Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T08:13:26.519Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kant’s Ideal of Systematicity in Historical Context

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 February 2021

Hein van den Berg*
Affiliation:
University of Amsterdam, Department of Philosophy, Institute for Logic, Language and Computation
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article explains Kant’s claim that sciences must take, at least as their ideal, the form of a ‘system’. I argue that Kant’s notion of systematicity can be understood against the background of de Jong and Betti’s Classical Model of Science (2010) and the writings of Georg Friedrich Meier and Johann Heinrich Lambert. According to my interpretation, Meier, Lambert and Kant accepted an axiomatic idea of science, articulated by the Classical Model, which elucidates their conceptions of systematicity. I show that Kant’s critique of the mathematical method is compatible with his adherence to this axiomatic conception of science. I further show that systematicity advances traditionally accepted logical ideals of scientific knowledge, which explains why Meier and Kant think that sciences must be ‘systematic’.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Kantian Review

1. Introduction

Kant claims that sciences must take the form of systems (MFNS, 4: 467) and his views on systematicity have received considerable attention (Falkenburg Reference Falkenburg2000: 376–85; Sturm Reference Sturm2009: 129–82; Hoyningen-Huene Reference Hoyningen-Huene2013: 155–8; van den Berg Reference van den Berg2014: 17–24; Gava Reference Gava2014; Blomme Reference Blomme2015; Gava Reference Gava2018).Footnote 1 However, it is not yet fully clear why Kant claims that sciences must be systematic. In this paper, I provide a historical analysis that elucidates the concept of systematicity and explains why systematicity is an ideal for science.

An overview of Kant’s remarks on systematicity is contained in the Kant-Lexikon (Willascheck et al. Reference Willascheck, Stolzenberg, Mohr and Bacin2015: 2238–42). Much of the literature concerned with systematicity focuses on how it can explain the necessity of empirical laws in Kant (McNulty Reference McNulty2015: 2–3). Friedman has argued that necessary laws of nature result from the subsumption of empirical regularities under a priori principles (Friedman Reference Friedman and Guyer1992). By contrast, system interpretations (Buchdahl, Reference Buchdahl1971: 29, 32–3); Kitcher Reference Kitcher and Butts1986: 206, 209–10; Guyer Reference Guyer2003: 280–9) argue that the necessity of empirical laws involves the embedding of empirical regularities in systems of judgements (McNulty Reference McNulty2015: 3; Breitenbach Reference Breitenbach, Ott and Patton2018: 111). In this article, I will not be concerned with the necessity of empirical laws. Rather, I explain the historical context of Kant’s notion of systematicity and elucidate how the ideal of systematicity is to be understood.

Following Hinske (Reference Hinske and Funke1990), Blomme (Reference Blomme2015) and Sturm (Reference Sturm2009: 129–46), who discuss systematicity in Wolff, Lambert, Meier and Kant, I argue that Kant’s notion of systematicity can be understood against the background of the writings of Georg Friedrich Meier and Johann Heinrich Lambert. (I also briefly discuss Wolff: on Wolff and Lambert, see Waibel Reference Waibel, Stolzenberg and Rudolph2007; on Wolff and Kant, see Gava Reference Gava2018.) However, in contrast to these authors, I do not think that this is because Meier or Lambert (or Wolff) provides the origins of Kant’s notion of systematicity. Rather, I argue that all three authors endorse a classical idea of axiomatic science that explains their accounts of systematicity.Footnote 2 This classical idea of axiomatic science has been articulated by de Jong and Betti (Reference Betti2010) through the so-called Classical Model of Science (hereafter: Classical Model). My contention is that the Classical Model illuminates the concept of systematicity adopted by Meier, Lambert and Kant.

Like de Jong and Betti (Reference Betti2010: 186), I use the term ‘axiomatic science’ in a broad sense. Axiomatic science in this sense denotes a science that has (i) fundamental judgements and non-fundamental judgements that follow from these fundamental judgements, and (ii) fundamental concepts and non-fundamental concepts that are defined in terms of these fundamental concepts. If we adopt this idea of axiomatic science, we can describe Meier, Lambert and Kant as endorsing such an idea of science. I am aware that Kant applies the word axiom only to the principles of mathematics and argues that philosophy does not have axioms in this specific sense of the word (section 3.2). However, Kant does accept that a science should satisfy conditions (i) and (ii), and hence can be taken to accept an axiomatic idea of science if one adopts my broad use of the term ‘axiomatic science’.

We can distinguish my position from Hinske’s, since Hinske connects the idea of systematicity to Wolff’s idea of an axiomatic ideal for science (henceforth, ‘axiomatic idea of science’) (Hinske Reference Hinske and Funke1990: 158–62; see also Gava Reference Gava2018: 286). Hinske argues that Wolff’s concept of a system was influenced by his mathematical method, which he construes as embodying such an axiomatic ideal. However, he argues that Kant rejected the mathematical method and did not endorse an axiomatic idea of science, which led Kant to adopt a novel concept of systematicity. I agree that Wolff’s axiomatic idea of science influenced his idea of systematicity. However, in contrast to Hinske, I argue that Meier, Lambert and Kant all accepted an axiomatic idea of science as articulated by the Classical Model, and that this explains their concepts of systematicity. To achieve this aim I show that Kant’s critique of Wolff’s mathematical method is consistent with his adherence to the Classical Model.

I further argue that Meier’s writings provide an additional reason for Meier and Kant to think that sciences should be systematic. In his Vernunftlehre (1752), Meier discusses logical perfections of scientific knowledge. Systematicity, as described above, furthers many of these perfections. Kant also embraced several of these perfections. Thus it is probable that systematicity was accepted as an ideal by Meier and Kant because it furthers these perfections. Meier’s discussion of the logical perfections of science has not received much attention. However, Brigitte Falkenburg has analysed Kant’s logical perfections of scientific knowledge, which build on Meier (2000: 355–66). Falkenburg links these perfections of proper science to the ideal of systematicity by arguing that the perfections prescribe the construction of sciences that are maximally general and maximally specific (Reference Falkenburg2000: 383; 2001: 311). I extend Falkenburg’s analysis by (a) providing a novel analysis of Meier’s perfections of cognition, and (b) by specifying the relation between almost all of Meier’s perfections and the ideal of systematicity. This will illustrate that we can take the ideal of systematicity to be an ideal for science because it furthers logical perfections.Footnote 3

I have one final aim. Sturm (Reference Sturm2009) argues that Kant articulated a novel conception of systematicity by articulating the idea that a system is constructed by positing an idea of the whole (Sturm Reference Sturm2009: 143; see also Blomme Reference Blomme2015: 109–10; Hinske Reference Hinske and Funke1990: 172–3). I will argue that this idea is anticipated by Lambert’s idea that systematic sciences should be complete. According to Lambert, a systematic science is complete if we can specify all of its parts and specify rules in accordance with which we can treat these parts. I show that Kant’s idea that systematic sciences are constructed on the basis of an idea of the whole expresses the same point.

In section 2 I introduce the Classical Model. In section 3, I discuss Kant’s views on definitions and the difference between the mathematical and philosophical method, and show that, although Kant rejects Wolff’s mathematical method, he adheres to the Classical Model. Section 4 discusses Meier and Kant in relation to the Classical Model and the logical perfections of cognition. I show that Kant’s account of systematicity can be fruitfully interpreted against the background of the Classical Model and Meier’s logical perfections. In section 5, I discuss Lambert’s philosophy, the Classical Model and the relation of Lambert’s philosophy to Kant’s views on systematicity. I argue that Kant’s views that systematic sciences are complete and that systematicity is a regulative ideal can be traced back to Lambert’s views on the completeness of sciences.

2. The Classical Model of Science

The axiomatic idea of science adopted by Meier, Lambert and Kant has been articulated by de Jong and Betti’s Classical Model of Science (2010). According to this model, a proper science is a system S of propositions and concepts (or terms) which satisfies the following conditions:

  1. (1) All propositions and all concepts (or terms) of S concern a specific set of objects or are about a certain domain of being(s).

