Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T05:08:27.697Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Decisional enhancement and autonomy: public attitudes towards overt and covert nudges

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2023

Gidon Felsen*
Affiliation:
Department of Physiology & Biophysics, and Neuroscience Program, University of Colorado School of Medicine, 12800 E. 19th Ave., Mail Stop 8307, Aurora, CO, 80045
Noah Castelo*
Affiliation:
National Core for Neuroethics, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC, Canada
Peter B. Reiner
Affiliation:
National Core for Neuroethics, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC, Canada
*
Present address: Sauder School of Business, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC, Canada
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Ubiquitous cognitive biases hinder optimal decision making. Recent calls to assist decision makers in mitigating these biases—via interventions commonly called “nudges”—have been criticized as infringing upon individual autonomy. We tested the hypothesis that such “decisional enhancement” programs that target overt decision making—i.e., conscious, higher-order cognitive processes—would be more acceptable than similar programs that affect covert decision making—i.e., subconscious, lower-order processes. We presented respondents with vignettes in which they chose between an option that included a decisional enhancement program and a neutral option. In order to assess preferences for overt or covert decisional enhancement, we used the contrastive vignette technique in which different groups of respondents were presented with one of a pair of vignettes that targeted either conscious or subconscious processes. Other than the nature of the decisional enhancement, the vignettes were identical, allowing us to isolate the influence of the type of decisional enhancement on preferences. Overall, we found support for the hypothesis that people prefer conscious decisional enhancement. Further, respondents who perceived the influence of the program as more conscious than subconscious reported that their decisions under the program would be more “authentic”. However, this relative favorability was somewhat contingent upon context. We discuss our results with respect to the implementation and ethics of decisional enhancement.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
The authors license this article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License.
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors [2013] This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

1 Introduction

It has been well established that humans do not behave as fully rational actors but instead exhibit pervasive and predictable biases in decision-making (Reference ArielyAriely, 2008; Reference Marteau, Ogilvie, Roland, Suhrcke and KellyTversky & Kahneman, 1974). Efforts to counteract these biases in order to improve the outcome of decisions could be considered akin to, but distinct from, traditional cognitive enhancement (Reference Farah, Illes, Cook-Deegan, Gardner, Kandel, King, Parens, Sahakian and WolpeFarah et al., 2004) in that the goal is maximization of the value of choice outcomes, rather than improvement in particular domains of cognitive function that contribute to intelligence.Footnote 1 Recent proposals for such “decisional enhancement” have attracted interest from such diverse disciplines as public policy, psychology, economics, law, and ethics (Reference Jolls, Sunstein and ThalerJolls et al., 1998; Reference Camerer, Issacharoff, Loewenstein, O’Donoghue and RabinCamerer et al., 2003; Reference RachlinskiRachlinski, 2002; Reference Sunstein and ThalerSunstein & Thaler, 2003; Reference TroutTrout, 2005; Reference Blumenthal-Barby and BurroughsBlumenthal-Barby & Burroughs, 2012; Reference Bovens, Grüne-Yanoff and HanssonBovens, 2009). One well-known idea proposes modifying the environment in which choices are made such that individuals are “nudged” into making better decisions (Reference Thaler and SunsteinThaler & Sunstein, 2008). For example, requiring employees to opt out of, rather than opt in to, a retirement savings program takes advantage of the natural tendency to select the default option, thereby promoting the decision to save more for retirement. This approach has been dubbed “libertarian paternalism” in that a key feature of such decisional enhancement programs is that, while certain choices become more likely than others, the programs do not restrict the range of choices available to the individual. Although more employees will choose to save under the program described above, any individual employee remains free to choose to save any amount they want, including nothing.

Despite this attempt to preserve the range of available options, a key ethical issue engendered by the intentional attempt to influence individuals’ choices—even for their own benefit—is the potential for infringement on individual autonomy (Reference Blumenthal-Barby and BurroughsBlumenthal-Barby & Burroughs, 2012; Reference DworkinDworkin, 1988; Reference HillHill, 2007). One line of criticism suggests that deigning to know which choice is best for the individual based on presumed objective measures of the choice outcome disregards other, unknowable, factors that contribute to the decision, such as the individual’s value system (Reference White, Gaus, Favor and LamontWhite, 2008). For example, even if participating in a retirement savings program would objectively increase an employee’s future wealth she may oppose the program because it is inconsistent with her higher-order beliefs about investing, and therefore choosing to not participate in the program should not be considered a “poor” decision. According to this line of criticism, manipulating how the options are presented with the express purpose of making her more likely to join the program thus subverts her belief system, which disrespects her dignity as a person capable of autonomous decisions.

