Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T15:43:02.908Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Knowing Yourself and Being Worth Knowing

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 November 2018

JORDAN MACKENZIE*
Affiliation:
CENTER FOR BIOETHICS, NEW YORK UNIVERSITYjordan.mackenzie@nyu.edu

Abstract

Philosophers have often understood self-knowledge's value in instrumentalist terms. Self-knowledge may be valuable as a means to moral self-improvement and self-satisfaction, while its absence can lead to viciousness and frustration. These explanations, while compelling, do not fully explain the value that many of us place in self-knowledge. Rather, we have a tendency to treat self-knowledge as its own end. In this article, I vindicate this tendency by identifying a moral reason that we have to value and seek self-knowledge that is independent of the reason that we have to value the beneficial ends that it helps us achieve. I argue that we are in an inescapable relationship with ourselves that requires both self-love and self-respect. Self-love gives us a noninstrumental reason to know ourselves, while self-respect demands that we take this reason seriously. To pursue a project of self-discovery carefully and for its own sake, then, is part of what it is to stand in a loving and respectful relationship with ourselves.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This article would not exist were it not for Ram Neta, Susan Wolf, and Thomas E. Hill. I am also indebted to Simon Blackburn, Michael Cholbi, Krasimira Filcheva, Daniel Fogal, Camil Golub, Theodore Graham, Matthew Kotzen, Adam Lerner, S. Matthew Liao, Peter MacKenzie, Samuel Reis-Dennis, Chelsea Rosenthal, Bill Ruddick, and Keshav Singh, as well as to anonymous reviewers at this journal and to audiences at the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, the New York University Center for Bioethics, and Carleton College.

References

Aristotle. (1984) Magna Moralia. In Barnes, Jonathan (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle, vol. 2 (Princeton: Princeton University Press), 1969–1921.Google Scholar
Aristotle. (1985) Nichomachean Ethics. Translated by Irwin, Terence. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Baron, Marcia. (1998) ‘What is Wrong with Self-Deception?’ In McLaughlin, Brian P. and Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg (eds.), Perspectives on Self-Deception (Los Angeles: University of California Press), 431–49.Google Scholar
Bransen, Jan. (2015) ‘Self-Knowledge and Self-Love’. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18, 309–21.Google Scholar
Butler, Joseph. (1993) Fifteen Sermons. Charlottesville: Lincoln-Rembrandt Publishing.Google Scholar
Cassam, Quassim. (2014) Self-Knowledge for Humans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Clifford, W. K. (1879) Lectures and Essays, vol. 2. Edited by Stephen, Leslie and Pollock, Frederick. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Darwall, Stephen. (1977) ‘Two Kinds of Respect’. Ethics, 88, 3649.Google Scholar
Feinberg, Joel. (2008) ‘Absurd Self-Fulfillment’. In Klemke, E. D. and Cahn, Steven M. (eds.), The Meaning of Life: A Reader (New York: Oxford University Press), 153183.Google Scholar
Fessler, Ann. (2006) The Girls Who Went Away: The Hidden History of Women Who Surrendered Children for Adoption in the Decades before Roe v. Wade. New York: Penguin Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry. (2004) ‘On Love, and Its Reasons’. In Frankfurt, The Reasons of Love (Princeton: Princeton University Press), 3368.Google Scholar
Hill, Thomas E. (1991) Autonomy and Self-Respect. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hurka, Thomas. (2011) The Best Things in Life. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (2002) Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. Edited and translated by Hill, Thomas E. Jr. and Zweig, Arnulf. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. (1996) The Metaphysics of Morals. Edited and translated by Gregor, Mary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Linehan, Elizabeth A. (1982) ‘Ignorance, Self-Deception and Moral Accountability’. Journal of Value Inquiry, 16, 101–15.Google Scholar
Meyers, Diana T. (1989) Self, Society, and Personal Choice. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Meyers, Diana T. (2004) Being Yourself: Essays on Identity, Action and Social Life. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Munro, Alice. (1977) The Beggar Maid. Middlesex: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Munro, Alice. (1982) Interview. In Twigg, Alan (ed.), For Openers: Conversations with 24 Canadian Writers (Madeira Park: Harbour), 1320.Google Scholar
Murdoch, Iris. (1997) ‘The Idea of Perfection’. In Murdoch, Existentialists and Mystics: Writings On Philosophy and Literature (New York; Penguin Books), 299362.Google Scholar
O'Hagan, Emer. (2012) ‘Self-Knowledge and Moral Stupidity’. Ratio: An International Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 25, 291306.Google Scholar
Plato. (1997) Plato: Collected Works. Edited by John Cooper, M.. Translated by Grube, G. M. A.. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph. (2001). Value, Respect, and Attachment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Roessler, Beate. (2015) ‘Autonomy, Self-Knowledge, and Oppression’. In Oshana, Marina (ed.), Personal Autonomy and Social Oppression: Philosophical Perspectives (New York: Routledge), 6884.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (1998) What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Seyersted, Per. (1992) ‘“Who Do You Think You Are?” Alice Munro and the Place of Origin’. American Studies in Scandinavia, 24, 1723.Google Scholar
Shakespeare, William. (2002) Oxford Shakespeare: The Complete Sonnets and Poems. Edited by Burrow, Colin. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, Adam. (1976) The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Edited by Raphael, D. D. and Macfie, A. L.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Telfer, Elizabeth. (1968) ‘Self-Respect’. Philosophical Quarterly, 18, 114–21.Google Scholar
Tiberius, Valerie. (2008) The Reflective Life: Living Wisely within Our Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thomas, Laurence. (1986) ‘Justice, Happiness, and Self-Knowledge’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 16, 6382.Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David. (1999) ‘Love as a Moral Emotion’. Ethics, 109, 338–74.Google Scholar
von Furstenberg, Diane. (2015) The Woman I Wanted to Be. New York: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Wilde, Oscar. (1894) ‘Phrases and Philosophies for the Use of the Young’. Chameleon, 1 (http://www.feedbooks.com/userbook/11356/phrases-and-philosophies-for-the-use-of-the-young).Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. (1981) Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wolf, Susan. (2015) The Variety of Values. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar