ordinals less than some given ordinal $\lambda $ that have cofinality $\kappa $ , for some regular cardinal $\kappa $ , by $S^\lambda _\kappa $ . Usually, in the present context, the set S above will be of the form $S^\theta _\omega $ , for some regular $\theta>\omega _1$ .
If F is only required to be unbounded, then the resulting principle is called $\mathsf {uDSR}({<}\kappa ,S)$ , and if it is required to be stationary, then it is denoted $\mathsf {sDSR}({<}\kappa ,S)$ .
Of relevance to us is the fact that the principle $\mathsf {SRP} (\omega _1,S^{\omega _2}_\omega )$ is equivalent to the principle $\mathsf {OSR}_{\omega _2}$ of Larson [Reference Larson18]. Larson showed that this principle follows from Martin’s Maximum, but not from $\mathsf {SRP} $ . Adding to this, in [Reference Fuchs and Lambie-Hanson11, Theorem 4.4], it was shown that $\mathsf {SRP} $ does not imply $\mathsf {uDSR}(1,S^\lambda _\omega )$ , for $\lambda>\omega _2$ , while [Reference Fuchs9] shows that for $\lambda>2^\omega $ , $\mathsf {SCFA} $ implies even the stronger principle $\mathsf {DSR}(\omega _1,S^\lambda _\omega )$ . Thus, the strong reflection principles fail to capture these consequences of $\mathsf {MM} /\mathsf {SCFA} $ , and our goal is to show that the diagonal strong reflection principles do capture them; in fact, even $\mathsf {wDRP}_{\mathsf {IA}}$ is sufficient.
Note that the assumptions of the following theorem are satisfied if $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa )$ holds, or if $\kappa>2^\omega $ and $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa )$ holds, by Corollary 6.9.
Theorem 6.11. Let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be regular. Then $\mathsf {w}\mathsf {DRP} _{\mathsf {IA}}(\mathcal {S}_{\mathsf {lift}}(\kappa ))\implies \mathsf {DSR}(\omega _1,S^\kappa _\omega )$ .
Proof Let ${\vec {S}}={\langle S_{\alpha ,i}\;|\;} {\alpha <\theta ,i<\omega _1\rangle }$ be a matrix of stationary subsets of $S^\kappa _\omega $ . Let $\theta $ be a regular cardinal such that $\mathcal {S}_{\mathsf {lift}}(\kappa )\subseteq H_\theta $ . By $\mathsf {w}\mathsf {DRP} _{\mathsf {IA}}(\mathcal {S}_{\mathsf {lift}}(\theta ))$ , let $W\prec {\langle H_\kappa ,\in ,{\vec {S}} \rangle } $ satisfy clauses (1)(a) and (b) of Lemma 6.6.
Let $C=W\cap \kappa $ , and let $\gamma =\sup (C)<\kappa $ . Since W is internally approachable, it can be written as $W=\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}W_i$ , where $\vec {W}$ is a continuous elementary chain such that for all $i<\omega _1$ , $\vec {W}{\restriction } i\in W$ . Thus, if we let $\theta _i=\sup (W_i\cap \theta )$ , then $\bar {C}=\{\theta _i\;|\; i<\omega _1\}$ is a closed unbounded subset of C, and since $\vec {\theta }$ is strictly increasing, the cofinality of $\gamma $ is $\omega _1$ .
-
(1) For every $\alpha \in C$ , and for every $i<\omega _1$ , $S_{\alpha ,i}\cap \gamma $ is stationary in $\gamma $ .
To see this, fix $\alpha \in C$ and $i<\omega _1$ . Note that $S_{\alpha ,i}\in W$ , and $\kappa $ , being definable from ${\vec {S}}$ , is also in W. Hence, $\tilde {S}_{\alpha ,i}=\mathsf {lift}(S_{\alpha ,i},[H_\kappa ]^\omega )\in W\cap \mathcal {S}_{\mathsf {lift}}(\kappa )$ . It follows that $\tilde {S}_{\alpha ,i}\cap [W\cap H_\kappa ]^\omega $ is stationary in $W\cap H_\kappa $ . A standard argument shows that this, in turn, implies that $S_{\alpha ,i}\cap \gamma $ is stationary in $\gamma $ . In detail, let $D\subseteq \gamma $ be club. Let $E=D\cap \bar {C}$ . Since $ {\mathrm cf} (\gamma )>\omega $ , E is club. Let $f:C\longrightarrow C$ be defined by $f(\xi )=\min (E\setminus (\xi +1))$ . Since $\tilde {S}_{\alpha ,i}\cap [W\cap H_\kappa ]^\omega $ is stationary, we can pick a set $x\in \tilde {S}_{\alpha ,i}\cap [W\cap H_\kappa ]^\omega $ closed under f. Let $\delta =\sup (x\cap \kappa )$ . Since $x\in \tilde {S}_{\alpha ,i}$ , it follows that $\delta \in S_{\alpha ,i}$ . By definition of f, $\delta $ is clearly a limit point of E, hence also a limit point of D. So $\delta \in (S_{\alpha ,i}\cap \gamma )\cap D$ .
Thus, the club set $\bar {C}$ witnesses this instance of $\mathsf {DSR}(\omega _1,S^\theta _\omega )$ .
