Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T18:06:39.983Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The finite model property for various fragments of linear logic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Yves Lafont*
Affiliation:
Institut de Mathématiques de Luminy, UPR 9016 du CNRS, 163 Avenue de Luminy, Case 930, 13288 Marseille Cedex 9, France, E-mail: lafont@iml.univ-mrs.fr

Extract

To show that a formula A is not provable in propositional classical logic, it suffices to exhibit a finite boolean model which does not satisfy A. A similar property holds in the intuitionistic case, with Kripke models instead of boolean models (see for instance [11]). One says that the propositional classical logic and the propositional intuitionistic logic satisfy a finite model property. In particular, they are decidable: there is a semi-algorithm for provability (proof search) and a semi-algorithm for non provability (model search). For that reason, a logic which is undecidable, such as first order logic, cannot satisfy a finite model property.

The case of linear logic is more complicated. The full propositional fragment LL has a complete semantics in terms of phase spaces [2, 3], but it is undecidable [9]. The multiplicative additive fragment MALL is decidable, in fact PSPACE-complete [9], but the decidability of the multiplicative exponential fragment MELL is still an open problem. For affine logic, that is, linear logic with weakening, the situation is somewhat better: the full propositional fragment LLW is decidable [5].

Here, we show that the finite phase semantics is complete for MALL and for LLW, but not for MELL. In particular, this gives a new proof of the decidability of LLW. The noncommutative case is mentioned, but not handled in detail.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

[1]Abrusci, V. M., Phase semantics and sequent calculus for pure noncommutative classical linear propositional logic, this Journal, vol. 56 (1991), pp. 14031451.Google Scholar
[2]Girard, J.-Y., Linear logic, Theoretical Computer Science, vol. 50 (1987), pp. 1102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3]Girard, J.-Y., Linear logic: its syntax and semantics, Advances in linear logic (Girard, J.-Y., Lafont, Y., and Regnier, L., editors), London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series, vol. 222, Cambridge University Press, 1995, pp. 142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[4]Kanovich, M., Simulating computations in second order non-commutative linear logic, manuscript, 1995.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5]Kopylov, A. P., Propositional linear logic with weakening is decidable, Proceedings of the 10th Annual IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, San Diego, California, IEEE Computer Society Press, 1995.Google Scholar
[6]Kopylov, A. P., The undecidability of second order linear affine logic, manuscript, 1995.Google Scholar
[7]Lafont, Y., The undecidability of second order linear logic without exponentials, this Journal, vol. 61 (1996), pp. 541548.Google Scholar
[8]Lafont, Y. and Scedrov, A., The undecidability of second order multiplicative linear logic, Information and Computation, vol. 125 (1996), pp. 4651.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[9]Lincoln, P., Mitchell, J., Scedrov, A., and Shankar, N., Decision problems for propositional linear logic, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 56 (1992), pp. 239311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[10]Okada, M., Girard's phase semantics and a higher order cut-elimination proof, available by anonymous ftp on iml. univ-mrs. fr, in pub/okada, 1994.Google Scholar
[11]Troelstra, A. S. and van Dalen, D., Constructivism in mathematics, an introduction, vol. 1, Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, vol. 121, North-Holland, 1988.Google Scholar