Thus, there is an inevitable tension between the respect for autonomy and the potentially beneficial outcomes—for both the individual and society—of improved decisions (Reference Blumenthal-Barby and BurroughsBlumenthal-Barby & Burroughs, 2012). It is therefore of interest to determine how the public—key stakeholders in any social engineering program—deems the acceptability of decisional enhancement, and whether the degree of acceptability is dependent on particular features of the program (Reference Castelo, Reiner and FelsenCastelo et al., 2012; House of Lords Science and Technology Select Committee, 2011). Although some studies have surveyed the levels of acceptance of generic decisional enhancement programs across different populations (Reference Branson, Duffy, Perry and WellingsBranson et al., 2011), few have examined the factors of specific programs that may affect acceptability (Reference Marteau, Ogilvie, Roland, Suhrcke and KellyMarteau et al., 2011). Our study explores the question of whether the nature of the influence on decisions—specifically, whether it is overt or covert, a dimension particularly relevant for the consideration of autonomy—affects public acceptability of decisional enhancement programs.

In principle, decisional enhancement could affect one or more of the processes involved in making autonomous decisions. Three criteria are generally accepted as being required for a decision to be considered autonomous: it must be (1) consistent with an individual’s conscious, higher-order desires; (2) rational, made with sufficient time and information to allow reflection; and (3) free from covert external influence (Reference ChristmanChristman, 1991; Reference DworkinDworkin, 1976; Reference DworkinDworkin, 1988; Reference Felsen and ReinerFelsen & Reiner, 2011; Reference FrankfurtFrankfurt, 1971; Reference SugdenSugden, 1991; Reference TaylorTaylor, 2005). Overt influences on decisions—i.e., those of which the decision maker is aware and can consciously process—do not appear to violate any of these conditions. Covert influences, however, present a challenge. While they plainly violate the third condition and therefore infringe upon autonomy, they may also be seen to enhance autonomy by increasing the likelihood of a decision aligned with the first condition, their higher-order desires (Reference TroutTrout, 2005). For example, subconsciously decreasing hunger (a lower-order desire) would make refraining from overeating (a higher-order desire) more likely.

While some studies suggest that covert influences may have a greater effect than overt influences on choice outcome (e.g., Reference Duffy and VergesDuffy & Verges, 2008; Reference Goldstein, Cialdini and GriskeviciusGoldstein et al., 2008; Reference Nolan, Schultz, Cialdini, Goldstein and GriskeviciusNolan et al., 2008; Reference Wisdom, Downs and LoewensteinWisdom et al., 2010), to our knowledge the question of which is more acceptable has not been addressed empirically. If covert influences are found to be more acceptable, then the most effective decisional enhancement programs would also be the most acceptable, providing a clear path for implementation of such programs. If, however, covert influences are found to be less acceptable, then the most effective and most acceptable strategies would be in conflict and policy makers would need to consider not only the value of improved decision making but also the tradeoff in terms of individual autonomy.

We hypothesized that overt influences would be more acceptable than covert influences. Consistent with the multiple necessary conditions for autonomy and the complexity of human decision processes, we found that our hypothesis was supported within most contexts (eating, purchasing, exercising, and investing decisions), but not in another (workplace productivity decisions). We discuss our findings within the framework of autonomous decision making, with an eye towards their application to the policy debate on, and ethics of, decisional enhancement.

2 Method

We used a between-subjects design—the contrastive vignette technique (Reference Burstin, Doughtie and RaphaeliBurstin et al., 1980)—to probe public attitudes towards manipulations that employed either conscious (overt) or subconscious (covert) decisional enhancement. Different versions of a single vignette with minimal variations were presented (Appendix), and respondents across conditions (subconscious and conscious) answered an identical set of questions (Table 1). Following acceptance of informed consent and completion of a brief set of demographic questions, each respondent was randomly assigned to see one and only one version of the vignette, within only one context (e.g., healthy eating), and was blind to the contrastive condition. The effects of the type of influence on decisions (e.g., subconscious), can be measured by comparing responses across conditions. Carefully constructed contrastive vignettes therefore allow us to control for demand characteristics, which are features of the experiment that could potentially alert participants to the study’s hypothesis. Such demand characteristics could in turn cause participants to alter their responses, consciously or not, in order to support or undermine the hypothesis or according to social desirability concerns (Reference OrneOrne, 1962; Reference Nichols and ManerNichols & Maner, 2008).