6.2 Consequences beyond $\mathsf {DRP} $ : exact reflection
It was pointed out in the beginning of this section that principles of exact reflection postulate the existence of points at which some stationary sets reflect, but others don’t. The fact that the weak diagonal reflection principle is monotonic in its argument (see Remark 6.7) is an indication that it does not capture these kinds of exact reflection. The proof of the following observation shows that sometimes, it is useful to have $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}})$ for a very small collection $\mathcal {S}$ of stationary sets indeed.
Observation 6.12. Let $\Gamma =\mathsf {SSP} $ or $\Gamma =\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ . Then $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} $ implies $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {SRP} $ .
Proof Let $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ , and let $S\subseteq [H_\kappa ]^\omega $ be stationary in $H_\kappa $ and $\Gamma $ -projective stationary. Let ${\vec {T}}={\langle T_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ be a partition of $\omega _1$ into stationary sets. Let $\mathcal {S}=\{S\}$ . Then $ {\langle \mathcal {S},{\vec {T}} \rangle } $ is $\Gamma $ -projective stationary (if $\Gamma =\mathsf {SSP} $ , then this is by Definition 4.3 and Theorem 4.6, and in case $\Gamma =\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ , it follows from Definition 5.3 and Theorem 5.5). Thus, by $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} $ , $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}})$ holds, but if $ {\langle \vec {Q},{\vec {S}} \rangle } $ witnesses this, then $\vec {Q}$ witnesses the required instance of $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {SRP} $ .
It will follow from results in Section 7 that an internally approachable form of the original principle $\mathsf {DRP} $ , which strengthens the principles of the form $\mathsf {wDRP}_{\mathsf {IA}}(\kappa )$ , does not imply $\mathsf {SRP} $ .
Coming up is a typical example of a consequence of a $\mathsf {DSRP} $ type assumption. To make exact reflection meaningful, we have to add in a constraint, but modulo this constraint, we get maximal reflection.
Lemma 6.13. Let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be a regular cardinal, and let $E\subseteq S^\kappa _\omega $ be stationary in $\kappa $ . Let
Let $\theta $ be a sufficiently large cardinal so that $\mathcal {S}\subseteq H_\theta $ . Then $\mathsf {eDSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ implies that for stationarily many $W\in [H_\theta ]^{\omega _1}$ , we have that $\omega _1\subseteq W$ and $\rho =\sup (W\cap \kappa )$ is an exact simultaneous reflection point of $\{A\in W\;|\; A\subseteq E$ and A is stationary in $\kappa $ }.
Note: Again, the assumptions of this lemma hold if $\mathsf {SSP} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa )$ holds, or if $\kappa>2^\omega $ and $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa )$ holds.
Proof Let $W\in [H_\theta ]^{\omega _1}$ be such that $W\prec {\langle H_\theta ,\mathcal {S} \rangle } $ , $\omega _1\subseteq W$ , and such that there is an exact diagonal chain $\vec {Q}$ through $\mathcal {S}$ up to W. By $\mathsf {eDSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ , there are stationarily many such. It then follows in a straightforward way that the set $\{\sup (Q_i\cap \kappa )\;|\; i<\omega _1\}$ is a club subset of $\bigcup \{A\in W\;|\; A\subseteq E\ \text {is stationary}\}$ , and since for every $A\subseteq E$ stationary in $\kappa $ that exists in W, the set $S=\mathsf {lift}(A,[H_\kappa ]^\omega )\in \mathcal {S}\cap W$ , we have that for stationarily many $i<\omega _1$ , $Q_i\in S$ , which means that $\sup (Q_i\cap \kappa )\in A$ , it follows that $\rho $ is a reflection point of A.
The previous lemma is of course most interesting if $S^\kappa _\omega \setminus E$ is also stationary in $\kappa $ . Let us now strengthen the diagonal reflection principles for sequences of stationary sets of ordinals, as given in Definition 6.10, so as to arrive at their exact versions, focusing on the variants most relevant for our purposes.
Definition 6.14. Let $\kappa $ be a regular cardinal, and let $S\subseteq \kappa $ be stationary. An $(\omega _1,S)$ -sequence is a sequence ${\langle S_{\alpha ,i}\;|\;} {\alpha <\kappa , i<\omega _1\rangle }$ of subsets of S stationary in $\kappa $ . Given such a sequence ${\vec {S}}$ , an ordinal $\rho <\kappa $ of uncountable cofinality is an exact diagonal reflection point of ${\vec {S}}$ if there is a set $R\subseteq \rho $ such that:
-
(1) R has cardinality $\omega _1$ .
-
(2) R contains a club in $\rho $ .
-
(3) $\rho $ is an exact simultaneous reflection point of $\{S_{\alpha ,i}\;|\;\alpha \in R, i<\omega _1\}$ .
The exact diagonal reflection principle $\mathsf {eDSR}(\omega _1,S)$ says that every $(\omega _1,S)$ -sequence has an exact diagonal reflection point.
Recall that even the simple (non-exact) diagonal reflection principle $\mathsf {DSR}(\omega _1,S^{\omega _2}_{\omega })$ , does not follow from $\mathsf {SRP} $ (see the discussion after Definition 6.10). The following theorem shows that $\mathsf {DSRP} $ implies the exact version.
Theorem 6.15. Let $\kappa>\omega _1$ be regular, and let ${\vec {S}}={\langle S_{\alpha ,i}\;|\;} {\alpha <\kappa , i<\omega _1\rangle }$ be an $(\omega _1,S^\kappa _\omega )$ -sequence. Let $\mathcal {S}=\{\mathsf {lift}(S_{\alpha ,i},[H_\kappa ]^\omega )\;|\;\alpha <\kappa ,\ i<\omega _1\}$ . Then $\mathsf {eDSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ implies the existence of an exact diagonal reflection point for ${\vec {S}}$ .
Note: By Lemma 6.1, the assumption of this theorem holds if $\kappa>2^\omega $ and $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa )$ holds, or if $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa )$ holds. That is, we have that “ $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa ) + \kappa>2^\omega $ is regular” implies $\mathsf {eDSR}(\omega _1,S^\kappa _\omega )$ , as does “ $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa ) + \kappa>\omega _1$ is regular.”
Proof Let $\theta $ be a cardinal such that $\mathcal {S}\subseteq H_\theta $ . Let $\omega _1\subseteq W\prec {\langle H_\theta ,\in ,\vec {S} \rangle } $ have size $\omega _1,$ and let $\vec {Q}$ be an exact diagonal chain through $\mathcal {S}$ up to W. Let $R=W\cap \kappa $ and $\rho =\sup (R)$ . We claim that $\rho $ is an exact diagonal reflection point of ${\vec {S}}$ , as witnessed by R. Let, for $j<\omega _1$ , $\rho _j=\sup (Q_j\cap \kappa )$ . Then $\rho =\sup _{j<\omega _1}\rho _j$ and $C=\{\rho _j\;|\; j<\omega _1\}$ is club in $\rho $ , $\rho $ has cofinality $\omega _1$ , and $C\subseteq R$ . This verifies conditions (1) and (2).
To see that $\rho $ is a reflection point of $S_{\alpha ,i}$ , for every $\alpha \in R$ and every $i<\omega _1$ , fix such $\alpha $ and i. Let $T_{\alpha ,i}=\{j<\omega _1\;|\; Q_j\in \mathsf {lift}(S_{\alpha ,i},[H_\kappa ]^\omega )\}$ . Since $\alpha , i\in W$ , it follows that $\mathsf {lift}(S_{\alpha ,i},[H_\kappa ]^\omega )\in W\cap \mathcal {S}$ , and so, $T_{\alpha ,i}$ is stationary in $\omega _1$ . But whenever $j\in T_{\alpha ,i}$ , then $\rho _j\in S_{\alpha ,i}$ . So since $T_{\alpha ,i}$ is stationary in $\omega _1$ and the map $j\mapsto \rho _j$ is continuous and strictly increasing, it follows that $\{\rho _j\;|\; j\in T_{\alpha ,i}\}$ is stationary in $\rho $ . Since $\{\rho _j\;|\; j\in T_{\alpha ,i}\}\subseteq S_{\alpha ,i}$ , it follows that $\rho $ is a reflection point of $S_{\alpha ,i}$ . Thus, $\rho $ is a simultaneous reflection point of $\{S_{\alpha ,i}\;|\;\alpha \in R, i<\omega _1\}$ .
Finally, since $\vec {Q}$ is exact, we have that for every $j<\omega _1$ , $Q_j\in S$ , for some $S\in \mathcal {S}\cap W$ , and hence, $\rho _j\in S_{\alpha ,i}$ , for some $\alpha \in W\cap \kappa $ and some $i<\omega _1$ . This is because if $S\in \mathcal {S}\cap W$ , then since $W\prec {\langle H_\theta ,\in ,{\vec {S}} \rangle } $ , there is a least pair $ {\langle \alpha ,i \rangle } $ such that $S=S_{\alpha ,i}$ , which must be in W. Thus, $C\subseteq \bigcup _{\alpha \in R, i<\omega _1}S_{\alpha ,i}$ , verifying the “exactness” part of condition (3).
As a last example, let us state an exact diagonal mutual reflection principle with a constraint. The formulation is a little tedious, but the principle is quite natural.
Definition 6.16. Let $\kappa $ be an ordinal of uncountable cofinality. We write $\mathsf {S}_\kappa $ for the collection of all stationary subsets of $\kappa $ . Given a set $E\subseteq \kappa $ , we write $\mathsf {S}_\kappa {\restriction } E$ for the collection of all subsets of E that are stationary in $\kappa $ .
Theorem 6.17. Let $K\neq \emptyset $ be a set of regular cardinals greater than $\omega _1$ , with supremum ${\tilde {\kappa }}$ . Let ${\langle E_\kappa \;|\;} {\kappa \in K\rangle }$ be a sequence of sets such that for each $\kappa \in K$ , $E_\kappa \subseteq S^\kappa _\omega $ is stationary in $\kappa $ . Now, for every ${\vec {A}}\in \prod _{\kappa \in K}\mathsf {S}_\kappa {\restriction } E_\kappa $ , let
and let
Assume $\mathsf {eDSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ holds and let $\theta $ be a cardinal sufficiently large so that $\mathcal {S}\subseteq H_\theta $ . Then there are stationarily many $W\in [H_\theta ]^{\omega _1}$ such that $:$
-
(1) $\omega _1\subseteq W$ .