  2. (2a) There are in S a number of so-called fundamental concepts (or terms).

  3. (2b) All other concepts (or terms) occurring in S are composed of (or are definable from) these fundamental concepts (or terms).

  4. (3a) There are in S a number of so-called fundamental propositions.

  5. (3b) All other propositions of S follow from or are grounded in (or are provable or demonstrable from) these fundamental propositions.

  6. (4) All propositions of S are true.

  7. (5) All propositions of S are universal and necessary in some sense or another.

  8. (6) All propositions of S are known to be true. A non-fundamental proposition is known to be true through its proof in S.

  9. (7) All concepts or terms of S are adequately known. A non-fundamental concept is adequately known through its composition (or definition). (de Jong and Betti Reference Betti2010: 186)

The Classical Model is an interpretative tool that reconstructs how several thinkers have traditionally understood a proper science. De Jong and Betti partly constructed the Classical Model on the basis of an analysis of the theory of science of Aristotle, the Port-Royal Logic of Arnauld and Nicole (1662), and the Wissenschaftslehre (1837) of Bolzano (de Jong and Betti Reference Betti2010: 187). The Classical Model is so named because it can be traced to Aristotle and remained influential for more than two millennia, being largely abandoned only after Frege due to various factors, including the improved rigour of logic after Frege’s and Hilbert’s formalistic turn in mathematics (de Jong and Betti Reference Betti2010: 197). The Classical Model is fruitfully applied to Kant in de Jong (Reference de Jong1995, 1997, 2010) and van den Berg (Reference van den Berg2011, Reference van den Berg2014: ch. 2).Footnote 4 In the following, I use the Classical Model as an interpretative tool to elucidate the concept of systematicity.Footnote 5

Some remarks on some conditions of the Classical Model are in order, because they play a role in my analysis of Meier, Lambert and Kant. Conditions (2) and (3) capture the core of the axiomatic idea of science that I attribute to Meier, Lambert and Kant. These conditions, I argue, also capture the core of Kant’s conception of systematicity. The fundamental propositions of an axiomatic science must be independent of one another. For example, in his Prize Essay of 1764 (as a referee has pointed out to me), Kant states as a second rule for the proper method of metaphysics that the fundamental (indemonstrable) judgements of metaphysics should not ‘be contained in another’ (NTM, 2: 285). Conditions (4)–(6) are typical of the Classical Model.Footnote 6 These conditions are not required by a modern account of an axiomatic system, in which a requirement of (syntactic or semantic) consistency is postulated. However, conditions (4)–(6) were endorsed by early modern followers of the Classical Model.

Condition (4) states that a proper science must have true propositions. For De Jong and Betti the postulate does not presuppose any particular conception of truth, but it excludes rhetorical talk of truth, such as ‘some conventionalist approaches in which truth has no role in the choice between rival theories’ (de Jong and Betti Reference Betti2010: 191). Condition (5) states that the propositions of a proper science must be universal, which often means that these propositions are maximally general and necessary in some sense. The necessity ascribed to propositions of a science may be weaker than what we understand by necessity today (ibid. 192). For example, Wolff argues that the non-fundamental propositions of empirical sciences follow deductively, a priori, or necessarily from certain fundamental propositions, and are in this sense necessary, while denying that these empirical propositions are true in all possible worlds (Wolff [1751] 2003: vol. 2, 352-4). Finally, condition (6) makes clear that the Classical Model involves a theory of justification of scientific knowledge, which, as de Jong and Betti note (Reference Betti2010: 192), often involves a form of foundationalism. According to Kant, for example, knowledge in the strict sense involves apodictic certainty, which means that we are justified in asserting the necessary truth of a judgement (MFNS, 4: 468). This condition is also satisfied in the case of empirical judgements, if judgements are (partly) proven on the basis of a priori principles (van den Berg Reference van den Berg2014: 35–7; Reference van den Berg2011: 16–18). For example, according to Kant we have knowledge of the law of gravity, which is an empirical law, based on empirical phenomena, proven partly on the basis of mathematical and metaphysical (a priori) principles (Friedman Reference Friedman and Guyer1992).

3. Kant on Real Definitions and the Mathematical Method

According to condition (2) of the Classical Model, non-fundamental concepts are defined in terms of fundamental concepts. In this section, I consider Kant’s views on definitions. Section 3.1 gives an account of Kant’s views on definitions, the distinction between nominal and real definitions, and his views on possibility and objective reality. In section 3.2, I discuss Kant’s views on the distinction between the mathematical and the philosophical method and its implications for his views on definitions. I argue that Kant’s acceptance of the Classical Model is compatible with his critique of Wolff’s mathematical method

3.1 Kant on Nominal and Real Definitions

According to the Logic lectures, a definition is a distinct, complete and precise concept (Log-W, 24: 912–14; Vanzo Reference Vanzo2010: 151; KrV, A727/B755). A concept is distinct if we clearly cognize its marks, i.e. the partial concepts contained in it (Log-W, 24: 847; Vanzo Reference Vanzo2010: 153). A concept is complete or exhaustive if we have cognition of all the marks or partial concepts contained in it (Log-W, 24: 847, 912; Vanzo Reference Vanzo2010: 154). A concept is precise if it is not superfluous, i.e. no mark is contained in another (Log-W, 24: 912–13; Vanzo Reference Vanzo2010: 154). Finally, definitions are original expositions of concepts (A727/B755). As Vanzo explains Kant, if <<human being>> is used to define <<philosopher>>, and <<rational>> is a mark of <<human being>>, an original exposition of <<philosopher>> will mention <<human being>> but not <<rational>>, the latter being a derived (not original) mark from <<human being>> (Vanzo Reference Vanzo2010: 154).

For Kant, definitions are either nominal or real. Nominal definitions are definitions of names or words (Vanzo Reference Vanzo2010: 156). They signify the logical essence of concepts, i.e. the partial concepts analytically contained in a concept (JL, 9: 143). In contrast, real definitions explicate the (real) essence of objects, explicating the (real) inner ground of that which belongs to the possibility of a thing (Vanzo Reference Vanzo2010: 153, 159; Log-W, 24: 919). Real definitions also enumerate all the essential features of an object, the complete essence of a thing, and thus allow us to strictly distinguish objects falling under the definiendum from other objects, something nominal definitions cannot do (Log-W, 24: 919; Vanzo Reference Vanzo2010: 160–1).

As Nunez has shown (Reference Nunez2014: 635), Kant thinks that real definitions consist of two parts: (i) a nominal definition (a definition in terms of genus and differentia, explicating the logical essence of a concept), and (ii) a proof of the possibility of the concept defined. In the Critique, for example, Kant notes that real definitions make concepts (a) distinct, i.e. we know a collection of marks contained in the defined concept (these marks are given by the nominal definition), and (b) contain a mark that secures the objective reality of the defined concept, i.e. the application of the concept to objects of experience (KrV, A241–2, n.).

As we have seen, real definitions prove the (real) possibility of concepts. To conclude this section, we must therefore analyse Kant’s views on possibility. In the pre-critical Prize Essay of 1764, Kant argued that definitions should not constitute the beginning of metaphysical treatises but rather the end point of inquiry. Metaphysics, according to Kant, is based on certain indemonstrable judgements, which provide data about what is immediately certain about one’s object of inquiry, from which further conclusions are then inferred (NTM, 2: 285). These indemonstrable propositions also provide the data from which definitions in the philosophical sciences can ultimately be drawn (281–2). Hence, the indemonstrable propositions provide the data from which the (real) possibility of concepts can be established (ibid.). In metaphysics, Kant argues, we follow the method of Newton, who derived rules governing motion analytically from experience and geometry. Likewise, in metaphysics we proceed from certain inner experiences which provide us with indemonstrable judgements on the basis of which a science of metaphysics can be erected (286).

While Kant relied on Newtonian verification criteria to establish the real possibility of concepts in his Prize Essay, he introduces a novel concept of (real) possibility in the first Critique. There Kant argues that logical possibility (consistency) is not sufficient to establish the real possibility of a concept (KrV, A220/B268). Rather, empirical concepts are really possible, i.e. applicable to objects of experience, because they are borrowed from our experience of objects, whereas a priori concepts are really possible because they express a condition ‘on which experience in general (its form) rests’ (ibid.). For example, the real possibility of the a priori concept of a triangle is not cognized from concepts, but from the fact that ‘this very same formative synthesis by means of which we construct a figure in imagination is entirely identical with that which we exercise in the apprehension of an appearance in order to make a concept of experience of it’ (A224/B271). It is the fact that the a priori concept of a triangle expresses a condition of experience that secures the objective reality of the concept of a triangle: it shows that this concept is applicable to objects of experience and is thus really possible. Insofar as real definitions secure the real possibility of concepts, they show that the concepts are objectively real or applicable to objects of experience.

3.2 Kant on Mathematical and Philosophical Method

I will argue that Kant adhered to the Classical Model and that this explains his views on systematicity. But first I will explain how his acceptance of the Classical Model is compatible with his critique of Wolff’s mathematical method in the first Critique. For it may be thought that Kant’s critique of the mathematical method implies a rejection of an axiomatic idea of science. Kant’s critique of Wolff’s mathematical method is often taken to imply that in philosophy, in contrast to mathematics, it is difficult or impossible to obtain real definitions (Vanzo Reference Vanzo2010: 160, n. 61; Beck Reference Beck1956: 183). If this is the case, how can Kant accept condition (2) of the Classical Model, which holds that non-fundamental concepts in proper sciences are defined in terms of fundamental concepts? In this section, I argue that Kant’s rejection of Wolff’s mathematical method, which should not be identified with the Classical Model, is consistent with adopting the Classical Model, which captures a conception of science shared by both Wolff and Kant (see for similarities between Wolff and Kant on method Gava Reference Gava2018; on Kant’s critique of the mathematical method, see de Jong Reference de Jong1995). With respect to definitions I argue, following Nunez (Reference Nunez2014), that Kant leaves room for the possibility of giving real definitions of philosophical concepts.

In the Doctrine of Method of the first Critique, Kant criticizes Wolff’s mathematical method by arguing that philosophy should not imitate mathematics by beginning with definitions (B758–9). According to Kant, as we have seen, a characteristic of a definition is that it provides a complete or exhaustive description of all the marks of a defined concept (A727/B755). Since the marks that we think in empirical concepts change in the course of empirical investigation, we cannot, if we adopt an analytic method, be certain that we have a complete specification of all the marks of an empirical concept, i.e. a definition. Similarly, if we adopt an analytic method we cannot be certain that we have a complete specification of all the marks of a priori given concepts in philosophy, and hence cannot be certain that we have attained a definition (A727–9/B755–7). Hence, in the philosophical sciences, if we adopt the analytic method, we often only have what Kant calls expositions, i.e. a possibly incomplete set of marks contained in a concept (A729/B757; JL, 9: 143). Note that such expositions follow the model of concepts as specified by the Classical Model: we describe non-fundamental concepts (species) in terms of more fundamental concepts or marks (genera), even though we cannot be certain that our list of marks is complete. In this sense, Kant’s ideas are consistent with the Classical Model. Kant’s point is that in the philosophical sciences we often cannot be sure whether we have obtained a definition. Nevertheless, definitions are an ideal of science. The Jäsche Logik states that definitions are logical perfections ‘that we must seek to attain’ (9: 143). Hence, Kant sees the model of definitions as represented in the Classical Model as an ideal for science, and accepts the model, even if this ideal is difficult to attain. As Kant puts it: attaining definitions in philosophy ‘is fine, but often very difficult’ (KrV, A731/B759 n.).

If definitions are an ideal for science, it should be possible to obtain them. It has been argued that Kant does not think real definitions can be obtained in philosophy (see e.g. Beck Reference Beck1956: 183). However, Tyke Nunez has argued that Kant does think that philosophical concepts allow of real definitions (Nunez Reference Nunez2014; see also de Jong Reference de Jong1995: 265–6). He interprets Kant’s negative remarks concerning the possibility of real definitions in philosophy as referring to philosophy as it was practised before Kant’s Copernican turn (Nunez Reference Nunez2014: 637). According to Nunez, Kant thinks that, although the traditional method of analysis cannot yield definitions of philosophical concepts, Kant adopts a synthetic method in the first Critique, exemplified by the derivation of the categories, that allows for definitions of philosophical concepts (638–44). Remember that Kant took real definitions to consist of (i) a nominal definition and (ii) a mark through which we can secure the objective reality of the defined concept (KrV, A241–2 n.). Nunez argues that Kant provides such definitions of the categories in the Critique. In the chapter on phenomena and noumena, Kant notes that we cannot define the categories without specifying conditions of sensibility that show the objective reality of the categories (A240–1/B300). As Nunez argues (644–8), Kant goes on to give real definitions of some categories (a) by supplying a nominal definition of the category in terms of genus and specific difference, and (b) by specifying the sensible condition or schema that secures the objective reality of the category. For example, Kant nominally defines the category of magnitude as ‘the determination of a thing through which it can be thought how many units are posited in it’ (A242/B300). The schema that secures the objective reality of this category is described as follows: ‘Only this how-many-times is grounded on successive repetition, thus on time and the synthesis (of the homogeneous) in it’ (ibid.). Nunez’s interpretation supports our reading of the model of definitions described in the Classical Model as an ideal for science.

Kant’s other critical remarks on the mathematical method are also consistent with the Classical Model. In his critique of Wolff’s mathematical method, he says that mathematics has axioms while philosophy does not (KrV, B760–1). However, Kant uses a specific interpretation of the term axiom. Axioms are immediately certain synthetic principles that are intuitive, i.e. that can be constructed in pure intuition (ibid.) Since philosophical principles do not allow of construction, philosophy lacks axioms. However, philosophy does have fundamental principles, as stated by the Classical Model, which are called discursive principles through concepts or acroamata (JL, 9: 110–11; de Jong Reference de Jong1995: 267). These fundamental principles ground the philosophical sciences.

Finally, Kant says that philosophy does not have demonstrations. However, by demonstration he means a constructive proof, as employed in mathematics, which he contrasts with acroamatic (discursive) proofs (KrV, B762). Although philosophy does not make use of constructive proofs, Kant does say that philosophy makes use of discursive proofs. In addition, in line with the Classical Model, he says that cognition must be logically grounded, which means that judgements must be logically derived from higher principles (van den Berg Reference van den Berg2014: 30–4; JL, 9: 51–2; Falkenburg Reference Falkenburg2000: 368–70). Hence, Kant’s critique of the mathematical method in the Doctrine of Method is consistent with adopting the Classical Model.

4. Meier and Kant on Systematicity, the Classical Model and the Logical Perfections of Knowledge

In this section I discuss Meier and Kant in relation to the Classical Model, their views on systematicity, and their views on the logical perfections of knowledge. I argue that both Meier and Kant accepted the Classical Model and that this model elucidates their ideas of systematicity. In addition, I discuss Meier’s and Kant’s views on logical perfections and their relation to the idea of systematicity. Meier devotes various chapters of his Vernunftlehre to discussing different perfections or ideals of scientific knowledge. I argue that systematicity furthers the perfections of (i) extensiveness, (ii) fruitfulness, (iii) truth, (iv) clarity, distinctness and completeness, and (v) certainty. This suggests that Meier embraced systematicity as an ideal partly because it furthers these perfections. As I shall argue Kant embraced systematicity as an ideal for science for the same reasons.

4.1 Meier and the Classical Model

That Meier endorses the Classical Model becomes clear from his Vernunftlehre (1752). There he notes that concepts are obtained through: experience, abstraction and combination (Meier Reference Meier1752: 416). His account of abstraction states that we obtain more from less fundamental concepts analytically through abstraction until we arrive at fundamental concepts (430–1). We obtain concepts through combination by proceeding synthetically from more simple and more fundamental concepts to more complex and less fundamental concepts (439). Hence, Meier’s account of concepts captures conditions (2a) and (2b) of the Classical Model.

According to Meier, constructing a system of concepts occurs through definitions and logical division. We define lower concepts (species) in terms of their proximate genus and specific difference (Meier Reference Meier1752: 451). Hence, through definitions we systematically relate lower to higher concepts. Constructing a system of concepts also requires that we logically divide higher concepts (genera) into lower concepts (species). This division is guided by the rule that the species must constitute all the concepts contained under the higher concept, i.e. the species must constitute the total extension of the divided concept (437–74; see also Kant at JL, 9: 146–7, discussed in section 4.8).

Meier also distinguishes between indemonstrable judgements, which do not require any demonstration, and demonstrable judgements, which require a demonstration (Meier Reference Meier1752: 514). The indemonstrable judgements are the fundamental judgements on the basis of which we demonstrate non-fundamental judgements in science. Hence, Meier accepted conditions (3a) and (3b) of the Classical Model.

The Classical Model illuminates how, according to Meier, systems of concepts and judgements are constructed. Systems of concepts are constructed by defining non-fundamental concepts on the basis of fundamental concepts, and systems of judgements are constructed by deducing non-fundamental judgements from fundamental judgements. In the next section, we will further explore the connection between axiomatics and systematicity in Meier.

4.2 Wolff and Meier on Mathematical Method: How to Construct Systematic Sciences

In the chapter on method, Meier discusses how we can construct systematic sciences. He stresses the importance of the mathematical method, which Wolff equated with the scientific method (Meier Reference Meier1752: 634). The mathematical method is a variety of the Classical Model, though not identical with it. It states that non-fundamental scientific concepts must be defined in terms of fundamental concepts, and that non-fundamental scientific propositions must be deduced from fundamental propositions (van den Berg and Demarest Reference van den Berg and Demarest2020: 383).

The nature of the mathematical method was explained by Wolff in Die Anfangsgründe aller Mathematischen Wissenschaften (1750 [1999]).Footnote 7 Wolff claims that the mathematical method proceeds from definitions to axioms, and from axioms to theorems and problems (5). Definitions, which are either nominal or real, ground axioms. For example, if we define a circle by giving the procedure of moving a straight line around a fixed point, we can infer that all the straight lines that are drawn from the centre to the perimeter are equal to each other (16). This truth is an axiom (Grundsatz). Axioms either show that something is the case, as in the example of equal radii, or that something can be done or constructed, for example that between any two points we can draw a straight line (17). The first type is called axiomata and the second postulata. Since the truth of axiomata and postulata immediately follows from definitions, they do not require proof (ibid.). We derive theorems through strict demonstrations from definitions, axiomata and postulata (21, 25, 27–8; Wolff 1716 [1965]: 501).

Wolff’s mathematical method presents us with an axiomatic method that derives theorems from definitions and axioms through logical proofs. Wolff and Meier take this axiomatic method to be the paradigmatic way of constructing systematic sciences (Hinske Reference Hinske and Funke1990: 159). Having described how Meier’s adherence to an axiomatic ideal for science explains his idea of systematicity, we may now turn to Meier’s discussion of the logical perfections of scientific knowledge. I will show that systematicity can be taken as an ideal for science because it furthers these perfections of knowledge.

4.3 Systematicity and Extensiveness in Meier

According to the perfection of extensiveness, cognition must be applicable to as many objects as possible (Meier Reference Meier1752: 41). The term cognition (Erkenntniß) refers to both concepts and judgements. Hence, the concepts and judgements of a science must be applicable to as many objects as possible.

Systematicity furthers the ideal of extensiveness. According to Meier, systems of concepts are constructed by means of definitions and the logical division of concepts (see section 4.1). The logical division of higher concepts into lower concepts must, as we have seen, satisfy the following rule: (i) the species must constitute the total extension of the divided concept. Condition (i) ensures that a division is complete and that the constructed system of concepts has the widest possible extension. Constructing a system of concepts in accordance with condition (i) thus furthers extensiveness.

4.4 Systematicity and Fruitfulness in Meier

The perfection of fruitfulness concerns the number of consequences that follow from a cognition: if a cognition has many consequences, Meier calls it fruitful (Meier Reference Meier1752: 101). Fruitfulness is a maxim of maximality. It tells us that scientific principles should allow for the derivation of the maximum number of consequences. It is related to the maxim of parsimony, which tells us that sciences should be based on a minimal set of principles. These two maxims combined give rise to the following maxim: in science, we should choose the smallest set of principles (parsimony) that allow us to derive the maximum number of consequences (fruitfulness). This maxim expresses an axiomatic ideal (de Jong and Betti Reference Betti2010), which directs us to derive as many consequences as possible from a minimal number of principles. Insofar as systematic sciences can be viewed as axiomatic sciences, systematic sciences can be taken to further the perfection of fruitfulness.Footnote 8

4.5 Systematicity and Truth in Meier

Meier’s account of truth corresponds to condition (4) of the Classical Model. Meier specifies two criteria for truth (Meier Reference Meier1752: 130). The first mark of truth is internal possibility: a true judgement must not be contradictory (131–2). The second mark of truth can be called grounding: a judgement is true if (i) it is a consequence of true grounds and (ii) it is a ground of consequences all of which are true (133). Condition (i) is plausible because we take something to be true on the basis of proofs, which show that something follows from true grounds. Condition (ii) is plausible because of scientific practice, in which we prove the truth of hypotheses by showing that all their consequences are true (134–5).

That systematicity is necessary for knowledge of truths follows from the marks of truth. We can say that a judgement is true if (i) it follows from true grounds and (ii) all its consequences are true. Hence, knowledge of true judgements requires that we systematically order judgements as a deductive interconnection of grounds and consequences.

4.6 Systematicity, Clarity, Distinctness and Completeness in Meier

Other perfections of cognition are the clarity, distinctness and completeness of cognition. These notions can be traced to Wolff, and before Wolff to the views of Descartes and Leibniz. According to Wolff a concept is clear if we can identify the things to which it applies (Wolff 1754 [1978]: 126; van den Berg Reference van den Berg2014: 19). A concept is distinct if we know its marks, i.e. the partial concepts contained within the concept (128; van den Berg Reference van den Berg2014: 19). Finally, a concept is complete if we know all its marks and if the marks we know are sufficient for knowing the things represented by the concept and distinguishing them from other things (129; van den Berg Reference van den Berg2014: 19). Meier adopts similar concepts of clarity, distinctness and completeness (Meier Reference Meier1752: 184, 214, 235).

Distinctness and completeness are perfections of cognition that are improved through establishing systems of cognition. If we construct systems of genera and species, we make the species distinct by explicating the genera that are contained in these species. In turn, we further the completeness of an analysed concept by explicating as many of the marks or more fundamental concepts that are contained in a concept. By constructing systems of concepts we thus improve the distinctness and completeness of cognition.

4.7 Systematicity and Certainty in Meier

Meier’s account of the perfection of certainty corresponds to condition (6) of the Classical Model. Certainty is that which secures that we know a true judgement (Meier Reference Meier1752: 251). In science, according to Meier, we aspire to logical certainty, which is knowledge of a truth through knowledge of its grounds. He distinguishes between exhaustive and inexhaustive certainty (255–6). If we know all of the grounds of a true judgement, as in mathematical demonstrations, we have obtained exhaustive certainty. Establishing a systematic and deductive interconnection of grounds and consequences is necessary for obtaining logical and exhaustive certainty.