Table 1: Questions in the Eating scenario. All respondents within each scenario were asked the same 5 questions (in addition to the comprehension check). The wording of some questions varied slightly across scenarios as appropriate; shown here are the questions asked in the Eating scenario. The vignette was presented following Question 1. Anchors for each 9-point Likert scale, and their corresponding numerical values (as superscript), are shown following each question.

Respondents from the United States and Canada were recruited via Amazon’s Mechanical Turk (Reference IpeirotisIpeirotis, 2010; Reference Paolacci, Chandler and IpeirotisPaolacci et al., 2010). Respondents were compensated $0.25 for completion of the survey. Once they accepted the assignment, they were directed to an external website, where they were randomly assigned to one of ten vignettes, composed of five pairs of contrastive vignettes.

The two versions of each pair of contrastive vignettes were designed to be as similar as possible in every respect except for the type of decisional influence: one purported to influence conscious processing and the other purported to influence subconscious processing. Differences in responses to the paired contrastive vignettes can therefore be largely attributed to whether the manipulation was conscious or subconscious. Five scenarios were explored: healthy eating, prudent purchasing, increased exercise, prudent investing, and productivity at work (referred to below as the Eating, Purchasing, Exercising, Investing, and Productivity scenarios, respectively). For example, in the Eating scenario, respondents in the SUBCONSCIOUS group read that a “cafeteria has been revamped so that unhealthy foods, such as candy bars, potato chips, and the like are not as conveniently located”, while respondents in the CONSCIOUS group read that a “cafeteria has been revamped so that all foods have their nutritional content clearly displayed.” The scenarios are in the Appendix. The effectiveness at reducing caloric intake of manipulations along each of these lines has been studied (Reference Chapman and OgdenChapman & Ogden, 2012; Reference Downs, Loewenstein and WisdomDowns et al., 2009; Reference Harnack and FrenchHarnack & French, 2008; Reference Pulos and LengPulos & Leng, 2010; Reference Roberto, Larsen, Agnew, Baik and BrownellRoberto et al., 2010; Reference Tandon, Zhou, Chan, Lozano, Couch, Glanz, Krieger and SaelensTandon et al., 2011; Reference Wisdom, Downs and LoewensteinWisdom et al., 2010), although to our knowledge their relative acceptability has not been examined.

Prior to the presentation of the vignettes, respondents were asked how much they felt they could use help making decisions within the context of the assigned scenario (Table 1, Question 1). This introductory query was used to determine whether attitudes towards subconscious and conscious decisional enhancement depended upon a desire for assistance.

Following each vignette, respondents were asked to consider a choice between two potential employers (Eating, Exercise, Investing, and Productivity) or credit card companies (Purchasing), where one employer/company offered the relevant decisional enhancement program while the other did not (the “neutral option”) (Table 1, Question 2). The primary outcome measure was the rating on a 9-point scale of the degree to which the program would affect the likelihood of favoring the option with the decisional enhancement program over the neutral option.

Three follow-up questions explored various aspects of respondents’ perceptions of the vignettes. First, respondents were asked to rate how authentic their decisions would be if they decided to select the option with the decisional enhancement program (Table 1, Question 3). Next, respondents were asked how the previously described program affected decision making (Table 1, Question 4). We used these responses as a measure of how the respondents perceived the effect of the program on decision making, which for some analyses is more informative than the stated condition (subconscious or conscious). Respondents were then offered the option of completing a free-form text box which asked them to tell us why they answered as they did (Table 1, Question 5). Finally, comprehension of the vignettes was verified; for example, respondents in the Eating scenario were asked which of the following “The previous question discussed”: “Strength training”, “Healthy food choices” (the correct answer), “Prudent online purchasing”, and “Improving productivity”. Correctly answering the comprehension check was required for responses to be including in the data set. The full set of vignettes, and questions presented for one representative scenario, can be found in the Appendix and Table 1, respectively.

3 Results

We collected data from 2,775 respondents from the United States and Canada who correctly answered the comprehension question at the end of the survey (mean age: 29.8 years; 40% female). Since our primary objective was to explore whether respondents felt that decisional enhancement programs that overtly affect conscious reasoning were more acceptable than those that covertly affect subconscious thought processes, we examined respondents’ stated perceptions of the manipulation (as affecting either conscious or subconscious decision making) to ensure the validity of our analyses. We found that, despite our explicit description of the manipulations as affecting either conscious or subconscious processing (Appendix), a sizeable fraction of each group perceived the intervention as incongruent with our description: 50% of the SUBCONSCIOUS group rated the manipulation as more conscious than subconscious, and 17% of the CONSCIOUS group rated the manipulation as more subconscious than conscious. In order to first analyze only the data from respondents whose perception matched our intended manipulation, we excluded respondents whose perception of the manipulation was incongruent with the assigned condition. We then tested the hypothesis that congruent respondents in the CONSCIOUS group would be more likely than congruent respondents in the SUBCONSCIOUS group to favor the option with the decisional enhancement program over the neutral option. The results support this hypothesis in the Eating, Purchasing, Exercising, and Investing scenarios, but not in the Productivity scenario (Figure 1; Eating, p = 0.0064; Purchasing, p ∼ .000; Exercising, p = 0.004; Investing, p ∼ .000; Productivity, p = 0.43. Results were similar when all respondents were included: Eating, p = 0.38; Purchasing, p = 0.004; Exercising, p = 0.025; Investing, p ∼ .000; Productivity, p = 0.83; 1-tailed t-tests).

