Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dk4vv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T19:38:05.878Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Objectivity and Reflection in Heidegger's Theory of Intentionality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2016

TUCKER MCKINNEY*
Affiliation:
COLLEGE OF WILLIAM AND MARYtwmckinney@wm.edu

Abstract:

Heidegger claims that Dasein's capacity for adopting intentional stances toward the world is grounded in the reflective structure of its being, which dictates that Dasein exists for the sake of a possibility of itself. Commentators have glossed this reflective structure in terms of the idea that our subjection to the normative demands of intentionality is grounded in a basic commitment to upholding an identity-concept, such as an occupation or a social role. I argue that this gloss has serious adverse implications for Heidegger's philosophical project and for the internal coherence of his theory of intention. I recommend an alternative gloss on the reflective structure of existence, according to which sustaining a robust claim to openness to the world specifies the universal, formal object of intentional stance-taking. The reflective structure of existence should be understood through the concept of self-maintenance rather than that of self-definition.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Blattner, William. (1999) Heidegger's Temporal Idealism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Braver, Lee. (2007) A Thing of This World: A History of Continental Anti-Realism. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Burch, Matthew. (2010) ‘Death and Deliberation: Overcoming the Decisionism Critique of Heidegger's Practical Philosophy’. Inquiry, 53, 211–34.Google Scholar
Crowell, Steven. (2007a) ‘Conscience and Reason: Heidegger and the Grounds of Intentionality’. In Crowell, Steven and Malpas, Jeff (eds.), Transcendental Heidegger (Stanford: Stanford University Press), 4362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crowell, Steven. (2007b) ‘Sorge or Selbstbewußtsein? Heidegger and Korsgaard on the Sources of Normativity’. European Journal of Philosophy, 15, 315–33.Google Scholar
Crowell, Steven. (2013) Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, Hubert. (1991) Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger's Sein und Zeit, Division I. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Engstrom, Stephen. (2009) The Form of Practical Knowledge: A Study of the Categorical Imperative. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Golob, Sacha. (2014) Heidegger on Concepts, Freedom, and Normativity. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Haugeland, John. (2000) ‘Truth and Finitude: Heidegger's Transcendental Existentialism’. In Wrathall, Mark and Malpas, Jeff (eds.), Heidegger, Authenticity, and Modernity: Essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus, volume 1 (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 4377.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin (1962) Being and Time. Translated by Macquarrie, John and Robinson, Edward. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin. GA 24. (1975) Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie. Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin. GA 26. (1978) Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Logik im Ausgang von Leibniz. Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin. GA 31. (1982) Vom Wesen der Menschlichen Freiheit: Einleitung in die Philosophie. Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin. (2006) Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. ([1785] 1993) Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by Ellington, James W.. 3rd Edition. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. ([1788] 1997) Critique of Practical Reason. Translated by Gregor, Mary. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kenny, Anthony. (1963) Action, Emotion, and Will. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. (1996) The Sources of Normativity. Edited by O'Neill, Onora. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. (2009) Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Okrent, Mark. (1988) Heidegger's Pragmatism: Understanding, Being, and the Critique of Metaphysics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Okrent, Mark. (2000) ‘Heidegger and Korsgaard on Human Reflection’. Philosophical Topics, 27, 4776.Google Scholar
Okrent, Mark. (2007) ‘The “I Think” and the For-the-Sake-of-Which’. In Crowell, Steven and Malpas, Jeff (eds.), Transcendental Heidegger (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press), 151–68.Google Scholar
Sheehan, Thomas. (2001) ‘A Paradigm Shift in Heidegger Research’. Continental Philosophy Review, 34, 183202.Google Scholar