-
(2) For every $\kappa \in K\cap W$ , $\rho _\kappa =\sup (W\cap \kappa )$ is an exact simultaneous reflection point for $(\mathsf {S}_\kappa {\restriction } E_\kappa )\cap W$ .
-
(3) There is a matrix ${\langle \rho _{\kappa ,i}\;|\;} {\kappa \in K\cap W, i<\omega _1\rangle }$ such that $:$
-
(a) For every $\kappa \in K\cap W$ , there is a $\delta _\kappa <\omega _1$ such that the function $\delta _\kappa <i\mapsto \rho _{\kappa ,i}$ is strictly increasing, continuous, and cofinal in $\rho _\kappa $ .
-
(b) For every $\kappa \in K\cap W$ and every sufficiently large $i<\omega _1$ ,
$$\begin{align*}\rho_{\kappa,i}\in W\cap E_\kappa.\end{align*}$$ -
(c) For every ${\vec {A}}\in W\cap \prod _{\kappa \in K}\mathsf {S}_\kappa {\restriction } E_\kappa $ , there is a stationary subset $T_{{\vec {A}}}\subseteq \omega _1$ such that for every $\kappa \in K\cap W$ and every sufficiently large $i\in T_{{\vec {A}}}$ , $\rho _{\kappa ,i}\in A_\kappa $ .
-
Remark 6.18. It was shown in [Reference Fuchs10, Corollary 3.26] that $S_{{\vec {A}}}$ is projective stationary, and so, the assumptions of the theorem follow from $\mathsf {DSRP} $ . By [Reference Fuchs10, Corollary 3.32], $S_{\vec {A}}$ is even spread out if $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {SRP} + \mathsf {CH} $ holds, so the assumptions also follow from $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} + \mathsf {CH} $ .
Proof By assumption, there are stationarily in $H_\theta $ many $W\in [H_\theta ]^{\omega _1}$ with $\omega _1\subseteq W$ such that there is an exact diagonal chain ${\langle Q_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ through $\mathcal {S}$ up to W. Define, for $\kappa \in K\cap W$ and $i<\omega _1$ , $\rho _{\kappa ,i}=\sup (Q_i\cap \kappa )$ . It is routine to check that all the conditions are satisfied.
7 Limitations
In this section, we will present some negative results, separating some of the principles under investigation. The first of these employs methods of Miyamoto.
Theorem 7.1. Assuming the consistency of a supercompact cardinal, $\mathsf {DSRP} $ does not imply $\mathsf {MM} $ ; it is consistent with the existence of a Souslin tree.
Proof Miyamoto [Reference Miyamoto19, Definition 5.4] introduced the forcing axiom $\mathsf {MM} (Souslin)$ , which is the forcing axiom for the class of all stationary set preserving forcing notions that also preserve every $\omega _1$ -Souslin tree, and he showed [Reference Miyamoto19, Corollary 5.8] that assuming the consistency of a supercompact cardinal, $\mathsf {MM} (Souslin)+$ “there is a Souslin tree” is consistent. He also showed that $\mathsf {MM} (Souslin)$ implies $\mathsf {SRP} $ . All we have to do is observe that $\mathsf {MM} (Souslin)$ also implies $\mathsf {DSRP} $ . For this, it clearly suffices to show, given a pair $ {\langle \mathcal {S},{\vec {T}} \rangle } $ that is $\mathsf {SSP} $ -projective stationary, that ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}={\mathord {\mathbb P}}^{\mathsf {DSRP}}_{\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}}}$ preserves Souslin trees. So let U be a Souslin tree, let $p\in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , and suppose that $\dot {A}$ is a ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ -name such that p forces that $\dot {A}$ is a maximal antichain in T. We have to find an extension q of p that forces $\dot {A}$ to be countable. We may assume that $S=S^p_0$ is defined. So S is projective stationary on $T_0$ . Let $\theta $ be a sufficiently large regular cardinal, and let $X\prec {\langle H_\theta ,\in ,<^* \rangle } $ with ${\mathord {\mathbb P}},\mathcal {S},p,{\vec {T}},U\in X$ , and such that $\delta =X\cap \omega _1\in T_0$ and $X\cap H_\kappa \in S$ .
Let $\{t_n\;|\; n<\omega \}$ enumerate the $\delta $ -th level of U, and define
The point is that $D_n$ is dense in ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}\cap M$ , as is shown by the argument of [Reference Miyamoto19, Claim on page 1464]: let $a\in {\mathord {\mathbb P}}\cap M$ be given. If a is incompatible with p, then $a\in D_n$ and we are done. Otherwise, by strengthening a, we may assume that $a\le _{\mathord {\mathbb P}} p$ . Let $D=\{t\in U\;|\;\exists r\le _{\mathord {\mathbb P}} a\ r\Vdash \check {t}\in \dot {A}\}$ . Since a forces $\dot {A}$ to be a maximal antichain in U, it is easy to see that D is predense in U, that is, every element of U is comparable with some member of D. Since U is a Souslin tree, the set $b_n=\{t\in U\;|\; t<_U t_n\}\cap M$ is U-generic over M, and hence, it intersects D in M, as $D\in M$ . So let $t\in b_n\cap D\cap M$ . Let $r\le a$ witness that $t\in D$ . Then $r\in D_n$ , as witnessed by t.