Figure 1: Effect of condition (subconscious or conscious influence) on the relative favorability of the option with the decisional enhancement program over the neutral option. 1-tailed t-tests examined whether the CONSCIOUS group was more likely than the SUBCONSCIOUS group to favor the option with the decisional enhancement program, in each scenario. Respondents who perceived the effect of the program on decisions incongruently with their assigned condition were excluded. *, p < 0.01. Error bars, ± SEM.

In order to corroborate these results, we examined whether the likelihood of favoring the option with the decisional enhancement program (Table 1, Question 2) correlated with the respondents’ stated perception of how the program affected decision making (Table 1, Question 4). We included all respondents in this analysis (and in all subsequent analyses below), because we were specifically interested in how their stated perception of the manipulation as conscious or subconscious correlated with their stated preference for the option with the decisional enhancement program. In agreement with the results described above (Figure 1), there was a significant positive correlation between these variables in all scenarios except for the Productivity scenario (Table 2, row 1). In further support of our hypothesis, we found that respondents’ stated perception of the manipulation correlated with the extent to which they favored the option with the decisional enhancement program even within their assigned group (Table 2, rows 2-3).

Table 2: Correlation and regression results. Data from all respondents are included. Q1–4 refer to Questions 1–4 (see Table 1).

Any universally applied program—be it enacted by government, corporations, or other large organizations—will necessarily affect individuals who do not want help as well those who do. We therefore examined how the sentiments of respondents who reported that they could use help making decisions compared to those of respondents who reported that they could not use help. As expected, across all scenarios respondents in both the SUBCONSCIOUS and CONSCIOUS groups who wanted help were more likely to favor the option with the decisional enhancement program over the neutral option (Table 2, rows 4-5). However, the degree to which respondents wanted help had little effect on the relative favorability for the option with the conscious rather than subconscious decisional enhancement program: Only in the Eating scenario did this variable moderate the size of the effect (Table 2, row 6). Thus, we found support for our hypothesis that decisional enhancement that affects conscious deliberation is more acceptable than decisional enhancement that affects subconscious processes, but our results did not generalize across all five scenarios. We discuss possible interpretations of these results below.

Finally, we examined whether the type of manipulation (conscious or subconscious) affected the perceived authenticity of respondents’ decisions within the context of the decisional enhancement program. We first examined whether stated perceptions of how the program affected decision making (Table 1, Question 4) correlated with the extent to which decisions in the context of the program would be perceived as reflecting authentic preferences (Table 1, Question 3). We found a significant positive correlation in all scenarios (Table 2, row 7). In addition, we found that respondents’ likelihood of opting for the decisional enhancement program was related to whether the decisions they made were perceived as being authentic: In all scenarios, there was a significant positive correlation between the degree to which respondents felt that decisions made within the context of the decisional enhancement program would be authentic and how likely they were to opt for the program (Table 2, row 8; Figure 2). These data support the idea that preserving the individual’s capacity for making authentic decisions is an important condition for the acceptability of decisional enhancement programs.

Figure 2: Correlation between the authenticity of decisions made within the context of the program and the relative favorability of the option with the decisional enhancement program over the neutral option. (A) Paired responses to Questions 2 and 3 (see Table 1) are shown for all respondents in in the Eating scenario. Best-fit line shown in gray. (B-E) As in (A), in the Purchasing, Exercising, Investing, and Productivity scenarios, respectively. Circle size corresponds to number of respondents for each pair of responses, normalized within each scenario.

4 Discussion

Progress in the behavioral sciences has revealed the many ways in which human decision-making predictably departs from the rational actor model (Reference ArielyAriely, 2008; Reference KahnemanKahneman, 2011; Reference Jolls, Sunstein and ThalerStanovich & West, 2000; Reference Strack and DeutschStrack & Deutsch, 2004; Reference Marteau, Ogilvie, Roland, Suhrcke and KellyTversky & Kahneman, 1974) This insight has inspired “choice architects”, i.e., engineers of the environments in which decisions are made, to influence decisions according to their desired outcomes (which may or may not align with the desired outcomes of the decision makers). As more organizations consider implementing such programs, debate has arisen about the acceptability of their use given the frequent lack of objective criteria about what constitutes a better decision outcome, as well as the desire to protect autonomous decision making (Reference Blumenthal-Barby and BurroughsBlumenthal-Barby & Burroughs, 2012; Reference Bovens, Grüne-Yanoff and HanssonBovens, 2009; Reference Hausman and WelchHausman & Welch, 2010; Reference HillHill, 2007; Reference MitchellMitchell, 2004; House of Lords Science and Technology Select Committee, 2011; Reference SugdenSugden, 2008; Reference Sunstein and ThalerSunstein & Thaler, 2003; Reference White, Gaus, Favor and LamontWhite, 2008). The dominant narrative in this debate assumes that decisional enhancement necessarily infringes upon individual autonomy, and proceeds to weigh this cost against the benefits of the manipulation. There are, however, theoretical reasons to question the generality of this tradeoff. As described in the introduction, covert influences on decisions may subvert the autonomy of the decision maker. However, covertly influencing decision processes such that the resulting decision is aligned with higher-order desires may actually enhance autonomy (Reference TroutTrout, 2005), especially in situations in which the target population is known to want help with a given behavior. How these considerations interact in order to determine whether autonomy is reduced or enhanced by particular manipulations, and how this interaction depends on the context and the goals of the decision maker herself, are open questions that merit empirical study.

As an initial foray into empirically addressing the question of how to improve decision making while infringing minimally on autonomy, the present study examined public attitudes towards decisional enhancement programs intended to influence decision making either covertly or overtly. We probed how likely respondents would be to participate in such a program, as well as their perceptions of how authentic their resulting decisions would be. While overall we found support for our hypothesis that overt, rather than covert, influences would be more acceptable, our results depended to some extent on the specific context. In the Eating, Purchasing, Exercising, and Investing scenarios, but not the Productivity scenario, the relative favorability of the decisional enhancement program over the neutral option was higher when the influence on decision processes was conscious than when it was subconscious (Figure 1). In the Eating scenario only, the relative favorability of covert influences was moderated by the degree to which respondents wanted help such that, the less respondents wanted help, the more favorable they were to the conscious than the subconscious influence (Table 2, row 6). Under no conditions were the respondents more favorable to the subconscious influence than to the conscious influence. Further, we found that the degree to which respondents believed that their decisions within the context of the program would be authentic correlated with 1) the degree to which the influence affected conscious decision processes, and 2) how likely they were to favor the decisional enhancement program over the neutral option (Figure 2). Together, these results suggest that public acceptance of a given intervention may depend on the degree to which it infringes upon autonomy, but is also affected by other context-specific factors.

It is notable that we did we not observe a preference for overt over covert influences in the Productivity scenario (Figure 1; Table 2, row 1). One possibility that we considered was that respondents perceived the outcome of “enhanced” decisions as not benefiting them personally, i.e., not being in their own best interest. In an initial version of this vignette, the benefit to the “consultant” (i.e., the respondent) was ambiguous and respondents were no more favorable to conscious than subconscious decisional enhancement (data not shown). For this reason, we modified our original Productivity vignettes to make it clear that the benefits of the program accrued to the “consultant” and not to the company (Appendix), but we still found that the CONSCIOUS group was no more likely than the SUBCONSCIOUS group to favor the option with the decisional enhancement program over the neutral option. Thus, the lack of an effect in the Productivity scenario is not due to a perceived absence of personal benefit from the decisional enhancement program.

The general observation that context has a modest but meaningful impact upon preference for conscious versus subconscious decisional enhancement should give choice architects pause. Several possible explanations are worthy of further study. For example, it is possible that decisions in some contexts are seen as less “one’s own” in the first place, perhaps due to the personal experience of being unable to control their decisions, and therefore individuals may be more accepting of decisional enhancement programs in those contexts. Another possibility is that people may feel that decisions made in some contexts are more consciously driven than decisions made in other contexts. For example, respondents who wanted help with eating decisions may have been more likely to recognize that food choices are often subconsciously driven, and were therefore just as likely to favor the decisional enhancement program with covert influences as the program with overt influences, whereas respondents who did not want help with food choices reverted to the expected preference for overt influences (Table 3, row 6).