4.8 Kant on Systematicity as a Logical Perfection

Having described Meier’s views on systematicity, the Classical Model and the logical perfections, we may now turn to Kant. Kant describes systematicity as a logical perfection (JL, 9: 139–40).Footnote 9 The ideal of systematicity is related to the procedure of constructing systems of concepts. Kant states that a system of concepts depends on the ‘distinctness of concepts both in regard to what is contained in them and in respect of what is contained under them’ (ibid.). As was the case for Meier (section 4.1), this means that a system of concepts is constructed by specifying both the intension of concepts through definitions and the extension of concepts through logical division (Longuenesse Reference Longuenesse and Wolfe1998: 150–1; JL, 9: 140). In the following, I describe how definitions and logical division give rise to a system of concepts.

Kant distinguishes between synthetic and analytic definitions and between nominal and real definitions (JL, 9: 141–4). Synthetic nominal definitions are made through the arbitrary combination of concepts. We can, for example, give a nominal synthetic definition of the concept ‘square’ by combining the concepts ‘four-sided’, ‘equilateral’ and ‘rectangle’ (Log-D, 24: 757). In this way, we define less fundamental concepts (species) in terms of more fundamental concepts (genera and differentia), proceeding synthetically from the simpler, more fundamental to the complex, less fundamental concepts.

Synthetic real definitions are, as we have seen (section 3.1), based on synthetic nominal definitions. They consist of (i) a nominal definition and (ii) a proof of the real possibility of the defined concept. In mathematics, we prove the possibility of the defined concept through a constructive procedure that shows how an object is possible (JL, 9: 141). For example, we can define a circle by showing that it can be constructed by letting a straight line move around a fixed point. This construction is based on a synthetic nominal definition proceeding from genus and differentia to species, e.g. the nominal definition of a circle as a (curved) line (genus) whose points are all equidistant from a centre point (differentia) (see Nunez Reference Nunez2014: 633). The same is true for definitions of the categories. They consist of (a) a nominal definition of the category in terms of genus and specific difference, and (b) a specification of the schema that secures the objective reality of the category (Nunez Reference Nunez2014: 644–8).

To conclude: all synthetic real definitions are based on synthetic nominal definitions. This means that when giving synthetic real definitions we define complex, less fundamental concepts in terms of simpler and more fundamental ones and we proceed synthetically from simple, fundamental to complex, less fundamental concepts. Kant’s views on synthetic definitions thus capture conditions (2a) and (2b) of the Classical Model. Through defining concepts in terms of more fundamental ones, we construct a system of concepts.

Analytic definitions are constructed by analysing given concepts and making these concepts distinct and complete (JL, 9: 142). Using this method we proceed analytically from the more complex, less fundamental to more simple and fundamental concepts, and define less fundamental in terms of more fundamental concepts by means of genus and specific difference. Kant’s views on analytic definitions thus likewise capture conditions (2a) and (2b) of the Classical Model. As we have seen, however, Kant is sceptical about obtaining analytic definitions of empirical and a priori philosophical concepts.

Definitions bring about a system of concepts by specifying their intension. According to Kant, as was the case for Meier (section 4.1), the construction of a system of concepts also requires the determination of the extension of concepts through logical division (JL, 9: 146–7). Through logical division we obtain lower concepts (species) from higher concepts (genera). In the Jäsche Logik, Kant notes that the logical division of concepts must satisfy the following rules: the species (a) exclude each other; (b) belong under one higher concept; and, again like Meier, (c) constitute the total extension of the concept that is divided (van den Berg Reference van den Berg2014: 22; Anderson Reference Anderson2005: 29; JL, 9: 146–7). By following these rules, we systematically determine the extension of a concept.

Kant’s views on the systematicity of judgements are articulated in the doctrine of proof of the Jäsche Logik. A proof consists of three parts: (i) conclusion, (ii) ground of proof, (iii) the way in which (i) follows from (ii) (Log-D, 24: 748; Zinkstok Reference Zinkstok2013: 96–7). Through proofs we systematically relate grounds to their consequences. Proofs must terminate in fundamental principles (JL, 9: 71). Hence, Kant’s doctrine of proof captures conditions (3a) and (3b) of the Classical Model. Through providing proofs from fundamental principles we construct systems of judgements. In the next section, we discuss the similarities between Meier’s and Kant’s accounts of the logical perfections of knowledge.

4.9 Kant on Systematicity and the Perfections of Fruitfulness, Extensiveness and Truth

Kant discusses Meier’s account of the perfections in his logic lectures and accepts most of them (Falkenburg Reference Falkenburg2000: 355–66). However, in his lectures he does not explicitly relate these perfections to systematicity. Kant does relate the idea of systematicity to the perfections in the first Critique, where, as Falkenburg notes (Reference Falkenburg, Fulda and Stolzenberg2001: 312), Kant states that the goal of the systematic unity of knowledge amounts to the goal of satisfying logical perfections of knowledge (A838/B866). If we consider Kant’s remarks on systematicity in the first Critique, we find connections between the ideal of systematicity and the ideals of fruitfulness and, by implication, extensiveness and truth. Kant argues that through the systematic ordering of cognition, we achieve unity alongside the greatest possible extension (A644/B673). How a system furthers unity alongside maximal extension becomes clear if we discuss Kant’s remarks on systematicity in relation to the perfection of fruitfulness.

In our discussion of fruitfulness, we have introduced the following maxim: science should be based on the smallest set of principles (parsimony) that allow us to derive the maximum number of consequences (fruitfulness). Kant articulates this maxim in the section ‘On the regulative use of the ideas of pure reason’, where he discusses the maxims of genera and specification (see Guyer Reference Guyer1990: 21–34; 2003: 282; Falkenburg Reference Falkenburg2000: 382–5 discusses these maxims and also the logical perfections in this context). There he notes that systematic sciences are brought about by following what he calls the maxim of genera, according to which we subsume species under genera, then subsume these under higher genera, and so forth until we reach a highest genus (KrV, A651–2/B679–80). Applied to systems of judgements, this maxim expresses the idea that sciences should be based on a minimum number of principles. However, Kant notes that in science we should also follow the maxim of species, which directs us to maximally specify each species into subspecies, these subspecies into further subspecies, and so forth (A654–5/B682–3). Applied to systems of judgements, this maxim tells us that in science we need to choose principles that allow for the derivation of the most consequences. It is by following these two maxims that we establish systematic sciences (A658/B686). Hence, systematic sciences follow the maxim that we should choose the smallest set of principles (parsimony) that allow us to derive the maximum number of consequences (fruitfulness). This analysis also suggests that Kant adopted the perfection of extensiveness, and that he took systematicity to further the ideal of extensiveness, because his maxim of species directs us to continuously divide species into subspecies, thus ensuring that our cognition is applicable to as many objects as possible.

There are also similarities between Meier’s and Kant’s remarks on truth. Kant argues that systematicity is necessary for cognizing truths. Without systematic unity we have ‘no sufficient mark of empirical truth’ (KrV, A651/B679). Remarks such as these have led to much debate. Allison (Reference Allison and Sedgwick2000 82: 84–6) argues, following Ginsborg (Reference Ginsborg1990: 171–92), that systematicity is necessary for the formation of determinate empirical concepts, and thus a necessary condition for knowledge of empirical truths. This may be true, but we can explain Kant’s ideas in a simpler fashion if we take into account the position of Meier.

According to Meier, as we have seen, we know that a cognition is true if it is (i) a consequence of true grounds and (ii) a ground of consequences all of which are true. Hence, a systematic interconnection of grounds and consequences is necessary to cognize truths. In the Jäsche Logik, Kant puts forward a similar theory, arguing that a true cognition (x) has (true) grounds from which it follows and (y) does not have false consequences (JL, 9: 51). With respect to (y), Kant notes that ‘from the truth of the consequence we may infer the truth of the cognition as ground, but only negatively: if one false consequence flows from a cognition, then the cognition itself is false’ (JL, 9: 52). Hence, in line with Meier’s condition (ii), we may infer from the truth of all consequences to the truth of the ground, although Kant notes that one cannot know the totality of consequences of a ground and that we can therefore only use this criterion to establish hypothetical or probable truths (ibid.). In the first Critique, Kant relates Meier’s condition (ii) to what he calls the hypothetical use of reason. If we employ the hypothetical use of reason, we assume a universal problematically, and test whether several particular consequences follow from it. If these consequences follow from the rule, then the universality of the rule is inferred, although, again, we can only approximate universality through this mode of inference (A 646–7/B674–5).

