Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T17:43:19.645Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Some representations of Diophantine sets1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Raphael M. Robinson*
Affiliation:
University of California, Berkeley, California 94720

Extract

A set D of natural numbers is called Diophantine if it can be defined in the form

where P is a polynomial with integer coefficients. Recently, Ju. V. Matijasevič [2], [3] has shown that all recursively enumerable sets are Diophantine. From this, it follows that a bound for n may be given.

We use throughout the logical symbols ∧ (and), ∨ (or), → (if … then …), ↔ (if and only if), ⋀ (for every), and ⋁ (there exists); negation does not occur explicitly. The variables range over the natural numbers 0,1,2,3, …, except as otherwise noted.

It is the purpose of this paper to show that if we do not insist on prenex form, then every Diophantine set can be defined existentially by a formula in which not more than five existential quantifiers are nested. Besides existential quantifiers, only conjunctions are needed. By Matijasevič [2], [3], the representation extends to all recursively enumerable sets. Using this, we can find a bound for the number of conjuncts needed.

Davis [1] proved that every recursively enumerable set of natural numbers can be represented in the form

where P is a polynomial with integer coefficients. I showed in [5] that we can take λ = 4. (A minor error is corrected in an Appendix to this paper.) By the methods of the present paper, we can again obtain this result, and indeed in a stronger form, with the universal quantifier replaced by a conjunction.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1972

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

Presented to the Fourth International Congress for Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, in Bucharest, Romania, on September 3, 1971, under the title An undecidable Diophantine problem.

References

REFERENCES

[1]Davis, Martin, Arithmetical problems and recursively enumerable predicates, this Journal, vol. 18 (1953), pp. 3341.Google Scholar
[2]Matijasevič, Ju. V., Enumerable sets are Diophantine, Doklady Akademii Nauk SSSR, vol. 191 (1970), pp. 279282; Soviet Mathematics, Doklady, vol. 11 (1970), pp. 354–358.Google Scholar
[3]Matijasevič, Ju. V., Diophantine representation of enumerable predicates, Izvestija Akademii Nauk SSSR. Serija Matematičeskaja, vol. 35 (1971), pp. 330; Mathematics of the USSR—Izpestija, vol. 5 (1971), pp. 1–28.Google Scholar
[4]Robinson, Julia, Hilbert's tenth problem, Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, vol. 20, American Mathematical Society, Providence, R.I., 1971, pp. 191194.Google Scholar
[5]Robinson, Raphael M., Arithmetical representation of recursively enumerable sets, this Journal, vol. 21 (1956), pp. 162186.Google Scholar