It is worth noting some limitations of this study. Most obviously, the vignettes are hypothetical: our respondents reported how they thought they would act if placed in a particular situation, which may differ from how they would actually act in that real situation (Reference Chang, Lusk and NorwoodChang et al., 2009). A second limitation is the categorical distinction between conscious and subconscious manipulations. Each of the scenarios clearly described the manipulation as either explicitly “conscious” or “subconscious” (Appendix). Nevertheless, a substantial fraction of each group did not perceive the influence as explicitly stated, rating subconscious influences as more conscious than subconscious, and vice versa. This incongruence may have been due to inattentive respondents, who failed to understand our descriptions, but these same respondents passed our comprehension check, suggesting that it was not due to lack of attention. Instead, their stated opinions about the influence may reflect the fact that no influence affects only conscious or subconscious processes. It would therefore be more accurate to consider the influence of a decisional enhancement program to lie somewhere along the continuum from covert to overt. Indeed, this is why we examined how stated perceptions of the degree to which the program affected conscious processing correlated with several variables (Table 2). Despite these limitations, the present study is a necessary first step towards grounding the debate surrounding autonomy and the use of decisional enhancement in empirical data. It would be useful for future studies to examine these issues in “real life”, as opposed to survey-based, situations.

Despite the advantages of the contrastive vignette approach (see Method), it is possible that directly asking respondents whether they prefer a subconscious or conscious decisional enhancement program would more accurately reflect their opinion on the relevant policy question. To determine whether our results were affected by our methodology, we collected data from a new set of respondents using a direct comparison test. This experiment was identical to our Eating scenario except that respondents chose between Company A, which employed a decisional enhancement program in its cafeteria that targeted subconscious processes, and Company B, which employed a decisional enhancement program in its cafeteria that targeted conscious processes. We found that respondents significantly favored Company B (with the program targeting conscious processing) (p < 0.01, one-tailed t-test, n = 155). The magnitude of this effect (5.52 − 5.00 = 0.52) was similar to that observed in the contrastive vignette version of the Eating scenario (Conscious condition: 6.81; Subconscious condition: 6.33; difference: 6.81 − 6.33 = 0.48), suggesting that our results were not influenced by the use of contrastive vignettes.

These data have clear implications for public policy. Proponents of decisional enhancement may hesitate to enact programs that enhance decision making if they see the influence as restricting the individual’s ability to choose freely—an effect that may be seen as particularly pernicious with covert influences (Reference White, Gaus, Favor and LamontWhite, 2008). However, where public attitudes are indifferent between conscious and subconscious influences, we suggest that policy makers gain license to use the most effective tools at their disposal, even those that are covert. This recommendation is consistent with the possibility that the subconscious processing of covert external influences is sufficiently pervasive to call into question the degree to which many decisions can be autonomous at all (Reference Felsen and ReinerFelsen & Reiner, 2011). Hence, well-meaning attempts to “preserve” autonomy at the expense of improved decision outcomes may be misguided. On the other hand, in situations where public attitudes do indicate a preference for overt influences, or a distaste for covert influences, due consideration to the balance between outcomes and the preservation of perceived autonomy should be informed by empirical data.

Appendix:

Contrastive vignettes. Respondents were randomly assigned to 1 of the 5 scenarios (Eating, Purchasing, Exercising, Investing, or Productivity) and to 1 of the 2 conditions (subconscious or conscious). Respondents within each scenario were presented with identical text with the exception of the [Subconscious] and [Conscious] columns.

Footnotes

This study was supported by grants from the Boettcher Foundation (G.F.) and the Canadian Institutes of Health Research (P.B.R.). The authors thank Adrian Carter for helpful comments on the manuscript.

1 Note that increasing intelligence alone does not defend against maladaptive decision biases (Reference KahnemanStanovich & West, 2008).