The hypothetical use of reason thus tests whether the consequences that follow from a rule are true and infers to the universality of the rule itself. As such, the hypothetical use of reason illustrates Meier’s condition (ii). Since we know truths on the basis of a systematic interconnection of grounds and consequences, it is no surprise that Kant claims that systematicity is necessary for knowing (empirical) truths. The basic idea adopted by Meier and Kant is that we can only know truths (whether apodictic or probable) through inferential relations, and this presupposes that cognitions are systematically ordered.

We have seen that, for both Meier and Kant, the ideal of systematicity and the logical perfections of knowledge are intimately related. A properly systematic science satisfies the logical perfections of knowledge, which all sciences should satisfy to the highest extent. Hence, it is no surprise that Meier and Kant took systematicity to be an ideal for science.

5. Lambert and Kant on Systematicity and Completeness

In this section I turn to Lambert’s account of systematicity and its impact on Kant. In section 5.1 I will first, following Sturm (Reference Sturm2009), discuss passages in Lambert’s Neues Organon that illustrate his notion of systematicity. I will then argue that Lambert took systematic sciences to be complete and analyse what this means. Finally, I argue that Lambert rejected Wolff’s mathematical method but nevertheless accepted the Classical Model, which elucidates Lambert’s conception of systematicity. In section 5.2, I will argue that Kant’s idea that systematic sciences are constructed on the basis of an idea of a whole and are complete can be fruitfully understood on the basis of Lambert’s ideas of completeness.

5.1 Lambert on Scientific Knowledge, Completeness and the New Mathematical Method

In his Neues Organon (1764), Lambert distinguishes between common knowledge and scientific knowledge (see also Watkins Reference Watkins, Dyck and Wunderlich2018: 181–4). Scientific knowledge is characterized by dependency relations, whereas common knowledge is not (Lambert Reference Lambert1764: 389). Lambert construes sciences as deductive systems in which consequences are deduced from fundamental principles (394–5). Hence, he construes sciences as axiomatic deductive systems (Wolters Reference Wolters1980: 51, 55). Lambert states that scientific judgements are regarded as a systematic whole, in which every judgement is related to others (390). Hence, an axiomatic science, in which non-fundamental judgements are demonstrated on the basis of fundamental ones, satisfies Lambert’s criteria for a system of judgements.

According to Lambert, systematicity is the defining characteristic of scientific knowledge (Sturm Reference Sturm2009: 141). Lambert also argues that completeness is a characteristic of systematic sciences. Sturm (142) notes that completeness for Lambert involves having a principle that guides research. In the following, I will extend Sturm’s analysis and explain the notion of completeness.

In his Architectonic, Lambert states that completeness is a perfection of the foundational sciences (Lambert Reference Lambert1771: 29). In his Neues Organon, he notes that a scientific doctrine is complete if we can specify how all of its parts are to be treated (1764: 75). As an example of a complete science, Lambert mentions trigonometry (Reference Lambert1764: 406; cf. 1771: 13). The example of trigonometry illustrates Lambert’s notion of completeness. In his Mathematisches Lexicon (1716), Wolff defined trigonometry as a science that allows one to derive from three given parts of a triangle the other three parts. Wolff thinks that all problems in trigonometry reduce to a limited number of cases: (i) if two sides are given and one angle, to find the other two angles and the third side, (ii) if two angles are given and one side, to find the other two sides and the remaining angle, (iii) if three sides are given, to find the three angles, and (iv) in spherical triangles, if three angles are given, to find the three sides (Wolff 1716 [1965], 1428–9).

The cases above describe all the (types of) problems of trigonometry and the way in which they are to be treated. It is this feature that Lambert associates with completeness: it is the enumeration (Abzahlung) of all cases (Fälle) and the specification of the rules (Regeln) in accordance with which these cases are to be treated (traktirt) that makes a doctrine complete (1764: 75). This matches Lambert’s general idea of a system as a whole with parts that are related to each other (Waibel Reference Waibel, Stolzenberg and Rudolph2007: 53). Interestingly, Lambert also remarks that, since the realm of truths is infinite, completeness is often an ideal that we can only approximate (Reference Lambert1771: 30–1). In the next section, we will see that Kant argues, like Lambert, that the completeness of a systematic science consists in being able to say how all of its parts are to be ordered. In addition, like Lambert, he argues that the completeness of a science is an ideal that we can only approximate.

If we turn our attention to Lambert’s Anlage zur Architectonic (1771), it becomes clear that he rejected Wolff’s mathematical method. According to Lambert, as Heis and several other interpreters have shown (Heis Reference Heis2014: 616–17; Dunlop Reference Dunlop2009: esp. 48–54; Laywine Reference Laywine, Domski and Dickson2010: 114–21; Wolters Reference Wolters1980: 51–4), not every concept can be defined, since some concepts are simple. Because simple concepts cannot be defined, propositions that contain only simple concepts cannot be inferred from definitions. Hence, pace Wolff, postulates and axioms, which contain simple concepts, cannot be inferred from definitions. Rather, the possibility of every concept that is defined needs to be proven on the basis of postulates or axioms, which show how a certain concept is possible or consistent (Heis Reference Heis2014: 616–17; on Lambert’s postulates, see Laywine Reference Laywine, Domski and Dickson2010: 114–21; Dunlop Reference Dunlop2009: 52–62; Wolters Reference Wolters1980: 88–95; Wellmann Reference Wellmann2017: 142–6). In short, definitions do not ground axioms and postulates, but the converse is true: axioms and postulates ground the possibility of definitions (Lambert Reference Lambert1771: 10–12). This new mathematical method distinguishes Lambert’s conception of axiomatics from that of Wolff.

Although Lambert adopted a new mathematical method, he accepted the axiomatic conception of science articulated by the Classical Model. In the Anlage zur Architectonic, Lambert specifies the simple concepts that ground the so-called foundational sciences (1771: 46; Wellman Reference Wellmann2017: 141–2). For example, Lambert argues that the concept of identity, together with the concepts of force and solidity, form the basis for the foundational science called calculus quantitatum (47). Similarly, the fundamental concept of extension, together with the concept of unity, constitutes the basis of geometry (51). In this way, Lambert considers relations between simple concepts and specifies which combinations of concepts form the basis of which science. Lambert’s simple concepts ground non-fundamental concepts insofar as non-fundamental concepts are composed of simple ones (Reference Lambert1764: 420–2). As Lambert puts the point, if we analyse composite concepts (zusammengesetzte Begriffe) we arrive at simple concepts (einfache Begriffe), which provide the foundation of all knowledge (ibid.). Hence, Lambert accepts conditions (2a) and (2b) of the Classical Model. Moreover, through combining simple concepts Lambert obtains fundamental propositions of sciences, since axioms and postulates consist of combinations of simple concepts (1771: 20). From these fundamental propositions, we derive non-fundamental ones, as stipulated by conditions (3a) and (3b) of the Classical Model. Hence, Lambert adopts the Classical Model and this model elucidates his conception of systematic science.

5.2 Kant on the Completeness of Systematic Sciences

Kant follows Lambert by arguing that systematic sciences are complete and that completeness is an ideal for science. In the first Critique he notes that a system is based on an idea of the whole that precedes and determines each part (and hence is complete):

I understand by a system, however, the unity of the manifold cognitions under one idea. This is the rational concept of the form of a whole, insofar as through this the domain (Umfang) of the manifold as well as the position of the parts with respect to each other is determined a priori. (A832/B861; cf. A645/B673)

The nature of this idea of the whole is obscure. Zinkstok (Reference Zinkstok2013: 95) argues that Kant took this idea to be an idea of the highest genus of a Porphyrian tree. This is partly correct. Kant often construes the highest genus of a system of concepts as a transcendental idea that functions as a focus imaginarius when unifying our cognition. These ideas specify a certain domain of investigation, and thus allow us to distinguish a particular science from another science in terms of their different domains. For this reason, Kant claims that through transcendental ideas the domain (Umfang) of a science is determined (Rauscher Reference Rauscher and Guyer2010: 296).