Note that $D_n$ is not in M. But we may construct an M-generic G by forming a decreasing chain ${\langle p_n\;|\;} {n<\omega \rangle }$ of conditions in ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ such that, letting ${\langle E_n\;|\;} {n<\omega \rangle }$ enumerate all dense open subsets of ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ in M, $p_n\in D_n\cap E_n$ (note that $D_n$ is open as well), and such that $p_0\le p$ . Let G be the filter generated by ${\vec {p}}$ . Then, letting $\vec {Q}=\bigcup _{n<\omega }\vec {Q}^{p_n}$ and ${\vec {S}}=\bigcup _{n<\omega }{\vec {S}}^{p_n}$ , we have that $\delta $ is the length of $\vec {Q}$ , which is the same as the length of ${\vec {S}}$ , and $M\cap H_\kappa =\bigcup _{i<\delta }Q_i\in S_0$ . Since $\delta \in T_0$ , we can define a condition q by setting
Clearly, q forces that $\dot {A}$ is contained in $U{\restriction }\delta $ , the restriction of U to levels below $\delta $ .
It is now natural to ask for a similar separation between $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} $ and $\mathsf {FA}(\Gamma )$ , where $\Gamma $ is the class of all subcomplete or all $\infty $ -subcomplete forcing notions. It was observed in [Reference Fuchs10] that, assuming the consistency of $\mathsf {MM} $ , $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {SRP} $ does not imply $\mathsf {SCFA} $ , since under the assumption of $\mathsf {MM} $ , a model of $\mathsf {ZFC} $ can be constructed in which $\mathsf {SRP} + \neg \mathsf {uDSR}(1,S^{\omega _3}_\omega )$ holds. So this model satisfies $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {SRP} $ , but not $\mathsf {SCFA} $ , or else it would have to satisfy $\mathsf {DSR}(\omega _1,S^{\omega _3}_\omega )$ . For the same reason, though, $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} $ fails in this model as well, so this method does not separate $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} $ from $\mathsf {SCFA} $ . Theorem 7.1 does not achieve this separation either, because $\mathsf {SCFA} $ is consistent with the existence of Souslin trees. Furthermore, it was argued in [Reference Fuchs10] that the assumption of $\mathsf {CH} $ should be added to $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {SRP} $ , since for regular $\kappa \in (\omega _1,2^\omega )$ , $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {SRP} (\kappa )$ holds trivially. Since the models achieving the separations up to now satisfied $\mathsf {SRP} $ , $\mathsf {CH} $ fails in them, and so, they don’t achieve a separation of this kind.
The following theorem does achieve a certain separation at the level $\omega _2$ in the presence of $\mathsf {CH} $ . This result was alluded to at the end of the article [Reference Fuchs10], but not made precise. For this result, it is important that we work with subcompleteness, not $\infty $ -subcompleteness. Since we will be using results of [Reference Fuchs10] as a black box, the reasons for this will remain obscure here; let us just say that the problem is the iteration theorem [Reference Fuchs10, Theorem 4.17]. The exact relationship between subcompleteness and $\infty $ -subcompleteness is not well understood, but subcompleteness is a potentially more restrictive requirement than $\infty $ -subcompleteness, so that the principle $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} $ could be stronger than $\mathsf {SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} $ . But all the consequences of $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} $ presented in Section 6 also follow from $\mathsf {SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} $ , and the subcomplete fragment of $\mathsf {DSRP} $ can be characterized by replacing “spread out” with “fully spread out” everywhere (see [Reference Fuchs10, Definition 2.33]). The following definition summarizes the concepts needed for the statement of the result.
Definition 7.2. For a forcing class $\Gamma $ and a cardinal $\kappa $ , $\mathsf {BFA}(\Gamma ,{\le }\kappa )$ , the ${\le }\kappa $ -bounded forcing axiom for $\Gamma $ , says that if ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}\in \Gamma $ and ${\mathord {\mathbb {B}}}$ is the complete Boolean algebra of ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , and if $\mathcal {A}$ is a collection of at most $\omega _1$ many maximal antichains in ${\mathord {\mathbb {B}}}$ , each of which has cardinality at most $\kappa $ , then there is a filter in ${\mathord {\mathbb {B}}}$ that meets each antichain in $\mathcal {A}$ . We write $\mathsf {BSCFA} ({\le }\kappa )$ in case $\Gamma $ is the class of all subcomplete forcing notions.
For a regular cardinal $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ and an uncountable cardinal $\lambda $ , the principle $\mathsf {SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\kappa ,\lambda )$ asserts that whenever $\mathcal {S}$ is a nonempty collection of subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ that are stationary in $H_\kappa $ , such that $\mathcal {S}$ has size at most $\lambda $ , and ${\vec {T}}$ is a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , and $ {\langle \mathcal {S},{\vec {T}} \rangle } $ is $\mathsf {SC} $ -projective stationary, then $\mathsf {DSRP} (\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}})$ holds.