References

Ariely, D. (2008). Predictably irrational: The hidden forces that shape our decisions. New York: Harper.Google Scholar
Blumenthal-Barby, J. S., & Burroughs, H. (2012). Seeking better health care outcomes: the ethics of using the “nudge.” The American Journal of Bioethics, 12, 110.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bovens, L. (2009). The ethics of nudge. In Grüne-Yanoff, T. & Hansson, S. O. (Eds.), Preference Change: Approaches from Philosophy, Economics and Psychology (pp. 207220). Berlin and New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Branson, C., Duffy, B., Perry, C., & Wellings, D. (2011). Acceptable behaviour? Public opinion on behaviour change policy. Ipsos Social Research Institute.Google Scholar
Burstin, K., Doughtie, E. B., & Raphaeli, A. (1980). Contrastive vignette technique: An indirect methodology designed to address reactive social attitude measurement. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 10, 147165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Camerer, C., Issacharoff, S., Loewenstein, G., O’Donoghue, T., & Rabin, M. (2003). Regulation for conservatives: Behavioral economics and the case for “asymmetric paternalism.” University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 151, 12111254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Castelo, N., Reiner, P. B., & Felsen, G. (2012). Balancing autonomy and decisional enhancement: An evidence-based approach. The American Journal of Bioethics, 12, 3031.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chang, J. B., Lusk, J. L., & Norwood, F. B. (2009). How closely do hypothetical surveys and laboratory experiments predict field behavior? American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 91, 518534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chapman, K., & Ogden, J. (2012). Nudging customers towards healthier choices: an intervention in the university canteen. Journal of Food Research, 1, 1321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christman, J. (1991). Autonomy and personal history. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 21, 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downs, J. S., Loewenstein, G., & Wisdom, J. (2009). Strategies for promoting healthier food choices. American Economic Review, 99, 159164.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Duffy, S., & Verges, M. (2008). It matters a hole lot: Perceptual affordances of waste containers influence recycling compliance. Environment and Behavior, 41, 741749.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, G. (1976). Autonomy and behavior control. Hastings Center Report, 6, 2328.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dworkin, G. (1988). The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farah, M. J., Illes, J., Cook-Deegan, R., Gardner, H., Kandel, E., King, P., Parens, E., Sahakian, B, & Wolpe, P. R. (2004). Neurocognitive enhancement: What can we do and what should we do? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 5, 421425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Felsen, G., & Reiner, P. B. (2011). How the neuroscience of decision making informs our conception of autonomy. AJOB Neuroscience (Special issue: Free will and agency in neuroscience), 2, 314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy, 68, 520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldstein, N. J., Cialdini, R. B., & Griskevicius, V. (2008). A room with a viewpoint: Using social norms to motivate environmental conservation in hotels. Journal of Consumer Research, 35, 472482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harnack, L. J., & French, S. A. (2008). Effect of point-of-purchase calorie labeling on restaurant and cafeteria food choices: A review of the literature. International Journal of Behavioral Nutrition and Physical Activity, 5, 51.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hausman, D. M., & Welch, B. (2010). Debate: To nudge or not to nudge. Journal of Political Philosophy, 18, 123136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, C. (2007). Anti-Anti-Anti-Paternalism. New York University Journal of Law and Liberty, 2, 444454.Google Scholar
House of Lords Science and Technology Select Committee. (2011). Behaviour Change - Second Report.Google Scholar
Ipeirotis, P. G. (2010). Demographics of mechanical turk. Retrieved from http://www.ipeirotis.com/wp-content/uploads/2012/02/CeDER-10-01.pdf. Accessed 8/13/2012.Google Scholar
Jolls, C., Sunstein, C. R., & Thaler, R. (1998). A behavioral approach to law and economics. Stanford Law Review, 50, 14711550.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.Google Scholar
Marteau, T. M., Ogilvie, D., Roland, M., Suhrcke, M., & Kelly, M. P. (2011). Judging nudging: Can nudging improve population health? BMJ, 342, 263265.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mitchell, G. (2004). Libertarian paternalism is an oxymoron. Northwestern University Law Review, 99, 12451277.Google Scholar
Nichols, A., & Maner, J. (2008). The Good-Subject Effect: Investigating Participant Demand Characteristics. The Journal of General Psychology, 135, 151165.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nolan, J. M., Schultz, P. W., Cialdini, R. B., Goldstein, N. J., & Griskevicius, V. (2008). Normative social influence is underdetected. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34, 913923.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Orne, M. T. (1962). On the social psychology of the psychological experiment: With particular reference to demand characteristics and their implications. American Psychologist, 17, 776783.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paolacci, G., Chandler, J., & Ipeirotis, P. G. (2010). Running experiments on Amazon Mechanical Turk. Judgment and Decision Making, 5, 411419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pulos, E., & Leng, K. (2010). Evaluation of a voluntary menu-labeling program in full-service restaurants. American Journal of Public Health, 100, 10351039.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rachlinski, J. J. (2002). The uncertain psychological case for paternalism. Northwestern University Law Review, 97, 11651225.Google Scholar
Roberto, C. A., Larsen, P. D., Agnew, H., Baik, J., & Brownell, K. D. (2010). Evaluating the impact of menu labeling on food choices and intake. American Journal of Public Health, 100, 312318.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stanovich, K. E., & West, R. F. (2000). Individual differences in reasoning: implications for the rationality debate? The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23, 645665.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stanovich, K. E., & West, R. F. (2008). On the relative independence of thinking biases and cognitive ability. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 94, 672695.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Strack, F., & Deutsch, R. (2004). Reflective and impulsive determinants of social behavior. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 8, 220247.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sugden, R. (1991). Rational choice: A survey of contributions from economics and philosophy. The Economic Journal, 101, 751785.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, R. (2008). Why incoherent preferences do not justify paternalism. Constitutional Political Economy, 19, 226248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sunstein, C. R., & Thaler, R. H. (2003). Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron. University of Chicago Law Review, 70, 11591202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tandon, P. S., Zhou, C., Chan, N. L., Lozano, P., Couch, S. C., Glanz, K., Krieger, J., & Saelens, B. E. (2011). The impact of menu labeling on fast-food purchases for children and parents. American Journal of Preventive Medicine, 41, 434438.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Taylor, J. (2005). Personal autonomy: New essays on personal autonomy and its role in contemporary moral philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. R. (2008). Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Trout, J. D. (2005). Paternalism and cognitive bias. Law and Philosophy, 24, 393434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: heuristics and biases. Science, 185, 11241131.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
White, M. D. (2008). Behavioral law and economics: the assault on consent, will, and dignity. In Gaus, G., Favor, C., & Lamont, J. (Eds.), Essays on philosophy, politics and economics: Integration and common research projects (pp. 201224). Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Wisdom, J., Downs, J. S., & Loewenstein, G. (2010). Promoting healthy choices: information versus convenience. American Economic Journal: Applied Economics, 2, 164178.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1: Questions in the Eating scenario. All respondents within each scenario were asked the same 5 questions (in addition to the comprehension check). The wording of some questions varied slightly across scenarios as appropriate; shown here are the questions asked in the Eating scenario. The vignette was presented following Question 1. Anchors for each 9-point Likert scale, and their corresponding numerical values (as superscript), are shown following each question.