However (as an anonymous referee has stressed), it is not clear how a transcendental idea confers unity among the parts of a science. In our discussion of Lambert, we have seen that he took complete sciences to be sciences in which all the parts are specified and we have rules in accordance with which to treat these parts. Kant adopts a similar idea, insofar as he argues that a systematic and complete science is a science based on an idea of the whole, which means that we have a priori rules that allow us to relate all the parts of a science. It is for this reason that Kant claims that through the idea of the whole ‘the position of the parts with respect to each other is determined a priori’ (KrV, A 832/B 861).

An example from natural history illustrates the idea of a whole. (Here I follow van den Berg Reference van den Berg2014: 23–4, which draws on Müller-Wille Reference Müller-Wille2007: 546–7; Anderson Reference Anderson2005; Oittinen Reference Oittinen and Onnasch2009: 63–9. On the impact of Kant’s natural history and theory of race on his account of systematicity, see Sandford Reference Sandford2018.) In Linnaeus’ classification of plants, he divides the plant realm into classes by specifying the number of stamens, and into orders by specifying the number of pistils. We provide definitions of classes by specifying the genus ‘plant’ and by specifying the number of stamens (‘with one stamen’, ‘with two stamens’, etc.). We further specify the classes and provide definitions of orders by specifying a particular class as genus and by specifying the number of pistils (‘with one pistil’, ‘with two pistils’, etc.). We thus have a priori rules that govern the construction of a system of concepts and that determine the relation between these concepts. This is Kant’s point when he says that a system is based on an idea of the whole that determines the place of each part: we must, as was stressed by Lambert, have rules that specify how we are to treat and relate the parts of a science. For Kant, moreover, a complete empirical specification of genera and species in natural history (a ‘finished natural history’) is a regulative ideal. Hence, like Lambert, Kant saw completeness in this sense as an ideal for science that we can only approximate.

6. Conclusion

Kant’s idea of systematicity is anticipated by Meier and Lambert. This is not surprising given that these authors construed the notion of systematicity on the basis of a widely accepted axiomatic idea of science. More specifically, Kant’s conception of systematicity can be understood against the background of de Jong and Betti’s Classical Model of Science (2010), which was accepted by Kant and by his predecessors Meier and Lambert. I have shown that Kant’s adherence to the Classical Model is compatible with his critique of the mathematical method, and that conditions (2) and (3) of the Classical Model capture Meier’s and Kant’s account of systematicity. I have further argued that systematicity furthers several traditionally accepted logical ideals of scientific cognition, which explains why eighteenth-century authors insisted that sciences should be systematic. Although there is much continuity between Kant and his predecessors, Kant’s ideas that systems are constructed on the basis of transcendental ideas and on the basis of regulative principles were certainly novel. However, the ideal of a system understood as an axiomatized body of knowledge was standard in the eighteenth century. If we do not stress the link between systematicity and axiomatic science, we lose sight of the historical context and nature of Kant’s ideal of systematicity.Footnote 10

Footnotes

1 I use the following abbreviations for works of Kant. JL= Jäsche Logik, KrV = Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Log-D = Logik Dohna-Wundlacken, Log-W = Wiener Logik, MFNS = Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft, NTM = Untersuchung über die Deutlichkeit der Grundsätze der natürlichen Theologie und der Moral. Citations of KrV refer to the A/B pagination. Other citations refer to the Akademie edition of Kant’s works (Kant Reference Kant1900–) through volume and page number(s). English translations are taken from the Cambridge University Press edition of Kant’s works (Kant Reference Kant, Guyer and Wood1992–).

2 The present paper draws in part on my previous van den Berg Reference van den Berg2011 and 2014: ch. 2, where I used the Classical Model to elucidate Kant’s ideas on systems of concepts.

3 On the influence of Meier’s logic on Kant, see Pozzo Reference Pozzo2005.

4 Note that the Classical Model (de Jong and Betti Reference Betti2010) is a refined version of earlier versions of the model. On Bolzano’s views on systematic science, see Betti Reference Betti2010: 288.

5 Plaass (Reference Plaass1994: 235–6) argues that Kant cannot adopt an axiomatic conception of (natural) science because he (Plaass) cannot see how empirical principles have a role in axiomatic sciences (Sturm Reference Sturm2009: 153 follows Plaass). However, as shown in van den Berg Reference van den Berg2014: ch. 2, and van den Berg and Demarest Reference van den Berg and Demarest2020, Wolff and Kant allow for the possibility that (natural) sciences have empirical principles and are axiomatically structured. Walsh (Reference Walsh1940) wrongly argues that propositions of empirical sciences cannot count as knowledge. However, empirical propositions can constitute knowledge (see van den Berg Reference van den Berg2014: ch. 2).

6 I am grateful to an anonymous referee for pressing me to make this point.

7 On Wolff’s mathematical method, see Blok Reference Blok2016: 13–45, Shabel Reference Shabel2003: 49-52, Dunlop Reference Dunlop2013, Gava Reference Gava2018: 279-84. Here, I only discuss the basics of Wolff’s mathematical method.

8 On the perfections of simplicity and fruitfulness, Kant’s take on them and the relation between perfections and theoretical virtues, see also van den Berg Reference van den Berg2020, which draws on the present article.

9 In this section, I follow my van den Berg Reference van den Berg2014: 17–24 and Reference van den Berg2011: 8–11. This account is indebted to Falkenburg (Reference Falkenburg2000).

10 I would like to thank the UvA e-ideas research group, and especially Arianna Betti, for multiple helpful discussions of this article. Thanks also to very constructive comments of three anonymous referees, and to Tim Syme for the language edit. I benefited from feedback on this paper at the conference ‘Kant and the Systematicity of the Sciences’, Frankfurt (8 July 2019) and ‘Mathematics and its Philosophy in the 18th and 19th Century’, Amsterdam (13 July 2018). I have been supported in this work by The Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research under project no. 277-20-007.