Before moving to the separation result, let us make an observation related to the two cardinal version of $\mathsf {DSRP} $ introduced in the previous definition.
Observation 7.3. Let $\Gamma $ be $\mathsf {SSP} $ , $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ or $\mathsf {SC} $ . Let $\mathcal {S}$ be a collection of up to $\omega _1$ many sets $\Gamma $ -projective stationary in $H_\kappa $ , for some regular $\kappa \ge \omega _2$ . Then $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {SRP} (\kappa )$ implies $\mathsf {eDSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ .
Proof Let ${\vec {T}}$ be a maximal partition of $\omega _1$ into stationary sets, and let ${\langle S_i\;|\;} {i<\omega _1\rangle }$ enumerate $\mathcal {S}$ . Let
Claim: S is $\Gamma $ -projective stationary.
Case 1: $\Gamma =\mathsf {SSP} $ .
Then $\Gamma $ -projective stationarity is just projective stationarity. So let $A\subseteq \omega _1$ be stationary. By maximality of ${\vec {T}}$ , let $i_0<\omega _1$ be such that $A\cap T_{i_0}$ is stationary. Since $S_{i_0}$ is projective stationary,
is stationary. But this set is contained in $\{x\in S\;|\; x\cap \omega _1\in A\}$ , making the latter set stationary, and hence S is projective stationary.
Case 2: $\Gamma =\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ .
Then $\Gamma $ -projective stationarity is being spread out. So let $\theta $ be a sufficiently large cardinal, $H_\theta \subseteq N=L_\tau ^A\models {\mathsf {ZFC} }^- $ , $N|X\prec N$ , X countable and full, $\vec {S},{\vec {T}},S,a\in X$ . Since ${\vec {T}}$ is maximal, $Z=\omega _1\setminus \bigtriangledown _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ is not stationary. Since $Z\in X$ , it follows that $\delta =X\cap \omega _1\notin Z$ . So $\delta \in \bigtriangledown _{i<\omega _1}T_i$ . Let $\delta \in T_{i_0}$ . Then $i_0<\delta $ . So $S_{i_0}\in X$ . Since $S_{i_0}$ is spread out and $S_{i_0}\in X$ , let $\pi :N|X\longrightarrow N|Y\prec N$ be an isomorphism fixing $\vec {S},{\vec {T}},S,a$ , such that $Y\cap H_\kappa \in S_{i_0}$ . Since $Y\cap \omega _1=X\cap \omega _1=\delta \in T_{i_0}$ , it follows that $Y\cap H_\kappa \in S$ , verifying that S is spread out.
Case 3: $\Gamma =\mathsf {SC} $ .
In this case, one has to work with fully spread out sets instead of spread out sets (see [Reference Fuchs10, Definition 2.33]). The argument of case 2 goes through.
This proves the claim. Thus, by $\Gamma $ - $\mathsf {SRP} (\kappa )$ , there is a continuous $\in $ -chain of length $\omega _1$ through S, and this easily implies $\mathsf {eDSRP} (\mathcal {S})$ .
Theorem 7.4. Let $\Gamma $ be the class of all subcomplete, uncountable cofinality preserving forcing notions. If $\mathsf {ZFC} $ is consistent with $\mathsf {BFA}(\Gamma ,{\le }\omega _2)$ , then $\mathsf {ZFC} $ is consistent with the conjunction of the following statements $:$
-
(1) $\mathsf {CH} $ ,
-
(2) $\mathsf {BFA}(\Gamma ,{\le }\omega _2)$ ,
-
(3) $\neg \mathsf {BSCFA} (\omega _2)$ ,
-
(4) $\mathsf {SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\omega _2,\omega _2)$ .
Note: $\mathsf {SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\omega _2,\omega _2)+\mathsf {CH} $ has interesting consequences that go beyond $\mathsf {SC} $ - $\mathsf {SRP} (\omega _2)$ . For example, it implies $\mathsf {eDSR}(\omega _2,S^{\omega _2}_\omega )$ (see Theorem 6.15)—the collection $\mathcal {S}$ used in the proof of this theorem has size $\kappa =\omega _2$ in our situation.
Proof It was shown in [Reference Fuchs10, Theorem 4.25] that under the assumptions of the theorem, there is a model in which $\mathsf {ZFC} $ holds, together with (1)–(3). So it suffices to show that (1) + (2) implies (4).
