Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-mlc7c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T10:10:56.764Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Representability in second-order propositional poly-modal logic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

G. Aldo Antonelli
Affiliation:
Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science, University of California, Irvine, CA 92697-5100, USA, E-mail: aldo@uci.edu
Richmond H. Thomason
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI 48109-1003, USA, E-mail: rich@thomason.org

Abstract

A propositional system of modal logic is second-order if it contains quantifiers ∀p and ∃p which, in the standard interpretation, are construed as ranging over sets of possible worlds (propositions). Most second-order systems of modal logic are highly intractable; for instance, when augmented with propositional quantifiers, K, B, T, K4 and S4 all become effectively equivalent to full second-order logic. An exception is S5, which, being interpretable in monadic second-order logic, is decidable.

In this paper we generalize this framework by allowing multiple modalities. While this does not affect the undecidability of K, B, T, K4 and S4, poly-modal second-order S5 is dramatically more expressive than its mono-modal counterpart. As an example, we establish the definability of the transitive closure of finitely many modal operators. We also take up the decidability issue, and, using a novel encoding of sets of unordered pairs by partitions of the leaves of certain graphs, we show that the second-order propositional logic of two S5 modalitities is also equivalent to full second-order logic.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 2002

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Ackermann, Wilhelm [1954], Solvable cases of the decision problem, North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Fagin, Ronald, Halpern, Joseph Y., Moses, Yoram, and Vardi, Moshe Y. [1995], Reasoning about knowledge, The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.Google Scholar
Fine, Kit [1970], Propositional quantifiers in modal logic, Theoria, pp. 336346.Google Scholar
Kaplan, David [1970], S5 with quantifiable propositional variables, this Journal, vol. 35, no. 2, p. 355.Google Scholar
Kremer, Philip [1997], On the complexity of propositional quantification in intuitionistic logic, this Journal, vol. 62, no. 2, pp. 529544.Google Scholar
Nerode, Anil and Shore, Richard [1980], Second order logic and theories of reducibility orderings, The Kleene symposium (Amsterdam) (Barwise, Jon, Keisler, H. Jerome, and Kunen, Kenneth, editors), North-Holland, pp. 181200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabin, Michael O. [1965], A simple method for undecidability proofs and some applications, Logic, methodology and philosophy of science. Proceedings of the 1964 international congress (Amsterdam) (Bar-Hillel, Yehoshua, editor), North-Holland, pp. 5868.Google Scholar
Tarski, Alfred, Mostowski, Andrzej, and Robinson, Raphael M. [1953], Undecidable theories, North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam.Google Scholar