References

Allison, H. (2000) ‘Is the Critique of Judgment “Post-Critical”?’ In Sedgwick, S. (ed.), The Reception of Kant’s Critical Philosophy. Fichte, Schelling and Hegel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 7892.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, L. (2005) ‘The Wolffian Paradigm and its Discontents: Kant’s Containment Definition of Analyticity in Historical Context’. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 87, 2274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beck, L. W. (1956) ‘Kant’s Theory of Definition’. Philosophical Review, 65, 179–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Betti, A. (2010) ‘Explanation in Metaphysics and Bolzano’s Theory of Ground and Consequence’. Logique et Analyse, 53, 211, 281316.Google Scholar
Blok, J. (2016) Bolzano’s Early Quest for Apriori Synthetic Principles. Ph.D. dissertation, Groningen: University of Groningen.Google Scholar
Blomme, H. (2015) ‘La notion de “système” chez Wolff, Lambert et Kant’. Estudos Kantianos, 3, 105–26.Google Scholar
Breitenbach, A. (2018) ‘Laws and Ideal Unity’. In Ott, W. and Patton, L. (eds), Laws of Nature (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 109–21.Google Scholar
Buchdahl, G. (1971) ‘The Conception of Lawlikeness in Kant’s Philosophy of Science’. Synthese, 23, 2446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Jong, W. R. (1995) ‘How is Metaphysics as a Science Possible? Kant on the Distinction between Philosophical and Mathematical Method’. Review of Metaphysics, 49, 235–74.Google Scholar
de Jong, W. R. (1997) ‘Kant’s Theory of Geometrical Reasoning and the Analytic–Synthetic Distinction: On Hintikka’s Interpretation of Kant’s Philosophy of Mathematics’. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 28, 141–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Jong, W. R. (2010) ‘The Analytic–Synthetic Distinction and the Classical Model of Science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege’. Synthese, 174, 237–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Jong, W. R., and Betti, A. (2010) ‘The Classical Model of Science: A Millennia-Old Model of Scientific Rationality’. Synthese, 174, 185203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dunlop, K. (2009) ‘Why Euclid’s Geometry Brooked No Doubt: J. H. Lambert on Certainty and the Existence of Models’. Synthese, 167, 3365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dunlop, K. (2013) ‘Mathematical Method and Newtonian Science in the Philosophy of Christian Wolff’. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44, 457–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Falkenburg, B. (2000) Kants Kosmologie: Die wissenschaftliche Revolution der Naturphilosophie im 18. Jahrhundert. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
Falkenburg, B. (2001) ‘Kants Forderungen an eine wissenschaftliche Metaphysik der Natur’. In Fulda, H. F. and Stolzenberg, J. (eds), Architektonik und System in der Philosophie Kants (Hamburg: Felix Meiner), 307–27.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. (1992) ‘Causal Laws and the Foundations of Natural Science’. In Guyer, P. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 161–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gava, G. (2014) ‘Kant’s Definition of Science in the Architectonic of Pure Reason ’. Kant-Studien, 105, 372–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gava, G. (2018) ‘Kant, Wolff and the Method of Philosophy’. Oxford Studies in Modern Philosophy, 8, 271303.Google Scholar
Ginsborg, H. (1990) The Role of Taste in Kant’s Theory of Cognition. New York: Garland Publishing.Google Scholar
Guyer, P. (1990) ‘Reason and Reflective Judgment: Kant on the Significance of Systematicity’. Noûs, 24, 1743.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guyer, P. (2003) ‘Kant on the Systematicity of Nature: Two Puzzles’. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 20: 277–95.Google Scholar
Heis, J. (2014) ‘Kant (vs. Leibniz, Wolff and Lambert) on Real Definitions in Geometry’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 44, 605–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hinske, N. (1990) ‘Die Wissenschaften und ihre Zwecke: Kants Neuformulierung der Systemidee’. In Funke, G. (ed.), Akten des Siebenten Internationalen Kant-Kongresses (Bonn and Berlin: Bouvier), 157–77.Google Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2013) Systematicity: The Nature of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. (1900). Kants gesammelte Schriften. Berlin: De Gruyter, and predecessors Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1992) The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Ed. Guyer, P. and Wood, A. W.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1986) ‘Projecting the Order of Nature’. In Butts, R. E. (ed.), Kant’s Philosophy of Physical Science: Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft 1786–1986 (Dordrecht: Reidel), 201–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lambert, J. H. (1764) Neues Organon oder Gedanken über die Erforschung und Bezeichnung des Wahren und dessen Unterscheidung vom Irrthum und Schein, vol. 1. Leipzig: Wendler.Google Scholar
Lambert, J. H. (1771) Anlage zur Architectonic, oder Theorie des Einfachen und des Ersten in der Philosophischen und Mathematischen Erkenntniß, vol. 1. Riga: Hartknoch.Google Scholar
Laywine, A. (2010) ‘Kant and Lambert on Geometrical Postulates in the Reform of Metaphysics’. In Domski, M. and Dickson, M. (eds), Discourse on a New Method: Reinvigorating the Marriage of History and Philosophy of Science (Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open Court), 113–34.Google Scholar
Longuenesse, B. (1998) Kant and the Capacity to Judge: Sensibility and Discursivity in the Transcendental Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. Wolfe, C. T.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McNulty, M. B. (2015) ‘Rehabilitating the Regulative Use of Reason: Kant on Empirical and Chemical Laws’. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 54, 110.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Meier, G. F. (1752) Vernunftlehre. Halle: Gebauer.Google Scholar
Müller-Wille, S. (2007) ‘Collection and Collation: Theory and Practice of Linnaean Botany’. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 38, 541–62.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nunez, T. (2014) ‘Definitions of Kant’s Categories’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 44, 631–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oittinen, V. (2009) ‘Linné zwischen Wolff und Kant: Zu einigen Kantischen Motiven in Linnés biologischer Klassifikation’. In Onnasch, E.-O. (ed.), Kants Philosophie der Natur: Ihre Entwicklung im Opus postumum und ihre Wirkung (Berlin: de Gruyter), 5177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plaass, P. (1994) Kant’s Theory of Natural Science: Translation, Analytic Introduction and Commentary by Alfred E. and Maria G. Miller. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pozzo, R. (2005) ‘Prejudices and Horizons: G. F. Meier’s Vernunftlehre and its Relation to Kant’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 43, 185202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rauscher, F. (2010) ‘The Appendix to the Dialectic and the Canon of Pure Reason’. In Guyer, P. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 290309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandford, S. (2018) ‘Kant, Race, and Natural History’. Philosophy and Social Criticism, 44, 950–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shabel, L. (2003) Mathematics in Kant’s Critical Philosophy: Reflections on Mathematical Practice. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Sturm, T. (2009) Kant und die Wissenschaft vom Menschen. Paderborn: Mentis.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van den Berg, H. (2011) ‘Kant’s Conception of Proper Science’. Synthese, 183, 726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van den Berg, H. (2014) Kant on Proper Science: Biology in the Critical Philosophy and the Opus Postumum. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
van den Berg, H. (2020) ‘Theoretical Virtues in Eighteenth-Century Debates on Animal Cognition’. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 42(3), 37.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
van den Berg, H., and Demarest, B. (2020) ‘Axiomatic Natural Philosophy and the Emergence of Biology as a Science’. Journal of the History of Biology, 53, 379422.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Vanzo, A. (2010) ‘Kant on the Nominal Definition of Truth’. Kant-Studien, 101, 147–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waibel, V. (2007) ‘Die Systemkonzeption bei Lambert und Wolff’. In Stolzenberg, J. and Rudolph, O.-P. (eds), Christian Wolff und die europäische Aufklärung: Akten des 1. Internationalen Christian Wolff Kongresses, Halle (Saale), 4-8 April 2004, Teil 2. (Hildesheim: Olms), 5170.Google Scholar
Walsh, W. H. (1940) ‘Kant’s Conception of Scientific Knowledge’. Mind, 49, 445–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watkins, E. (2018) ‘Lambert and Kant on Cognition (Erkenntnis) and Science (Wissenschaft)’. In Dyck, C. and Wunderlich, F. (eds), Kant and his German Contemporaries (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 175–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wellmann, G. (2017) ‘Towards a New Conception of Metaphysics: Lambert’s Criticism on Wolff’s Mathematical Method’. Revista de Estudios Kantianos, 2, 135–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Willascheck, M., Stolzenberg, J., Mohr, G. and Bacin, S. (2015) Kant-Lexikon. Berlin: De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolff, C. (1716 [1965]) Mathematisches Lexicon. Hildesheim: Olms.Google Scholar
Wolff, C. (1750 [1999]) Die AnfangsGründe aller Mathematischen Wissenschaften. Erster Theil. Hildesheim: Olms.Google Scholar
Wolff, C. (1751 [2003]) Vernünfftige Gedancken von Gott, der Welt und der Seele des Menschen, auch allen Dingen überhaupt. Hildesheim: Olms.Google Scholar
Wolff, C. (1754 [1978]) Vernünfftige Gedancken von den Kräften des menschlichen Verstandes und ihrem richtigen Gebrauche in Erkäntniss der Wahrheit. Hildesheim: Olms.Google Scholar
Wolters, G. (1980) Basis und Deduktion: Studien zur Entstehung und Bedeutung der Theorie der Axiomatische Methode bei J. H. Lambert (1728–1777). Berlin: de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zinkstok, J. (2013) Kant’s Anatomy of Logic: Method and Logic in the Critical Philosophy. Ph.D. dissertation. Groningen: University of Groningen.Google Scholar