To see this, let $ {\langle \mathcal {S},{\vec {T}} \rangle } $ be $\mathsf {SC} $ -projective stationary, where $\mathcal {S}$ consists of subsets of $[H_\kappa ]^\omega $ stationary in $H_\kappa $ and has cardinality at most $\omega _2$ . Let $\theta $ be large enough that $\mathcal {S}\subseteq H_\theta $ , and let
be a model of a language of size $\omega _1$ with some extra predicate F, a well-order $<^*$ , constant symbols $\dot {\xi }$ for every countable ordinal $\xi $ , and with a constant symbol for $T_i$ , for every $i<\omega _1$ . We have to find an $M\prec \mathcal {M}$ of size $\omega _1$ , with $\omega _1\subseteq M$ , such that there is a diagonal chain through $\mathcal {S}$ up to M wrt. ${\vec {T}}$ . Let $\bar {\mathcal {M}}\prec \mathcal {M}$ be the transitive collapse of the hull of $H_{\omega _2}\cup \mathcal {S}$ in $\mathcal {M}$ . So $\bar {\mathcal {M}}$ has cardinality $\omega _2$ , since $2^{\omega _1}=\omega _2$ - it was shown in [Reference Fuchs10, Lemma 4.24(2)] that $\mathsf {BFA}(\Gamma ,{\le }\omega _2)$ implies $\mathsf {SC} $ - $\mathsf {SRP} (\omega _2)$ , and this, in turn, together with $\mathsf {CH} $ , implies $2^{\omega _1}=\omega _2$ , by [Reference Fuchs10, Theorem 3.19] and the following remarks, and [Reference Fuchs10, Fact 3.15]. Let G be ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}={\mathord {\mathbb P}}^{\mathsf {DSRP} }_{\mathcal {S},{\vec {T}}}$ -generic over $\mathrm {V} $ . In $\mathrm {V} [G]$ , let $ {\langle \vec {Q},{\vec {S}} \rangle } $ be the sequence added by G. Then $\bigcup _{i<\omega _1}Q_i=H_{\omega _2}$ and $\mathcal {S}=\{S_i\;|\; i<\omega _1\}$ . So in $\mathrm {V} [G]$ , the following statement is true about $\bar {\mathcal {M}}$ : there are sequences $\vec {Q}'$ and ${\vec {S}}'$ of length $\omega _1^{\bar {\mathcal {M}}}$ such that $\vec {Q}'$ is a continuous $\in $ -chain unioning up to $H_{\omega _2}^{\bar {\mathcal {M}}}$ , for every $i<\omega _1$ , $S^{\prime }_i\in \mathcal {S}^{\bar {\mathcal {M}}}$ , and if $j<\omega _1^{\bar {\mathcal {M}}}$ is such that $i\in T^{\bar {\mathcal {M}}}_j$ , then $Q^{\prime }_i\in S^{\prime }_j$ , and such that $\mathcal {S}^{\bar {\mathcal {M}}}=\{S^{\prime }_i\;|\; i<\omega _1\}$ . This is a $\Sigma _1$ statement about $\bar {\mathcal {M}}$ forced to be true by ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}$ , so since ${\mathord {\mathbb P}}\in \Gamma $ and $\mathsf {BFA}(\Gamma ,{\le }\omega _2)$ holds, there are by [Reference Fuchs10, Fact 4.21] (see also [Reference Claverie and Schindler2, Theorem 1.3]) a transitive model $\tilde {\mathcal {M}}$ of the same language as $\bar {\mathcal {M}}$ and an elementary embedding $j:\tilde {\mathcal {M}}\prec \bar {\mathcal {M}}$ , so that the same $\Sigma _1$ statement is true about $\tilde {\mathcal {M}}$ in $\mathrm {V} $ . Note that $\omega _1\subseteq \tilde {\mathcal {M}}$ and $j{\restriction }\omega _1= {\mathrm id} $ , since the language contains constant symbols for all the countable ordinals. If the witnessing sequences are $\vec {\tilde {Q}}$ and $\vec {\tilde {S}}$ , then, letting $\pi :\bar {\mathcal {M}}\longrightarrow \mathcal {M}$ be the inverse of the collapse, it follows that $\pi {\restriction } H_{\omega _2}= {\mathrm id} $ , and so, if we define $\vec {Q}'$ by $Q^{\prime }_i=j({\tilde {Q}}_i)$ and ${\vec {S}}'$ by $S^{\prime }_i=j(\tilde {S}_i)$ , then $ {\langle \vec {Q}',{\vec {S}}' \rangle } $ is a diagonal chain through $\mathcal {S}$ up to $M= {\mathrm ran} (\pi \circ j)$ with respect to ${\vec {T}}$ , where $\omega _1\subseteq M$ and $M\prec \mathcal {M}$ .
The last separation result concerns the diagonal reflection principle of [Reference Cox3] and its relationship to cardinal arithmetic. This principle is stronger than the principles of the form $\mathsf {wDRP}_{\mathsf {IA}}(\kappa )$ we have considered.
Definition 7.5. Let $\theta $ be an uncountable regular cardinal. The principle $\mathsf {DRP} (\theta ,\mathsf {IA})$ states that there are stationarily many $M\in [H_{(\theta ^\omega )^+}]^{\omega _1}$ such that $M\cap H_\theta \in \mathsf {IA}$ and for every stationary subset $R\in M$ of $[\theta ]^\omega $ , $R\cap [M\cap \theta ]^\omega $ is stationary in $M\cap \theta $ .
The principle $\mathsf {DRP} (\mathsf {IA})$ states that $\mathsf {DRP} (\theta ,\mathsf {IA})$ holds for all regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ .
Theorem 7.6. $\mathsf {DRP} (\mathsf {IA})$ does not limit the size of $2^{\omega _1}$ .
Note: This shows that this principle, if consistent, does not imply $\mathsf {eRefl} (\omega _1,S^{\omega _2}_\omega )$ (see Fact 6.5). In particular, it does not imply $\mathsf {SRP} $ .