Figure 1

Figure 1: Effect of condition (subconscious or conscious influence) on the relative favorability of the option with the decisional enhancement program over the neutral option. 1-tailed t-tests examined whether the CONSCIOUS group was more likely than the SUBCONSCIOUS group to favor the option with the decisional enhancement program, in each scenario. Respondents who perceived the effect of the program on decisions incongruently with their assigned condition were excluded. *, p < 0.01. Error bars, ± SEM.

Figure 2

Table 2: Correlation and regression results. Data from all respondents are included. Q1–4 refer to Questions 1–4 (see Table 1).

Figure 3

Figure 2: Correlation between the authenticity of decisions made within the context of the program and the relative favorability of the option with the decisional enhancement program over the neutral option. (A) Paired responses to Questions 2 and 3 (see Table 1) are shown for all respondents in in the Eating scenario. Best-fit line shown in gray. (B-E) As in (A), in the Purchasing, Exercising, Investing, and Productivity scenarios, respectively. Circle size corresponds to number of respondents for each pair of responses, normalized within each scenario.

Supplementary material: File

Felsen et al. supplementary material

Felsen et al. supplementary material 1
Download Felsen et al. supplementary material(File)
File 1.2 KB
Supplementary material: File

Felsen et al. supplementary material

Felsen et al. supplementary material 2
Download Felsen et al. supplementary material(File)
File 1.6 KB
Supplementary material: File

Felsen et al. supplementary material

Felsen et al. supplementary material 3
Download Felsen et al. supplementary material(File)
File 2.5 KB
Supplementary material: File

Felsen et al. supplementary material

Felsen et al. supplementary material 4
Download Felsen et al. supplementary material(File)
File 1.1 KB
Supplementary material: File

Felsen et al. supplementary material

Felsen et al. supplementary material 5
Download Felsen et al. supplementary material(File)
File 2.6 KB
Supplementary material: File

Felsen et al. supplementary material

Felsen et al. supplementary material 6
Download Felsen et al. supplementary material(File)
File 2.9 KB
Supplementary material: File

Felsen et al. supplementary material

Felsen et al. supplementary material 7
Download Felsen et al. supplementary material(File)
File 2.7 KB
Supplementary material: File

Felsen et al. supplementary material

Felsen et al. supplementary material 8
Download Felsen et al. supplementary material(File)
File 1.5 KB
Supplementary material: File

Felsen et al. supplementary material

Felsen et al. supplementary material 9
Download Felsen et al. supplementary material(File)
File 2.9 KB
Supplementary material: File

Felsen et al. supplementary material

Felsen et al. supplementary material 10
Download Felsen et al. supplementary material(File)
File 1.9 KB
Supplementary material: File

Felsen et al. supplementary material

Felsen et al. supplementary material 11
Download Felsen et al. supplementary material(File)
File 2.6 KB