Proof We will show that the theory “ $\mathsf {CH} $ plus the forcing axiom $\text {FA}^{+\omega _1}(\sigma \text {-closed})$ ” is preserved after adding any number of Cohen subsets of $\omega _1$ . This will suffice, since:
-
(1) $\text {FA}^{+\omega _1}(\sigma \text {-closed})$ implies $\mathsf {DRP} (\theta ,\mathsf {IA})$ , for all regular $\theta>\omega _1$ [Reference Cox3, Theorem 4.1]; and
-
(2) $\mathsf {CH} $ is consistent with $\text {FA}^{+\omega _1}(\sigma \text {-closed})$ ([Reference Foreman, Magidor and Shelah7] shows that forcing with $\text {Col}(\omega _1,<\kappa )$ when $\kappa $ is supercompact produces a model satisfying this).
So assume $\mathsf {CH} $ plus $\text {FA}^{+\omega _1}(\sigma \text {-closed})$ both hold in V. Pick any cardinal $\lambda $ , and let $\mathbb {P}$ be the countable support product of $\lambda $ -many copies of $\text {Add}(\omega _1)$ . Since $\mathsf {CH} $ holds, $\mathbb {P}$ has the $\omega _2$ -cc, so in particular, $\mathbb {P}$ preserves all cardinals $\ge \omega _2$ , and forces $2^{\omega _1} \ge \lambda $ . It remains to show that $\text {FA}^{+\omega _1}(\sigma \text {-closed})$ is preserved.
Let p be any condition in $\mathbb {P}$ , and let $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ be a $\mathbb {P}$ -name for a $\sigma $ -closed poset. Then $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ is $\sigma $ -closed. Fix a regular $\theta $ such that $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {R}} \in H_\theta $ . Since $\mathrm {V} $ models $\text {FA}^{+\omega _1}(\sigma \text {-closed})$ , [Reference Cox4, Theorem 4.5] implies that in some generic extension W of V, there is an elementary embedding $j: \mathrm {V} \prec N$ such that:
-
(1) $\text {crit}(j) = \omega _2^{\mathrm {V}} =:\kappa $ .
-
(2) $j \restriction H^{\mathrm {V}}_\theta \in N$ .
-
(3) $|H^{\mathrm {V}}_\theta |^N=\aleph _1$ .
-
(4) $H^{\mathrm {V}}_\theta $ is an element of the (transitivized) wellfounded part of N.
-
(5) There is some $G*H \in N$ that is generic over V for $(\mathbb {P} \restriction p )*\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ .
Since $\mathbb {P}$ has the $\kappa $ -cc in $\mathrm {V} $ and $\text {crit}(j)=\kappa $ , the map $j \restriction \mathbb {P}: \mathbb {P} \to j(\mathbb {P})$ is a regular embedding; so if we let $G'$ be generic over W for the poset $j(\mathbb {P})/j"G$ , it follows that $G'$ extends $j"G$ , and in $W[G']$ the map j lifts to an elementary embedding
Since $G*H$ was already in N and was generic over V for $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ , then in particular $H \in N[G']$ and H is generic over $V[G]$ for $\mathbb {R}=\dot {\mathbb {R}}_G$ . Also, since both $j \restriction H^V_\theta $ and $G'$ are elements of N, it follows that $\widetilde {j} \restriction H^V_\theta [G]$ is an element of $N[G']$ . Hence by (the reverse direction of) [Reference Cox4, Theorem 4.5], the forcing axiom for $\mathbb {R}$ holds in $V[G]$ .
8 Open questions
In Section 6.2, we presented consequences of $\mathsf {DSRP} $ that neither follow from $\mathsf {SRP} $ nor from $\mathsf {DRP} _{\mathsf {IA}}$ . However, we have not separated the conjunction of $\mathsf {SRP} $ and $\mathsf {DRP} _{\mathsf {IA}}$ from $\mathsf {DSRP} $ , even though it seems unlikely that this conjunction implies $\mathsf {DSRP} $ . It would be interesting to know how to do that.
Question 8.1. Does $\mathsf {SRP} +\mathsf {w}\mathsf {DRP} _{\mathsf {IA}}$ imply $\mathsf {eDSR}(\omega _1,S^{\omega _2}_\omega )$ , or even $\mathsf {DSRP} $ ?
Regarding the separation of $\mathsf {SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\omega _2,\omega _2)$ from $\mathsf {BSCFA} (\omega _2)$ , it would be interesting to know if this can be improved.
Question 8.2. Can one show that $\mathsf {SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} (\omega _2)+\mathsf {CH} $ does not imply $\mathsf {BSCFA} (\omega _2)$ ? That $\mathsf {SC} $ - $\mathsf {DSRP} +\mathsf {CH} $ does not imply $\mathsf {SCFA} $ ? How about the $\mathsf {\infty \text {-}SC} $ -versions of these separations?
Acknowledgments
The second author is grateful for the hospitality of the logic group at Virginia Commonwealth University, and in particular to Brent Cody, during a visit in August 2019.
Funding
The second author acknowledges support from PSC-CUNY Award #63516-00 51, jointly funded by The Professional Staff Congress and The City University of New York, and by Simons Award Number 580600.